1°) μ- Ζ Ο cx ο = ω. ο » τς ω c Ww 2 2 > I 17 3 one ἌΝ, oe ee : GEORGE BOOLE’S COLLECTED LOGIGAL WORKS VOLUME Η ni los ogc ΤΣ Α͂ GEORGE BOOLE’S COLLECTED LOGICAL WORKS | VOLUME ii THE LAWS OF THOUGHT (1854) CHICAGO AND LONDON mHE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY 1916 Copyright in Great Britain under the Act of 1911 PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY NEILL AND CO., LTD., EDINBURGH. NOTE ΤῸ ἘΠΕ NEW EDERION BooLr’s Laws of Thought was originally published at London and Cambridge in 1854, and this new edition of that famous work, which is issued with the kind permission of Mrs. Boole and her family, is an exact reproduction of the original, including the title-page. The Errata have of course been corrected. The numbers giving the pages of the original have been inserted in the text in thicker type and enclosed in square brackets, so that references to pages of the original can at once be found in this edition. An Index has also been added. This new edition of the Laws of Thought forms the second volume of Boole’s Collected Logical Works, and a biography of Boole and account of his mathematical and logical work is given in the introduction to the first volume. In that introduction also is given some account of Boole’s logical thought subsequent to the publication of the Laws of Thought. The first volume also contains Boole’s three publications on logic prior to the appearance of the Laws of Thought, and all his papers on the theory of probabilities. PHILIP: EB. JOURDAIN. AN INVESTIGATION OF ΠΗ AWS OF EHO UG EL ON WHICH ARE FOUNDED THE MATHEMATICAL THEORIES OF LOGIC AND PROBABILITIES. BY GHEORGHE BOGE 1. PROFESSOR OF MATHEMATICS IN QUEEN’S COLLEGE, CORK. HON DON. WALTON AND MABERLEY, UPPER GOWER-STREET, AND IVY-LANE, PATERNOSTER.«ROW. CAMBRIDGE: MACMILLAN AND CO. 1854. TO JOHN RYALE Le p. VICE-PRESIDENT AND PROFESSOR OF GREEK IN QUEEN’S COLLEGE, CORK THIS WORK IS INSCRIBED IN TESTIMONY OF FRIENDSHIP AND ESTEEM Ea ᾿ iit] PREFACE THE following work is not a republication of a former treatise by the Author, entitled The Mathematical Analysis | of Logic. Its earlier portion is indeed devoted to the same object, and it begins by establishing the same system of fundamental laws, but its methods are more general, and its range of applications far wider. It exhibits the results, matured by some years of study and reflection, of a principle of investigation relating to the intellectual operations, the previous exposition of which was written within a few weeks after its idea had been conceived. That portion of this work which relates to Logic pre- supposes in its reader a knowledge of the most important terms of the science, as usually treated, and of its general object. On these points there is no better guide than Archbishop Whately’s Elements of Logic, or Mr. Thomson’s Outlines of the Laws of Thought. To the former of these treatises, the present revival of attention to this class of studies seems in a great measure due. Some acquaintance with the principles of Algebra is also requisite, but it is not necessary that this application should have been carried beyond the solution of simple equations. For the study of those chapters which relate to the theory of probabilities, a somewhat larger knowledge of Algebra is required, and espe-[iv]cially of the doctrine of Elimination, and of the solution of Equations containing more than one unknown quantity. Preliminary information upon the subject-matter will be found in the special treatises on Probabilities in Lardners Cabinet Cyclopedia, and the Library of Useful ΧΙ ΧΙ THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Knowledge, the former of these by Professor De Morgan, the latter by Sir John Lubbock ; and in an interesting series of Letters translated from the French of M. Quetelet. Other references will be given in the work. On a first perusal the reader may omit at his discretion, Chapters X., XIV., and X1X., together with any of the applications which he may deem uninviting or irrelevant. In different parts of the work, and especially in the notes to the concluding chapter, will be found references to various writers, ancient and modern, chiefly designed to illustrate a certain view of the history of philosophy. With respect to these, the Author thinks it proper to add, that he has in no instance given a citation which he has not believed upon careful examination to be supported either by parallel authorities, or by the general tenor of the work from which it was taken. While he would gladly have avoided the introduction of anything which might by possibility be con- strued into the parade of learning, he felt it to be due both to his subject and to the truth, that the statements in the text should be accompanied by the means of verification. And if now, in bringing to its close a labour, of the extent of which few persons will be able to judge from its apparent fruits, he may be permitted to speak for a single moment of the feelings with which he has pursued, and with which he now lays aside, his task, he would say, that he never doubted that it was worthy of his best efforts ; that he felt that what- ever of truth it might bring to light was not a private or arbitrary thing, not dependent, as to its essence, upon any human opinion. He was fully aware that learned and able men maintained opinions upon the subject of [v] Logic directly opposed to the views upon which the entire argu- ment and procedure of his work rested. While he believed those opinions to be erroneous, he was conscious that his own views might insensibly be warped by an influence of another kind. He felt in an especial manner the danger of that intellectual bias which long attention to a particular aspect of truth tends to produce. But he trusts that out of BAN eae αν So ES Le ERS SP ee OE ee Se Rese ἐς PREFACE xiii this conflict of opinions the same truth will but emerge the more free from any personal admixture ; that its different parts will be seen in their just proportion ; and that none of them will eventually be too highly valued or too lightly regarded because of the prejudices which may attach to the mere form of its exposition. To his valued friend, the Rev. George Stephens Dickson, of Lincoln, the Author desires to record his obligations for much kind assistance in the revision of this work, and for some important suggestions. 5, GRENVILLE-PLACE, CORK, Nov. 30th, 1853. Sore ee oo aa CONTENTS CHAPTER =] PAGE NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS Work, . : : ᾿ : Ι GHAP-ER ΙΙ SIGNS AND THEIR Laws, : : : : : : 1526 CHAPTER 111 DERIVATION OF THE Laws, . : : Ξ : : ἢ ὩΣ CHAPTER. Ly. DIVISION OF PROPOSITIONS, . : : ; : ᾿ gee CHAR EE Rey, PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING, : ‘ eee CHAPTER VI OF INTERPRETATION, . : ey CHAP LE Rw V.E Or ELIMINATION, . : : : : : : Ἴ πΘ 7 CHAPTER VIII Or REDUCTION, . : : ' ᾿ is CHAPTER. 1x METHODS OF ABBREVIATION, ; : ᾿ ἱ : 3.5 150 [viii] CHAPTER X ConpiITIONS OF A PERFECT METHOD, . : : τ 1 50 XV Xvi LAWS OF THOUGHT CHAPTER Xl Or SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS, CHAPTER ΧΗ METHODS IN SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS, CHAPTER XIll CLARKE AND SPINOZA, . CPAPTER XEV, EXAMPLE OF ANALYSIS, CHAPTER XV OF THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC, CHAPTER XVI Or THE THEORY OF PROBABILITIES, CHAPTER XVII GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES, . CHAP THR XV it ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS, CHAP PER XTX Or STATISTICAL CONDITIONS, CHAPTER Xx PROBLEMS ON CAUSES, . CHAPTER ΧΧῚ PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS, CHAPTER XXII CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT, PAGE 168 188 197 232 239 257 268 292 ΤΙ 337 393 418 [1] AN INVESTIGATION OF Pot PAW s OF THOUGHT CRATERS | NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 1. THE design of the following treatise is to investigate the fundamental laws of those operations of the mind by which reasoning is performed ; to give expression to them in the symbolical language of a Calculus, and upon this foundation to establish the science of Logic and construct its method ; to make that method itself the basis of a general method for the application of the mathematical doctrine of Probabilities; and, finally, to collect from the various elements of truth brought to view in the course of these inquiries some probable intimations concerning the nature and constitution of the human mind. 2. That this design is not altogether a novel one it is almost needless to remark, and it is well known that to its two main practical divisions of Logic and Probabilities a very considerable share of the attention of philosophers has been directed. In its ancient and scholastic form, indeed, the subject of Logic stands almost exclusively associated with the great name of Aristotle. As it was presented to ancient Greece in the partly technical, partly metaphysical disquisitions of the Organon, such, with scarcely any essential change, it has continued to the present day. The stream of origina: inquiry has rather been directed towards questions of general philosophy, which, though they [2] have arisen 1 I 2 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT among the disputes of the logicians, have outgrown their origin, and given to successive ages of speculation their peculiar bent and character. The eras of Porphyry and Proclus, of Anselm and Abelard, of Ramus, and of Descartes, together with the final protests of Bacon and Locke, rise up before the mind as examples of the remoter influences of the study upon the course of human thought, partly in suggest- ing topics fertile of discussion, partly in provoking remon- strance against its own undue pretensions. The history of the theory of Probabilities, on the other hand, has presented far more of that character of steady growth which belongs to science. In its origin the early genius of Pascal,—in its maturer stages of development the most recondite of all the mathematical speculations of Laplace,—were directed to its improvement ; to omit here the mention of other names scarcely less distinguished than these. As the study of Logic has been remarkable for the kindred questions of Metaphysics to which it has given occasion, so that of Probabilities also has been remarkable for the impulse which it has bestowed upon the higher departments of mathematical science. Each of these subjects has, moreover, been justly regarded as having relation to a speculative as well as toa practical end. To enable us to deduce correct inferences from given premises is not the only object of Logic; nor is it the sole claim of the theory of Probabilities that it teaches us how to establish the business or life assurance on a secure basis ; and how to condense whatever is valuable in the re- cords of innumerable observations in astronomy, in physics, or in that field of social inquiry which is fast assuming a character of great importance. Both these studies have also an interest of another kind, derived from the light which they shed upon the intellectual powers. They instruct us concerning the mode in which language and number serve as instrumental aids to the processes of reasoning ; they reveal to us in some degree the connexion between different powers of our common intellect ; they set before us what, in the two domains of demonstrative and of probable know- NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK — 3 ledge, are the essential standards of truth and correctness, —standards not derived from without, but deeply founded in the constitution of the human faculties. These ends of speculation yield neither in interest nor in dignity, nor yet, it [3] may be added, in importance, to the practical objects, with the pursuit of which they have been historically associ- ated. To unfold the secret laws and relations of those high faculties of thought by which all beyond the merely per- ceptive knowledge of the world and of ourselves is attained or matured, is an object which does not stand in need of commendation to a rational mind. 3. But although certain parts of the design of this work have been entertained by others, its general conception, its method, and, to a considerable extent, its results, are believed to be original. For this reason 1 shall offer, in the present chapter, some preparatory statements and explana- tions, in order that the real aim of this treatise may be understood, and the treatment of its subject facilitated. It is designed, in the first place, to investigate the funda- mental laws of those operations of the mind by which reason- ing is performed. It is unnecessary to enter here into any argument to prove that the operations of the mind are in a certain real sense subject to laws, and that a science of the mind is therefore possible. If these are questions which admit of doubt, that doubt is not to be met by an en- deavour to settle the point of dispute @ przorz, but by direct- ing the attention of the objector to the evidence of actual laws, by referring him to an actual science. And thus the solution of that doubt would belong not to the introduction to this treatise, but to the treatise itself. Let the assump- tion be granted, that a science of the intellectual powers is possible, and let us ‘us for a moment consider how the know- ledge of it is to be obtained. 4. Like all other sciences, that of the intellectual opera- tions must primarily rest upon observations, —the subject of such observation being the very operations and processes of which we desire to determine the laws. But while the 4 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT necessity of a foundation in experience is thus a condition common to all sciences, there are some special differences between the modes in which this principle becomes available for the determination of general truths when the subject of inquiry is the mind, and when the subject is external nature. To these it is necessary to direct attention. [4] The general laws of Nature are not, for the most part, immediate objects of perception. They are either inductive “inferences from a large body of facts, the common truth in ‘which they express, or, in their origin at least, physical hypotheses of a causal nature serving to explain phanomena with undeviating precision, and to enable us to predict new Combinations of them, ©. Phey, are in all cases, and. in the strictest sense of the term, probable conclusions, approach- ing, indeed, ever and ever nearer to certainty, as they receive more and more of the confirmation of experience. But of the character of probability, in the strict and proper sense of that term, they are never wholly divested. On the other hand, the knowledge of the laws of the mind does not require as its basis any extensive collection of observations. The general truth is seen in the particular instance, and it is not confirmed by the repetition of instances. We may illustrate this position by an obvious example. It may be a question whether that formula of reasoning, which is called the dictum of Aristotle, de omni et nullo, expresses a primary law of human reasoning or not; but it is no~ question that it expresses a general truth in Logic. Now | that truth is made manifest in all its generality by reflection upon a single instance of its application. And this is both an evidence that the particular principle or formula in question is founded upon some general law or laws of the mind, and an illustration of the doctrine that the perception of such general truths is not derived from an induction from many instances, but is involved in the clear appre- hension of a single instance. In connexion with this truth is seen the not less important one that our knowledge of the laws upon which the science of the intellectual powers NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS. WORK 34 rests, whatever may be its extent or its deficiency, is not probable knowledge. For we not only see in the particular example the general truth, but we see it also as a certain truth,——a truth, our confidence in which will not continue to increase with increasing experience of its practical verifications. 5. But if the general truths of Logic are of sucha nature. that when presented to the mind.they at once command _ assent, wherein consists the difficulty of constructing. the. Science of Logic? Not, it may be answered, in collecting the materials of knowledge, but in discriminating _ their nature, and determining [5] their mutual place and relation. Alfsciences consist of general truths, but of those truths some only are primary and fundamental, others are secondary and derived. The laws of elliptic motion, discovered by Kepler, are general truths in astronomy, but they are not its fundamental truths. And it is so also in the purely mathematical sciences. An almost boundless diversity of theorems, which are known, and an infinite possibility of others, as yet unknown, rest together upon the foundation of a few simple axioms ; and yet these are all genxerad truths. It may be added, that they are truths which to an intelli- gence sufficiently refined would shine forth in their own unborrowed light, without the need of those connecting links of thought, those steps of wearisome and often painful deduction, by which the knowledge of them is actually acquired. Let us define as fundamental those laws. and principles from which all other general truths of science may be deduced, and into which they may all be again resolved. Shall we then err in regarding that as the true science of Logic which, laying down certain elementary laws, con- firmed by the very testimony of the mind, permits us thence to deduce, by uniform processes, the entire chain of its secondary consequences, and furnishes, for its practical applications, methods of perfect generality? Let it be considered whether in any science, viewed either asa system of truth or as the foundation of a practical art, there can 6 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT properly be any other test of the completeness and the fundamental characters of its laws, than the completeness of its system of derived truths, and the generality of the methods which it serves to establish. Other questions may indeed present themselves. Convenience, prescription, in- dividual preference, may urge their claims and deserve attention. But as respects the question of what constitutes science in its abstract integrity, I apprehend that no other considerations than the above are properly of any value. 6. It is designed, in the next place, to give expression in this treatise to the fundamental laws of reasoning in the symbolical language of a Calculus. Upon this head it will suffice to say, that those laws are such as to suggest this mode of expression, and to give to it a peculiar and ex- clusive fitness for the ends in view. [6] There is not only a close analogy between the operations of the mind in general reasoning and its operations in the particular science of Algebra, but there is to a considerable extent an exact agreement in the laws by which the two classes of operations are conducted. Of course the laws must in both cases be determined independently ; any formal agreement between them can only be established a@ posteriort by actual compari- son. To borrow the notation of the science of Number, and then assume that in its new application the laws by which its use is governed will remain unchanged, would be mere hypothesis. There exist, indeed, certain general principles founded in the very nature of language, by which the use of symbols, which are but the elements of scientific language, is determined. To a certain extent these elements are arbitrary. Their interpretation is purely conventional: we are permitted to employ them in what- ever sense we please, But this permission is limited by two indispensable conditions,—first, that from the sense once conventionally established we never, in the same process of reasoning, depart ; secondly, that the laws by which the process is conducted be founded exclusively _upon the above fixed sense or meaning of the symbols NATURE AND DESIGN. OF (THIS WORK. °% employed. In accordance with these principles, any agree- ment which may be established between the laws of the symbols of Logic and those of Algebra can but issue in an agreement of processes. The two provinces of interpreta- tion remain apart and independent, each subject to its own laws and conditions. Now the actual investigations of the following pages exhibit Logic, in its practical aspect, as a system of pro- cesses carried on by the aid of symbols having a definite interpretation, and subject to laws founded upon that inter- “pretation alone. But at the same time they exhibit those faws as identical in form with the laws of the general symbols of Algebra, with this single addition, viz., that the symbols of Logic are further subject to a special law (Chap. II.), to which the symbols of quantity, as such, are not subject. Upon the nature and the evidence of this law it is not purposed here to dwell. These questions will be fully discussed in a future page. But as constituting the essential ground of difference between those forms of infer- ence with which Logic is [7] conversant, and those which present themselves in the particular science of Number, the law i in question is deserving of more than a passing notice. . it may be said that it lies at the very foundation of general reasoning, —that it governs those intellectual acts of concep- tion or of imagination which are preliminary to the processes of logical deduction, and that it gives to the processes them- selves much of their actual form and expression. It may hence be affirmed that this law constitutes the germ or seminal principle, of which every approximation to a general method in Logic is the more or less perfect development. 7. The principle has already been laid down (5) that the sufficiency and truly fundamental character of any assumed system of laws in the science of Logic must partly be seen in the perfection of the methods to which they conduct us. It remains, then, to consider what the requirements of a general method in Logic are, and how far they are fulfilled in the system of the present work. 8 THE LAWS OF THOCGHT Logic is conversant with two kinds of relations, —relations among things, and relations among facts. But as facts are -expressed by propositions, the latter species of relation may, at least for the purposes of Logic, be resolved into a relation among propositions. The assertion that the fact or event 4 is an invariable consequent of the fact or event B may, to this extent at least, be regarded as equivalent to the assertion, that the truth of the proposition affirming the occurrence of the event & always implies the truth of the proposition affirming the occurrence of the event A. Instead, then, of saying that Logic is conversant with relations among things and relations among facts, we are permitted , to say that it is concerned with relations among things and ᾿ relations among propositions. Of the former kind of rela- tions we have an example in the proposition—‘‘ All men are mortal” ; of the latter kind in the proposition—‘‘ If the sun is totally eclipsed, the stars will become visible.” The one expresses a relation between ‘‘men” and ‘‘ mortal beings,” the other between the elementary propositions— ‘‘The sun is totally eclipsed”; ‘*The stars will become visible.” Among such relations I suppose to be included those which affirm or deny existence with respect to things, and those which affirm or deny truth with re-[8]spect to propositions. Now let those things or those propositions among which relation is expressed be termed the elements of the propositions by which such relation is expressed. Proceeding from this definition, we may then say that the “ premises of any logical argument express given relations among certain elements, and that the conclusion must ex- press an zmplied relation among those elements, or among a part of them, ze. a relation implied by or inferentially involved in the premises, 8. Now this being premised, the requirements of a general method in Logic seem to be the following :— Ist. As the conclusion must express a relation among the whole or among a part of the elements involved in the premises, it is requisite that we should possess the means of NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK <9 eliminating those elements which we desire not to appear in the conclusion, and of determining the whole amount of relation implied by the premises among the elements which we wish to retain. Those elements which do not present themselves in the conclusion are, in the language of the common Logic, called middle terms; and the species of limination exemplified in treatises on Logic consists in deducing from two propositions, containing a common element or middle term, a conclusion connecting the two remaining terms. But the problem of elimination, as con- templated in this work, possesses a much wider scope. It proposes not merely the elimination of one middle term from two propositions, but the elimination generally of middle terms from propositions, without regard to the number of either of them, or to the nature of their connexion. To this object neither the processes of Logic nor those of Algebra, in their actual state, present any strict parallel. In the latter science the problem of elimination is known to be limited in the following manner :—From two equations we can eliminate one symbol of quantity; from three equations two symbols; and, generally, from 2 equations m—1 symbols. But though this condition, necessary in Algebra, seems to prevail in the existing Logic also, it has no essential place in Logic as a science. There, no relation whatever can be proved to prevail between the number of terms to be eliminated and the number of propositions from which the elimination is to be effected. From the equation representing a single proposition, any num-[9]ber of symbols representing terms or elements in Logic may be eliminated ; and from any number of equations represent- ing propositions, one or any other number of symbols of this kind may be eliminated in a similar manner. For such elimination there exists one general process applicable to all cases. This is one of the many remarkable consequences of that distinguishing law of the symbols of Logic, to which attention has been already directed. 2ndly. It should be within the province of a general 10 THE LAWS OF FHOUGAT method in Logic to express the final relation among the elements of the conclusion by any admissible £zxd of pro- position, or in any selected order of terms. Among varieties of kind we may reckon those which logicians have designated by the terms categorical, hypothetical, disjunctive, &c. To a choice or selection in the order of the terms, we may refer whatsoever is dependent upon the appearance of particular elements in the subject or in the predicate, in the antecedent or in the consequent, of that proposition which forms the ‘‘conclusion.” But waiving the language of the schools, let us consider what really distinct species of problems may present themselves to our notice. We have seen that the elements of the final or inferred relation may either be ¢hzngs or propositions. Suppose the former case ; then it might be required to deduce from the premises a definition or descrip- tion of some one thing, or class of things, constituting an element of the conclusion in terms of the other things in- volved in it. Or we might form the conception of some thing or class of things, involving more than one of the elements of the conclusion, and require its expression in terms of the other elements. Again, suppose the elements retained in the conclusion to be propositions, we might desire to ascertain such points as the following, Viz. , Whether, in virtue of the premises, any of those propositions, taken singly, are true or false?—Whether particular com- binations of them are true or false ?—Whether, assuming a particular proposition to be true, any consequences will follow, and if so, what consequences, with respect to the other propositions?—Whether any particular condition being assumed with reference to certain of the propositions, any consequences, and what consequences, will follow with respect to the others? and [10] so on. I say that these are general questions, which it should fall within the scope or province of a general method in Logic to solve. Perhaps we might include them all under this one statement of the final problem of practical Logic. Given a set of premises expressing relations among certain elements, whether things NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS (WORK . 1% or propositions : required explicitly the whole relation con- sequent among any of those elements under any proposed conditions, and in any proposed form. That this problem, under all its aspects, is resolvable, will hereafter appear. But it is not for the sake of noticing this fact, that the above inquiry into the nature and the functions of a general method in Logic has been introduced. It is necessary that the reader should apprehend what are the specific ends of the investigation upon which we are entering, as well as the principles which are to guide us to the attainment of them. Ὁ Possibly it may here be said that the Logic. of Aristotle, in its rules of syllogism and conversion, sets forth the elementary processes of which all reasoning con- sists, and that beyond these there is neither scope nor occasion for a general method. I have no desire to point out the defects of the common Logic, nor do I wish to refer to it any further than is necessary, in order to place in its true light the nature of the present treatise. With this end alone in view, I would remark :—tIst. That syllogism, con- version, &c., are not the ultimate processes of Logic. It will be shown in this treatise that they are founded upon, and are resolvable into, ulterior and more simple processes which constitute the real elements of method in Logic. Nor is it true in fact that all inference is reducible to the par- ticular forms of syllogism and conversion.—Vzde Chap. XV. 2ndly. If all inference were reducible to these two processes (and it has been maintained that it is reducible to syllogism alone), there would still exist the same necessity for a general method. For it would still be requisite to determine in what order the processes should succeed each other, as well as their particular nature, in order that the desired relation should be obtained. By the desired relation | mean that full relation which, in virtue of the premises, con- nects any elements selected out of the premises at will, and which, moreover, expresses that relation in any desired form and order. [11] If we may judge from the mathe- matical sciences, which are the most perfect examples of 12 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT method known, this drective function of Method constitutes its chief office and distinction. The fundamental processes of arithmetic, for instance, are in themselves but the elements of a possible science. To assign their nature is the first business of its method, but to arrange their succession is its subsequent and higher function. In the more complex examples of logical deduction, and especially in those which form a basis for the solution of difficult questions in the theory of Probabilities, the aid of a directive method, such as a Calculus alone can supply, is indispensable. 10. Whence it is that the ultimate laws of Logic are mathematical in their form; why they are, except in a single point, identical with the general laws of Number ; and why in that particular point they differ ;—are questions upon which it might not be very remote from presumption to endeavour to pronounce a positive judgment. Probably they lie beyond the reach of our limited faculties. It may, perhaps, be permitted to the mind to attain a knowledge of the laws to which it is itself subject, without its being also given to it to understand their ground and origin, or even, except in a very limited degree, to comprehend their fitness for their end, as compared with other and conceivable systems of law. Such knowledge is, indeed, unnecessary for the ends of science, which properly concerns itself with what is, and seeks not for grounds of preference or reasons of appoint- ment, These considerations furnish a sufficient answer to all protests against the exhibition of Logic in the form of a Calculus. It is not because we choose to assign to it such a mode of manifestation, but because the ultimate laws of thought render that mode possible, and prescribe its character, and forbid, as it would seem, the perfect manifestation of the science in any other form, that such a mode demands adoption. It is to be remembered that it is the business of science not to create laws, but to discover them. We’do not originate the constitution of our own minds, greatly as it may be in our power to modify their character. And as the laws of the human intellect do not depend upon our will, so NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 13 the forms of the science, of which they constitute the basis, are in all essential regards independent of individual choice. [12] 11. Beside the general statement of the principles of the above method, this treatise will exhibit its applica- tion to the analysis of a considerable variety of proposi- tions, and of trains of propositions constituting the premises of demonstrative arguments. These examples have been selected from various writers, they differ greatly in com- plexity, and they embrace a wide range of subjects. Though in this particular respect it may appear to some that too great a latitude of choice has been exercised, I do not deem it necessary to offer any apology upon this account. That Logic, as a science, is susceptible of very wide applications is admitted ; but it is equally certain that its ultimate forms and processes are mathematical. Any objection a priori which may therefore be supposed to lie against the adoption of such forms and processes in the discussion of a problem of morals or of general philosophy must be founded upon misapprehension or false analogy. It is not of the essence of mathematics to be conversant with the ideas of number and quantity. Whether as a general habit of mind it would be desirable to apply symbolical processes to moral argu- ment, is another question. Possibly, as I have elsewhere observed,* the perfection of the method of Logic may be chiefly valuable as an evidence of the speculative truth of its principles. To supersede the employment of common reasoning, or to subject it to the rigour of technical forms, would be the last desire of one who knows the value of that intellectual toil and warfare which imparts to the mind an athletic vigour, and teaches it to contend with difficulties, and to rely upon itself in emergencies. Nevertheless, cases may arise in which the value of a scientific procedure, even in those things which fall confessedly under the ordinary dominion of the reason, may be felt and acknowledged. Some examples of this kind will be found in the present work. * Mathematical Analysis of Logic. London: G, Bell. 1847. 14 THE PAWS OF THOUGHT 12. The general doctrine and method of Logic above explained form also the basis of a theory and corresponding method of Probabilities. Accordingly, the development of such a theory and method, upon the above principles, will constitute a distinct object of the present treatise. Of the nature of this application it may be desirable to give here some account, more especially as [13] regards the character of the solutions to which it leads. In connexion with this object some further detail will be requisite concerning the forms in which the results of the logical analysis are presented. The ground of this necessity of a prior method in Logic, as the basis of a theory of Probabilities, may be stated in a few words. Before we can determine the mode in which the expected frequency of occurrence of a particular event is dependent upon the known frequency of occurrence of any other events, we must be acquainted with the mutual dependence of the events themselves. Speaking technically, we must be able to express the event whose probability is sought, as a function of the events whose probabilities are given. Now this explicit determination belongs in all in- stances to the department of Logic. Probability, however, in its mathematical acceptation, admits of numerical measure- ment. Hence the subject of Probabilities belongs equally to the science of Number and to that of Logic. In recognis- ing the co-ordinate existence of both these elements, the present treatise differs from all previous ones; and as this difference not only affects the question of the possibility of the solution of problems in a large number of instances, but also introduces new and important elements into the solutions obtained, I deem it necessary to state here, at some length, the peculiar consequences of the theory developed in the following pages. 13. The measure of the probability of an event is usually defined as a fraction, of which the numerator represents the number of cases favourable to the event, and the denominator the whole number of cases favourable and unfavourable ; all NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK: ἃς cases being supposed equally likely to happen. That defini- tion is adopted in the present work. At the same time it is shown that there is another aspect of the subject (shortly to be referred to) which might equally be regarded as funda- mental, and which would actually lead to the same system of methods and conclusions, It may be added, that so far as the received conclusions of the theory of Probabilities extend, and so far as they are consequences of its funda- mental definitions, they do not differ from the results (supposed to be equally correct in inference) of the method of this work. [14] Again, although questions in the theory of Pro- babilities present themselves under various aspects, and may be variously modified by algebraical and other con- ditions, there seems to be one general type to which all such questions, or so much of each of them as truly belongs to the theory of Probabilities, may be referred. Considered with reference to the data and the gu@sztum, that type may be described as follows :—1st. The data are the probabilities of one or more given events, each probability being either that of the absolute fulfilment of the event to which it re- lates, or the probability of its fulfilment under given sup- posed conditions. 2ndly. The gu@siztum, or object sought, is the probability of the fulfilment, absolutely or condition- ally, of some other event differing in expression from those in the data, but more or less involving the same elements. As concerns the data, they are either causally given,—as when the probability of a particular throw of a die is deduced from a knowledge of the constitution of the piece, —or they are derived from observation of repeated in- stances of the success or failure of events. In the latter case the probability of an event may be defined as the limit toward which the ratio of the favourable to the whole number of observed cases approaches (the uniformity of nature being presupposed) as the observations are indefinitely continued. Lastly, as concerns the nature or relation of the events in question, an important distinction remains. Those events 16 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT are either simple or compound. By a compound event is meant one of which the expression in language, or the con- ception in thought, depends upon the expression or the con- ception of other events, which, in relation to it, may be regarded as simple events. To say ‘‘it. rains,” or to say ‘it thunders,” is to express the occurrence of a simple event; but to say ‘‘it rains and thunders,” or to say ‘‘it either rains or thunders,” is to express that of a compound event. For the expression of that event depends upon the elementary expressions, ‘‘it rains,” ‘‘it thunders.” The criterion of simple events is not, therefore, any supposed sim- plicity in their nature. It is founded solely on the mode of their expression in language or conception in thought. 14. Now one general problem, which the existing theory of Probabilities enables us to solve, is the following, viz. :— Given [15] the probabilities of any simple events : required the probability of a given compound event, z.e. of an event compounded in a given manner out of the given simple events. The problem can also be solved when the compound event, whose probability is required, is subjected to given conditions, z.e. to conditions dependent also in a given manner on the given simple events. Beside this general problem, there exist also particular problems of which the principle of solution is known. Various questions relating to causes and effects can be solved by known methods under the particular hypothesis that the causes are mutually ex- clusive, but apparently not otherwise. Beyond this it is not clear that any advance has been made toward the solution of what may be regarded as the general problem of the science, viz. : Given the probabilities of any events, simple or compound, conditioned or unconditioned : required the probability of any other event equally arbitrary in ex- pression and conception. In the statement of this question it is not even postulated that the events whose probabilities are given, and the one whose probability is sought, should involve some common elements, because it is the office of a method to determine whether the data of a problem are NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 17 sufficient for the end in view, and to indicate, when they are not so, wherein the deficiency consists. This problem, in the most unrestricted form of its state- ment, is resolvable by the method of the present treatise ; or, to speak more precisely, its theoretical solution is com- pletely given, and its practical solution is brought to depend only upon processes purely mathematical, such as the re- solution and analysis of equations. The order and character of the general solution may thus be described. 15. In the first place it is always possible, by the pre- liminary method of the Calculus of Logic, to express the event whose probability is sought as a logical function of the events whose probabilities are given. The result is of the following character : Suppose that Y represents the event whose probability is sought, A, δ, C, &c. the events whose probabilities are given, those events being either simple or compound. Then the whole relation of the event X to the events, A, B, C, &c. is deduced in the form of what mathe- maticians term a development, consisting, in [16] the most ’ general case, of four distinct classes of terms. By the first ~class are expressed those combinations of the events A, B, C, which both necessarily accompany and necessarily indicate the occurrence of the event X ; by the second class, those combinations which necessarily accompany, but do not necessarily imply, the occurrence of the event 1; by the third class, those combinations whose occurrence in con- nexion with the event X is impossible, but not otherwise impossible ; by the fourth class, those combinations whose occurrence is impossible under any circumstances. I shall not dwell upon this statement of the result of the logical analysis of the problem, further than to remark that the elements which it presents are precisely those by which the expectation of the event Y, as dependent upon our know- ledge of the events A, B, C, is, or alone can be, affected. General reasoning would verify this conclusion ; but general reasoning would not usually avail to disentangle the com- plicated web of events and circumstances from which the 2 18 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT solution above described must be evolved. The attainment of this object constitutes the first step towards the complete solution of the question proposed. It is to be noted that thus far the process of solution is logical, z.e. conducted by symbols of logical significance, and resulting in an equation interpretable into a proposttion. Let this result be termed the final logical equation. The second step of the process deserves attentive remark. From the final logical equation to which the previous step has conducted us, are deduced, by inspection, a series of algebraic equations implicitly involving the complete solu- tion of the problem proposed. Of the mode in which this transition is effected let it suffice to say, that there exists a definite relation between the laws by which the pro- babilities of events are expressed as algebraic functions of the probabilities of other events upon which they depend, and the laws by which the logical connexion of the events is itself expressed. This relation, like the other coincidences of formal law which have been referred to, is not founded upon hypothesis, but is made known to us by observation (1. 4), and reflection. If, however, its reality were assumed a priort as the basis of the very definition of Probability, strict deduction would thence lead us to the received numerical definition as a [17] necessary consequence. The Theory of Probabilities stands, as it has already been remarked (I. 12), in equally close relation to Logic and to Arithmetic ; and it is indifferent, so far as results are con- cerned, whether we regard it as springing out of the latter of these sciences, or as founded in the mutual relations which connect the two together. ) 16, There are some circumstances, interesting perhaps to the mathematician, attending the general solutions deduced by the above method, which it may be desirable to notice. ist. As the method is independent of the number and the nature of the data, it continues to be applicable when the latter are insufficient to render determinate the value sought. When such is the case, the final expression of the solution NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 19 ’ will contain terms with arbitrary constant coefficients. To such terms there will correspond terms in the final logical equation (I. 15), the interpretation of which will inform us what new data are requisite in order to determine the values of those constants, and thus render the numerical solution complete. If such data are not to be obtained, we can still, by giving to the constants their limiting values Ὁ and 1, determine the limits within which the probability sought must lie independently of all further experience. When the event whose probability is sought is guzte independent of those whose probabilities are given, the limits thus obtained for its value will be o and 1, as it is evident that they ought to be, and the interpretation of the constants will only lead to a re-statement of the original problem. : 2ndly. The expression of the final solution will in all cases involve a particular element of quantity, determinable by the solution of an algebraic equation. Now when that equation is of an elevated degree, a difficulty may seem to arise as to the selection of the proper root. There are, indeed, cases in which both the elements given and the element sought are so obviously restricted by necessary conditions that no choice remains. But in complex in- stances the discovery of such conditions, by unassisted force of reasoning, would be hopeless. A distinct method is requisite for this end,—a method which might not inappro- priately be termed the Calculus of Statistical Conditions. Into the nature of this method [ shall not here further enter [18] than to say, that, like the previous method, it is based upon the employment of the ‘‘ final logical equation,” and that it definitely assigns, Ist, the conditions which must be fulfilled among the numerical elements of the data, in order that the problem may be real, z.e. derived from a fosszble expertence; 2ndly, the numerical limits, within which the probability sought must have been confined, if, instead of being determined by theory, it had been deduced directly by observation from the same system of phenomena from which the data were derived. It is clear that these limits 20 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT will be actual limits of the probability sought. Now, on supposing the data subject to the conditions above assigned to them, it appears in every instance which I have examined that there exists one root, and only one root, of the final algebraic equation which is subject to the required limita- tions. Every source of ambiguity is thus removed. It would even seem that new truths relating to the theory of algebraic equations are thus incidentally brought to light. It is remarkable that the special element of quantity, to which the previous discussion relates, depends only upon the daa, and not at all upon the guesztum of the problem proposed. Hence the solution of each particular problem unties the knot of difficulty for a system of problems, viz., for that system of problems which is marked by the possession of common data, independently of the nature of their gu@szta. This circumstance is important whenever from a particular system of data it is required to deduce a series of connected conclusions. And it further gives to the solutions of particular problems that character of relationship, derived from their dependence upon a central and fundamental unity, which not unfrequently marks the application of general methods. 17. But though the above considerations, with others of a like nature, justify the assertion that the method of this treatise, for the solution of questions in the theory of Probabilities, is a general method, it does not thence follow that we are relieved in all cases from the necessity of re- course to hypothetical grounds. It has been observed that a solution may consist entirely of terms affected by arbitrary constant coefficients,—may, in fact, be wholly indefinite. The application of the method of this work to some of the most important questions within its range would—[19] were the data of experience alone employed—present results of this character. ‘To obtain a definite solution it is necessary, in such cases, to have recourse to hypotheses possessing more or less of independent probability, but incapable of exact verification. Generally speaking, such hypotheses will differ NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 21 from the immediate results of experience in partaking of a logical rather than of a numerical character ; in prescribing the conditions under which phenomena occur, rather than assigning the relative frequency of their occurrence. This circumstance is, however, unimportant. Whatever their nature may be, the hypotheses assumed must thenceforth be regarded as belonging to the actual data, although tend- ing, as is obvious, to give to the solution itself somewhat of a hypothetical character. With this understanding as to the possible sources of the data actually employed, the method is perfectly general, but for the correctness of the hypothetical elements introduced it is of course no more responsible than for the correctness of the numerical data derived from experience. In illustration of these remarks we may observe that the theory of the reduction of astronomical observations * rests, in part, upon hypothetical grounds. It assumes certain positions as to the nature of error, the equal probabilities of its occurrence in the form of excess or defect, &c., without which it would be impossible to obtain any definite con- clusions from a system of conflicting observations. But granting such positions as the above, the residue of the investigation falls strictly within the province of the theory of Probabilities. Similar observations apply to the important problem which proposes to deduce from the records of the “majorities of a deliberative assembly the mean probability of correct judgment in one of its members. If the method of this treatise be applied to the mere numerical data, the solution obtained is of that wholly indefinite kind above described. And to show in a more eminent degree the insufficiency of those data by themselves, the interpretation of the arbitrary constants (I. 16) which appear in the solution, merely produces [20] a re-statement of the original problem. Admitting, however, the hypothesis of the independent formation of opinion in the individual mind, either absolutely, * The author designs to treat this subject either in a separate work or ina future Appendix. In the present treatise he avoids the use of the integral calculus, 22 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT as in the speculations of Laplace and Poisson, or under limitations imposed by the actual data, as will be seen in this treatise, Chap. XXI., the problem assumes a far more definite character. It will be manifest that the ulterior value of the theory of Probabilities must depend very much upon the correct formation of such mediate hypotheses, where the purely experimental data are insufficient for definite solution, and where that further experience indicated by the interpretation of the final logical equation is unattain- able. Upon the other hand, an undue readiness to form hypotheses in subjects which from their very nature are placed beyond human ken, must re-act upon the credit of the theory of Probabilities, and tend to throw doubt in the general mind over its most legitimate conclusions. 18. It would, perhaps, be premature to speculate here upon the question whether the methods of abstract science are likely at any future day to render service in the investi- gation of social problems at all commensurate with those which they have rendered in various departments of physical inquiry. An attempt to resolve this question upon pure a priori grounds of reasoning would be very likely to mis- lead us. For example, the consideration of human free- agency would seem at first sight to preclude the idea that the movements of the social system should ever manifest that character of orderly evolution which we are prepared to expect under the reign of a physical necessity. Yet already do the researches of the statist reveal to us facts at variance with such an anticipation. Thus the records of crime and pauperism present a degree of regularity unknown in regions in which the disturbing influence of human wants and passions is unfelt. On the other hand, the distemperature of seasons, the eruption of volcanoes, the spread of blight in the vegetable, or of epidemic maladies in the animal kingdom, things apparently or chiefly the product of natural causes, refuse to be submitted to regular and apprehensible laws. ‘‘ Fickle as the wind,” is a proverbial expression. Reflection upon these points teaches us in some degree to NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK δὴ correct our earlier judgments. We learn that we are not to [21] expect, under the dominion of necessity, an order per- ceptible to human observation, unless the play of its produc- ing causes is sufficiently simple ; nor, on the other hand, to deem that free agency in the individual is inconsistent with regularity in the motions of the system of which he forms a component unit. Human freedom stands out as an apparent fact of our consciousness, while it is also, 1 conceive, a highly probable deduction of analogy (Chap. XXII.) from the nature of that portion of the mind whose scientific constitution we are able to investigate. But whether accepted as a fact reposing on consciousness, or as a conclusion sanctioned by the reason, it must be so interpreted as not to conflict with an established result of observation, viz. : that phanomena, in the production of which large masses of men are concerned, do actually exhibit a very remarkable degree of regularity, enabling us to collect in each succeeding age the elements upon which the estimate of its state and progress, so far as manifested in outward results, must depend. There is thus no sound objection ὦ priorvt against the possibility of that species of data which is requisite for the experimental foundation of a science of social statistics. Again, what- ever other object this treatise may accomplish, it is presumed that it will leave no doubt as to the existence of a system of abstract principles and of methods founded upon those principles, by which any collective body of social data may be made to yield, in an explicit form, whatever information they implicitly involve. There may, where the data are exceedingly complex, be very great difficulty in obtaining this information,—difficulty due not to any imperfection of the theory, but to the laborious character of the analytical _ processes to which it points. It is quite conceivable that in many instances that difficulty may be such as only united effort could overcome. But that we possess theoretically in all cases, and practically, so far as the requisite labour of calculation may be supplied, the means of evolving from statistical records the seeds of general truths which lie buried 24 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT amid the mass of figures, is a position which may, 1 con- ceive, with perfect safety be affirmed. 19. But beyond these general positions I do not venture to speak in terms of assurance. Whether the results which might be expected from the application of scientific methods to statis-[22]tical records, over and above those the dis- covery of which requires no such aid, would so far com- pensate for the labour involved as to render it worth while to institute such investigations upon a proper scale of magni- tude, is a point which could, perhaps, only be determined by experience. It is to be desired, and it might without great presumption be expected, that in this, as in other instances, the abstract doctrines of science should minister to more than intellectual gratification. Nor, viewing the apparent order in which the sciences have been evolved, and have successively contributed their aid to the service of man- kind, does it seem very improbable that a day may arrive in which similar aid may accrue from departments of the field of knowledge yet more intimately allied with the elements of human welfare. Let the speculations of this treatise, however, rest at present simply upon their claim to be regarded as true. 20. I design, in the last place, to endeavour to educe from the scientific results of the previous inquiries some general intimations respecting the nature and constitution of the human mind. Into the grounds of the possibility of this species of inference it is not necessary to enter here. One or two general observations may serve to indicate the track which I shall endeavour to follow. It cannot but be admitted that our views of the science of Logic must materially in- fluence, perhaps mainly determine, our opinions upon the nature of the intellectual faculties. For example, the ques- tion whether reasoning consists merely in the application of certain first or necessary truths, with which the mind has been originally imprinted, or whether the mind is itself a seat of law, whose operation is as manifest and as con- clusive in the particular as in the general formula, or whether, NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK 25 as some not undistinguished writers seem to maintain, all reasoning is of particulars ; this question, I say, is one which not merely affects the science of Logic, but also concerns the formation of just views of the constitution of the intellectual faculties. Again, if it is concluded that the mind is by original constitution a seat of law, the question of the nature of its subjection to this law,—whether, for instance, it is an obedience founded upon necessity, like that which sustains the revolutions of the heavens, and preserves the order of Nature,—or whether [23] it is a subjection of some quite distinct kind, is also a matter of deep speculative interest. Further, if the mind is truly determined to be a subject of law, and if its laws also are truly assigned, the question of their probable or necessary influence upon the course of human thought in different ages is one invested with great importance, and well deserving a patient investigation, as matter both of philosophy and of history. These and other questions I propose, however imperfectly, to discuss in the concluding portion of the present work. They belong, _ perhaps, to the domain of probable or conjectural, rather than to that of positive, knowledge. But it may happen that where there is not sufficient warrant for the certainties of science, there may be grounds of analogy adequate for the suggestion of highly probable opinions. It has seemed to me better that this discussion should be entirely reserved for the sequel of the main business of this treatise, —which is the investigation of scientific truths and laws. Experience sufficiently instructs us that the proper order of advance- ment in all inquiries after truth is to proceed from the known to the unknown. There are parts, even of the philosophy and constitution of the human mind, which have been placed fully within the reach of our investigation. To make a due acquaintance with those portions of our nature the basis of all endeavours to penetrate amid the shadows and uncertainties of that conjectural realm which lies beyond and above them, is the course most accordant with the limitations of our present condition. [24] CHAPTER II OF SIGNS IN GENERAL, AND OF THE SIGNS APPROPRIATE TO THE SCIENCE OF LOGIC IN PARTICULAR; ALSO OF THE LAWS TO WHICH THAT CLASS OF SIGNS ARE SUBJECT 1. THAT Language is-an instrument of human reason, and not merely a medium for the expression of thought, is a truth generally admitted. It is proposed in this chapter to inquire what it is that renders Language thus subservient to the most important of our intellectual faculties. In the various steps of this inquiry we shall be led to consider the constitution of Language, considered as a system adapted to an end or purpose ; to investigate its elements ; to seek to determine their mutual relation and dependence ; and to inquire in what manner they contribute to the attainment of the end to which, as co-ordinate parts of a system, they have respect. In proceeding to these inquiries, it will not be necessary to enter into the discussion of that famous question of the schools, whether Language is to be regarded as an essential instrument of reasoning, or whether, on the other hand, it is possible for us to reason without its aid. I suppose this question to be beside the design of the present treatise, for the following reason, viz., that it is the business of Science to investigate laws; and that, whether we regard signs as the representatives of things and of their relations, or as the representatives of the conceptions and operations of the human intellect, in studying the laws of signs, we are in effect studying the manifested laws of reasoning. If there exists a difference between the two inquiries, it is one which does not affect the scientific expressions of formal law, which 26 SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 27 are the object of investigation in the present stage of this work, but relates only to the mode in which those results are presented to the mental regard. For though in in- vestigating the laws of signs, a posterzorz, the immediate subject of examination is Language, with the rules which govern its use ; while in making the internal [25] processes of thought the direct object of inquiry, we appeal in a more immediate way to our personal consciousness,—it will be found that in both cases the results obtained are formally equivalent. Nor could we easily conceive, that the un- numbered tongues and dialects of the earth should have preserved through a long succession of ages so much that is common and universal, were we not assured of the existence of some deep foundation of their agreement in the laws of the mind itself. 2. The elements of which all language consists are signs or symbols. Words are signs. Sometimes they are said to represent things ; sometimes the operations by which the mind combines together the simple notions of things into complex conceptions ; sometimes they express the relations of action, passion, or mere quality, which we perceive to exist among the objects of our experience ; sometimes the emotions of the perceiving mind. But words, although in this and in other ways they fulfil the office of signs, or re- presentative symbols, are not the only signs which we are capable of employing. Arbitrary marks, which speak only to the eye, and arbitrary sounds or actions, which address themselves to some other sense, are equally of the nature of signs, provided that their representative office is defined and ‘understood. Inthe mathematical sciences, letters, and the symbols +, —, =, &c., are used as signs, although the _ term ‘‘sign” is applied to the latter class of symbols, which represent operations or relations, rather than to the former, which represent the elements of number and quantity. As the real import of a sign does not in any way depend upon ‘its particular form or expression, so neither do the laws which determine its use. In the present treatise, however, 28 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT it is with written signs that we have to do, and it is with reference to these exclusively that the term ‘‘sign” will be employed. The essential properties of signs are enumerated in the following definition. Definition.—A sign is an arbitrary mark, having a fixed interpretation, and susceptible of combination with other signs in subjection to fixed laws dependent upon their mutual interpretation. 3. Let us consider the particulars involved in the above definition separately. [26] (1.) In the first place, a sign is an arbitrary mark. It is clearly indifferent what particular word or token we associate with a given idea, provided that the association once made is permanent. The Romans expressed by the word ‘‘civitas” what we designate by the word ‘‘ state.” But both they and we might equally well have employed any other word to represent the same conception. Nothing, indeed, in the nature of Language would prevent us from using a mere letter in the same sense. Were this done, the laws according to which that letter would require to be used would be essentially the same with the laws which govern the use of ‘‘civitas” in the Latin, and of ‘‘state” in the English language, so far at least as the use of those words . is regulated by any general principles common to all languages alike. (2.) In the second place, it is necessary that each sign should possess, within the limits of the same discourse or process of reasoning, a fixed interpretation. The necessity of this condition is obvious, and seems to be founded in the very nature of the subject. There exists, however, a dispute as to the precise nature of the representative office of words or symbols used as names in the processes of reasoning. By some it is maintained, that they represent the conceptions of the mind alone; by others, that they represent things. The question is not of great importance here, as its decision cannot affect the laws according to which signs are employed. I apprehend, however, that the general answer to this and SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 29 such like questions is, that in the processes of reasoning, signs stand in the place and fulfil the office of the conceptions and operations of the mind ; but that as those conceptions and operations represent things, and the connexions and relations of things, so signs represent things with their con- nexions and relations ; and lastly, that as signs stand in the place of the conceptions and operations of the mind, they are subject to the laws of those conceptions and operations. This view will be more fully elucidated in the next chapter ; but it here serves to explain the third of those particulars involved in the definition of a sign, viz., its subjection to fixed laws of combination depending upon the nature of its interpretation. 4. The analysis and classification of those signs by which the [27] operations of reasoning are conducted will Be con- sidered in the following Proposition : PROPOSITION I All the operations of Language, as an instrument of reasoning, may be conducted by a system of signs composed of the following elements, viz. : Ist. Leteral symbols, as x, y, &c., representing things as subjects of our conceptions. 2nd. Szgus of operation, as +, —, xX, standing for those operations of the mind by which the conceptions of things are combined or resolved so as to form new conceptions involving the same elements. = 3rd. The sign of identity, = And these symbols of Logtc are tn their use subject to definite laws, partly agreeing with and partly differing from the laws of the corresponding symbols tn the sctence of Algebra. Let it be assumed as a criterion of the true elements of rational discourse, that they should be susceptible of com- bination in the simplest forms and by the simplest laws, and thus combining should generate 411 other known and 30 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT conceivable forms of language ; and adopting this principle, let the following classification be considered. CLASS I 5. Appellative or descriptive signs, expressing etther the name of a thing, or some quality or ctrcumstance belonging to tt. To this class we may obviously refer the substantive proper or common, and the adjective. These may indeed be regarded as differing only in this respect, that the former expresses the substantive existence of the individual thing or things to which it refers; the latter implies that exist- ence. If we attach to the adjective the universally under- stood subject ‘‘ being” or ‘‘thing,” it becomes virtually a substantive, and may for all the essential purposes of reason- ing be replaced by the substantive. Whether or not, in every particular of the mental regard, it is the same thing to say, ‘‘ Water is a fluid thing,” as to say, ‘‘ Water is fluid” ; it is at least equivalent in the expression of the processes of reasoning. [28] It is clear also, that to the above class we must refer any sign which may conventionally be used to express some circumstances or relation, the detailed exposition of which would involve the use of many signs. The epithets of poetic diction are very frequently of this kind. They are usually compounded adjectives, singly fulfilling the office of a many-worded description. Homer’s ‘‘ deep-eddying ocean” embodies a virtual description in the single word βαθυδίνης. And conventionally any other description ad- dressed either to the imagination or to the intellect might equally be represented by a single sign, the use of which would in all essential points be subject to the same laws as the use of the adjective ‘‘ good” or ‘‘ great.” Combined with the subject ‘“‘thing,” such a sign would virtually — become a substantive; and by a single substantive the combined meaning both of thing and quality might ΡῈ expressed. SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 31 6. Now, as it has been defined that a sign is an arbitrary mark, it is permissible to replace all signs of the species above described by letters. Let us then agree to represent the class of individuals to which a particular name or description is applicable, by a single letter, as x If the name is ‘‘men,” for instance, let x represent ‘‘ all men,” or the class ‘‘men.” By a class is usually meant a collection of individuals, to each of which a particular name or descrip- tion may be applied ; but in this work the meaning of the term will be extended so as to include the case in which but a single individual exists, answering to the required mame or description, as well as the cases denoted by the mms “nothing” and “‘universe,” which as “classes” should be understood to comprise respectively ‘‘no beings,” ‘fall beings.” Again, if an adjective, as ‘‘ good,” is em- ployed as a term of description, let us represent by a letter, as y, all things to which the description ‘‘ good” is applicable, ze, ‘‘all good things,” or the class ‘‘ good things.” Let it further be agreed, that by the combination ay shall be represented that class of things to which the names or descriptions represented by x and y are simultane- ously applicable. Thus, if x alone stands for ‘‘ white _ things,” and y for ‘‘ sheep,” let xy stand for ‘‘ white sheep ” ; and in like manner, if ¢ stand for ‘‘horned things,” and 4 and y retain their previous interpretations, let zy re- present [29] ‘‘ horned white sheep,” z.e. that collection of things to which the name ‘‘sheep,” and the descriptions “white” and ‘‘horned” are together applicable. Let us now consider the laws to which the symbols 4, y, : &c., used in the above sense, are subject. 7. First, it is evident, that according to the above com- _binations, the order in which two symbols are written is indifferent. The expressions zy and yx equally represent that class of things to the several members of which the _fames or descriptions + and y are together applicable. Hence we have, XY =X. (1) 32 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT In the case of x representing white things, and y sheep, either of the members of this equation will represent the class of ‘‘white sheep.” There may be a difference as to the order in which the conception is formed, but there is none as to the individual things which are comprehended under it. In like manner, if + represent ‘‘ estuaries,” and y “rivers,” the expressions xy and yx will indifferently re- Present | vivers that are estuaries,” or ‘‘ estuaries that are rivers,” the combination in this case being in ordinary language that of two substantives, instead of that of a substantive and an adjective as in the previous instance. Let there be a third symbol, as 2, representing that class of things to which the term ‘‘ navigable” is applicable, and any one of the following expressions, COV, Bays Χ»5, (ECS will represent the class of ‘‘navigable rivers that are estuaries. ” If one of the descriptive terms should have some implied reference to another, it is only necessary to include that reference expressly in its stated meaning, in order to render the above remarks still applicable. Thus, if x represent ἐξ wise” and y ‘‘counsellor,” we shall have to define whether x implies wisdom in the absolute sense, or only the wisdom of counsel. With such definition the law ry =yx continues to be valid. We are permitted, therefore, to employ the symbols x, y, 2, &c., in the place of the substantives, adjectives, and descriptive phrases subject to the rule of interpretation, that any expression in which several of these symbols are written together shall — vepresent all the objects or tnadt-[30]|viduals to which their several meanings are together applicable, and to the law that the order in which the symbols succeed each other ts indifferent. As the rule of interpretation has been sufficiently ex- emplified, I shall deem it unnecessary always to express the subject ‘‘things” in defining the interpretation of a symbol used for an adjective. When I say, let x represent SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 33 ‘* good,” it will be understood that x only represents ‘‘ good ” when a subject for that quality is supplied by another pool, and that, used alone, its interpretation will be ‘*good things.” 8. Concerning the law above determined, the folate observations, which will also be more or less appropriate to certain other laws to be deduced hereafter, may be added. First, I would remark, that this law is a law of thought, and not, properly speaking, a law of things. Difference in the order of the qualities or attributes of an object, apart from all questions of causation, is a difference in conception merely. The law (1) expresses as a general truth, that the same thing may be conceived in different ways, and states the nature of that difference ; and it does no more than this. Secondly, As a law of thought, it is actually developed ‘in a law of Language, the product and the instrument of thought. Though the tendency of prose writing is toward uniformity, yet even there the order of sequence of adjectives, absolute in their meaning, and applied to the same subject, is indifferent, but poetic diction borrows much of its rich diversity from the extension of the same lawful freedom to the substantive also. The language of Milton is peculiarly distinguished by this species of variety. Not only does the substantive often precede the adjectives by which it is qualified, but it is frequently placed in their midst. In the first few lines of the invocation to Light, we meet with such examples as the following : “ Offspring of heaven first-born.” “The rising world of waters dark and deep.” “Bright effluence of dr7ght essence increate.” Now these inverted forms are not simply the fruits of a poetic license. They are the natural expressions of a freedom sanc-[3I]tioned by the intimate laws of thought, but for reasons of convenience not exercised in the ordinary use of language. Thirdly, The law expressed by (1) may be characterized 3 34 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT by saying that the literal symbols 7, 7, 5, are commutative, like the symbols of Algebra. In saying this, it is not affirmed that the process of multiplication in Algebra, of which the fundamental law is expressed by the equation Δ το 8 possesses in itself any analogy with that process of logical combination which xy has been made to represent above ; but only that if the arithmetical and the logical process are expressed in the same manner, their symbolical expressions will be subject to the same formal law. The evidence of that subjection is in the two cases quite distinct. 9. As the combination of two literal symbols in the form ay expresses the whole of that class of objects to which the names or qualities represented by x and y are together applicable, it follows that if the two symbols have exactly the same signification, their combination expresses no more than either of the symbols taken alone would do. In such case we should therefore have Ly =X: As y is, however, supposed to have the same meaning as x, we may replace it in the above equation by x, and we thus get XX =X. Now in common Algebra the combination xxv is more briefly represented by 2%. Let us adopt the same principle of notation here; for the mode of expressing a particular succession of mental operations is a thing in itself quite as arbitrary as the mode of expressing a single idea or operation (II. 3). In accordance with this notation, then, the above equation assumes the form x= x, (2) and is, in fact, the expression of a second general law of those symbols by which names, qualities, or descriptions, are symbolically represented. [32] The reader must bear in mind that although the SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 35 _symbols x and y in the examples previously formed received significations distinct from each other, nothing prevents us from attributing to them precisely the same signification, It is evident that the more nearly their actual significations approach to each other, the more nearly does the class of things denoted by the combination xy approach to identity with the class denoted by 4, as well as with that denoted by y. The case supposed in the demonstration of the equation (2) is that of absolute identity of meaning. The law which it expresses is practically exemplified in language. To say ‘‘good, good,” in relation to any subject, though a cumbrous and useless pleonasm, is the same as to say ‘‘sood.” Thus ‘‘ good, good” men, is equivalent to ‘‘ good ” men. Such repetitions of words are indeed sometimes em- ployed to heighten a quality or strengthen an affirmation. But this effect is merely secondary and conventional ; it is not founded in the intrinsic relations of language and thought. Most of the operations which we observe in nature, or per- form ourselves, are of such a kind that their effect is aug- mented by repetition, and this circumstance prepares us to expect the same thing in language, and even to use repetition when we design to speak with emphasis. But neither in strict reasoning nor in exact discourse is there any just ground for such a practice. 10. We pass now to the consideration of another class of the signs of speech, and of the laws connected with their use. CLASS II 11. Szgus of those mental operations whereby we collect parts into a whole, or separate a whole into 115 parts. We are not only capable of entertaining the conceptions of objects, as characterized by names, qualities, or circum- stances, applicable to each individual of the group under consideration, but also of forming the aggregate conception of a group of objects consisting of partial groups, each of which is separately named or described. For this purpose we use the conjunctions ‘‘and,” ‘‘or,” ὅς. ‘‘ Trees and 36 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT minerals,” ‘‘ barren mountains, or fertile vales,” are examples of this kind. In strictness, the words [33] ‘‘and,” ‘‘or,” interposed between the terms descriptive of two or more classes of objects, imply that those classes are quite distinct, so that no member of one is found in another. In this and in all other respects the words ‘‘and” ‘‘or” are analogous with the sign + in algebra, and their laws are identical. Thus the expression ‘‘men and women” is, conventional meanings set aside, equivalent with the expression ‘* women and men.” Let represent ‘‘men,” y, ‘‘women”; and let + stand for ‘‘and” and ‘‘ or,” then we have X+YH=VH+X, (3) an equation which would equally hold true if x and y repre- sented zumbers, and + were the sign of arithmetical addition. Let the symbol z stand for the adjective ‘‘ European,” then since it is, in effect, the same thing to say ‘‘ European men and women,” as to say ‘‘ European men and European women,” we have a(x +y) = 2x + 27. (4) And this equation also would be equally true were 7, y, and z symbols of number, and were the juxtaposition of two literal symbols to represent their algebraic product, just as in the logical signification previously given, it re- presents the class of objects to which both the epithets conjoined belong. The above are the laws which govern the use of the sign +, here used to denote the positive operation of aggregating parts into a whole. But the very idea of an operation effect- ing some positive change seems to suggest to us the idea of an opposite or negative operation, having the effect of un- doing what the former one has done. Thus we cannot conceive it possible to collect parts into a whole, and not conceive it also possible to separate a part from a whole. This operation we express in common language by the sign except, as, ‘‘ All men except Asiatics,” ‘‘ All states except those which are monarchical.” Here it is implied that the SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 37 things excepted form a part of the things from which they are excepted. As we have expressed the operation of aggregation by the sign +, so we may express the negative operation above described by — minus. Thus if + be taken ἡ to represent men, and y, Asiatics, 2,4. Asiatic men, [34] then the conception of ‘‘ All men except Asiatics” will be expressed by x—y. And if we represent by 2, ‘‘ states,” and by y the descriptive property ‘‘ having a monarchical form,” then the conception of ‘‘ All states except those which are monarchical” will be expressed by x—-2y. As it is indifferent for all the essextzal purposes of reason- ing whether we express excepted cases first or last in the order of speech, it is also indifferent in what order we write any series of terms, some of which are affected by the sign —. Thus we have, as in the common algebra, x Y= -Y+x, (5) Still representing by x the class ‘‘ men,” and by y ‘‘ Asiatics,” let z represent the adjective ‘‘ white.” Now to apply the adjective ‘‘ white” to the collection of men expressed by the phrase ‘‘ Men except Asiatics,” is the same as to say, ‘White men, except white Asiatics.” Hence we have a(x — y) = 2x -- By. (6) This is also in accordance with the laws of ordinary algebra. The equations (4) and (6) may be considered as exempli- fication of a single general law, which may be stated by saying, that the literal symbols, x, y, 2, &c. are distributive in thetr operation, ‘The general fact which that law ex- presses is this, viz. :—If any quality or circumstance is ascribed to all the members of a group, formed either by aggregation or exclusion of partial groups, the resulting conception is the same as if the quality or circumstance were first ascribed to each member of the partial groups, and the aggregation or exclusion effected afterwards. That which is ascribed to the members of the whole is ascribed to the members of all its parts, howsoever those parts are connected together. 38 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT CLASS ΠῚ 12. Signs by which relation is expressed, and by which we form propostitons. Though all verbs may with propriety be referred to this class, it is sufficient for the purposes of Logic to consider it as including only the substantive verb zs or ave, since every other verb [35] may be resolved into this element, and one of the signs included under Class I. For as those signs are used to express quality or circumstance of every kind, they may be employed to express the active or pass- ive relation of the subject of the verb, considered with refer- ence either to past, to present, or to future time. Thus the Proposition, ‘‘Czsar conquered the Gauls,” may be re- solved into ‘‘Czesar is he who conquered the Gauls.” The ground of this analysis I conceive to be the following :— Unless we understand what is meant by having conquered the Gauls, z.e. by the expression ‘‘ One who conquered the Gauls,” we cannot understand the sentence in question. It is, therefore, truly an element of that sentence ; another element is ‘‘ Cesar,” and there is yet another required, the copula zs, to show the connexion of these two. I do not, however, affirm that there is no other mode than the above of contemplating the relation expressed by the proposition, ‘‘Czesar conquered the Gauls”; but only that the analysis here given is a correct one for the particular point of view which has been taken, and that it suffices for the purposes of logical deduction. It may be remarked that the passive | and future participles of the Greek language imply the existence of the principle which has been asserted, viz. : that the sign zs or ave may be regarded as an element of ἢ every personal verb. 13. The above sign, zs or ave, may be expressed by the symbol =. The laws, or as would usually be said, the axioms which the symbol introduces, are next to be considered. Let us take the Proposition, ‘‘ The stars are the suns and SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 39 the planets,” and let us represent stars by +, suns by y, and planets by z; we have then X=Y+2. (7) Now if it be true that the stars are the suns and the planets, it will follow that the stars, except the planets, are suns. This would give the equation τ τς (8) which must therefore be a deduction from (7). Thus a term z has been removed from one side of an equation to the other by [36] changing its sign. This is in accordance with the algebraic rule of transposition. But instead of dwelling upon particular cases, we may at once affirm the general axioms :— ist. If equal things are added to equal things, the wholes are equal. 2nd. If equal things are taken from equal things, the remainders are equal. And it hence appears that we may add or subtract equations, and employ the rule of transposition above given just as in common algebra. Again: If two classes of things, x and y, be identical, that is, if all the members of the one are members of the other, then those members of the one class which possess a given property 2 will be identical with those members of the other which possess the same property z. Hence if we have the equation eee then whatever class or property # may represent, we have also ZX = ZY. This is formally the same as the algebraic law :—If both members of an equation are multiplied by the same quantity, the products are equal. In like manner it may be shown that if the correspond- 40 THE. LAWS OF THOUGHT ing members of two equations are multiplied together, the resulting equation is true. 14. Here, however, the analogy of the present system with that of algebra, as commonly stated, appears to stop. Suppose it true that those members of a class x which possess a certain property 2 are identical with those members of a class y which possess the same property 2, it does not follow that the members of the class x universally are identical with the members of the class y. Hence it cannot be inferred from the equation 2. ΞΞΖ2.. that the equation τ πε is also true. In other words, the axiom of algebraists, that both [37] sides of an equation may be divided by the same quantity, has no formal equivalent here. I say no formal equivalent, because, in accordance with the general spirit of these inquiries, it is not even sought to determine whether the mental operation which is represented by removing a logical symbol, 5, from a combination gx, is in itself analogous with the operation of division in Arithmetic. That mental operation is indeed identical with what is commonly termed Abstraction, and it will hereafter appear that its laws are dependent upon the laws already deduced in this chapter. What has now been shown is, that there does not exist among those laws anything analogous in form with a commonly received axiom of Algebra. But a little consideration will show that even in common algebra that axiom does not possess the generality of those other axioms which have been considered. The deduction of the equation r=y from the equation zr=zy is only valid when it is known that ¢ is not equal to o. If then the value z=0 is supposed to be admissible in the algebraic system, the axiom above stated ceases to be applicable, and the analogy before exemplified remains at least unbroken. 15. However, it is not with the symbols of quantity generally that it is of any importance, except as a matter of SIGNS AND THEIR LAWS 41 speculation, to trace such affinities. We have seen (II. 9) that the symbols of Logic are subject to the special law, w= x Now of the symbols of Number there are but two, viz. o and 1, which are subject to the same formal law. We know that o?=o, and that 17=1; and the equation τ τ, considered as algebraic, has no other roots than o and 1. Hence, instead of determining the measure of formal agreement of the symbols of Logic with those of Number generally, it is more immediately suggested to us to com- pare them with symbols of quantity admitting only of the values Ὁ and 1. Let us conceive, then, of an Algebra in which the symbols 2, y, 2, &c. admit indifferently of the values Ο and 1, and of these values alone. The laws, the -axioms, and the processes of such an Algebra will be identical in their whole extent with the laws, the axioms, and the processes of an Al-[38]gebra of Logic. Difference of interpretation will alone divide them. Upon this principle the method of the following work is established. 16. It now remains to show that those constituent parts of ordinary language which have not been considered in the previous sections of this chapter are either resolvable _ into the same elements as those which have been considered, or are subsidiary to those elements by contributing to their more precise definition. The substantive, the adjective, and the verb, together with the particles and, except, we have already considered. The pronoun may be regarded as a particular form of the substantive or the adjective. The adverb modifies the meaning of the verb, but does not affect its nature. Pre- positions contribute to the expression of circumstance or relation, and thus tend to give precision and detail to the meaning of the literal symbols. The conjunctions 7/, either, or, are used chiefly in the expression of relation among propositions, and it will hereafter be shown that the same relations can be completely expressed by elementary 42 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT symbols analogous in interpretation, and identical in form and law with the symbols whose use and meaning have been explained in this Chapter. As to any remaining elements of speech, it will, upon examination, be found that they are used either to give a more definite significance to the terms of discourse, and thus enter into the inter- pretation of the literal symbols already considered, or to express some emotion or state of feeling accompanying the utterance of a proposition, and thus do not belong to the province of the understanding, with which alone our present concern lies. Experience of its use will testify to the sufficiency of the classification which has been adopted. [39] CELAL Pik ΠῚ DERIVATION OF THE LAWS OF THE SYMBOLS OF LOGIC FROM THE ~*~ LAWS OF THE OPERATIONS OF THE HUMAN MIND 1. THE object of science, properly so called, is the know- ledge of laws and relations. To be able to distinguish what is essential to this end, from what is only accidentally associated with it, is one of the most important conditions of scientific progress. I say, to distinguish between these elements, because a consistent devotion to science does not require that the attention should be altogether withdrawn from other speculations, often of a metaphysical nature, _ with which it is not unfrequently connected. Such ques- tions, for instance, as the existence of a sustaining ground — zi . οὗ phenomena, the reality of cause, the propriety of forms of speech implying that the successive states of things are connected by operations, and others of a like nature, may possess a deep interest and significance in relation to science, without being essentially scientific. It is indeed scarcely possible to express the conclusions of natural science without _ borrowing the language of these conceptions. Nor is there necessarily any practical inconvenience arising from this source. They who believe, and they who refuse to believe, ἘΠῚ ἑ that there is more in the relation of cause and effect than an invariable order of succession, agree in their interpretation of the conclusions of physical astronomy. But they only _ agree because they recognise a common element of scientific truth, which is independent of their particular views of the ry - Nature of causation. 2. If this distinction is important in physical science, much more does it deserve attention in connexion with 43 44 THE TRAWS OF THOCGA SE the science of the intellectual powers. For the questions which this science presents become, in expression at least, almost necessarily mixed up with modes of thought and language, which betray a metaphysical origin. The idealist would give to the laws of reasoning [40] one form of ex- pression; the sceptic, if true to his principles, another. They who regard the phenomena with which we are con- cerned in this inquiry as the mere successive states of the thinking subject devoid of any causal connexion, and they who refer them to the operations of an active intelligence, would, if consistent, equally differ in their modes of state- ment. Like difference would also result from a difference — of classification of the mental faculties. Now the principle — which I would here assert, as affording us the only ground | of confidence and stability amid so much of seeming and of : real diversity, is the following, viz., that if the laws in ques- ; tion are really deduced from observation, they have a real F existence as laws of the human mind, independently of any ~ metaphysical theory which may seem to be involved in the — mode of their statement. They contain an element of truth — which no ulterior criticism upon the nature, or even upon — the reality, of the mind’s operations, can essentially affect. — Let it even be granted that the mind is but a succession of — states of consciousness, a series of fleeting impressions un-_ caused from without or from within, emerging out of nothing, and returning into nothing again,—the last refinement of — the sceptic intellect,—still, as laws of succession, or at least of a past succession, the results to which observation had led | would remain true. They would require to be interpreted into a language from whose vocabulary all such terms as | cause and effect, operation and subject, substance and attri- | bute, had been banished ; but they would still be valid as scientific truths. Moreover, as any statement of the laws of thought, — founded upon actual observation, must thus contain scientific elements which are independent of metaphysical theories of the nature of the mind, the practical application of such ele- DERIVATION OF THE LAWS 45 ments to the construction of a system or method of reason- ing must also be independent of metaphysical distinctions. For it is upon the scientific elements involved in the state- ment of the laws, that any practical application will rest, just as the practical conclusions of physical astronomy are independent of any theory of the cause of gravitation, but rest only on the knowledge of its phenomenal effects. And, therefore, as respects both the determi-[41]nation of the laws of thought, and the practical use of them when dis- covered, we are, for all really scientific ends, unconcerned with the truth or falsehood of any metaphysical speculations whatever. . 3. The course which it appears to me to be expedient, under these circumstances, to adopt, is to avail myself as far as possible of the language of common discourse, without regard to any theory of the nature and powers of the mind which it may be thought to embody. For instance, it is agreeable to common usage to say that we converse with each other by the communication of ideas, or conceptions, such communication being the office of words; and that ‘with reference to any particular ideas or conceptions pre- sented to it, the mind possesses certain powers or faculties by which the mental regard may be fixed upon some ideas, to the exclusion of others, or by which the given conceptions or ideas may, in various ways, be combined together. To those faculties or powers different names, as Attention, Simple Apprehension, Conception or Imagination, Abstrac- tion, &c., have been given,—names which have not only furnished the titles of distinct divisions of the philosophy of the human mind, but passed into the common language of -men. Whenever, then, occasion shall occur to use these | terms, I shall do so without implying thereby that I accept the theory that the mind possesses such and such powers and faculties as distinct elements of its activity. Nor is . it indeed necessary to inquire whether such powers of the understanding have a distinct existence or not. We may merge these different titles under the one generic name of 46 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Operations of the human mind, define these operations so far as is necessary for the purposes of this work, and then seek to express their ultimate laws. Such will be the general order of the course which I shall pursue, though reference will occasionally be made to the names which common agreement has assigned to the particular states or operations of the mind which may fall under our notice. It will be most convenient to distribute the more definite re- sults of the following investigation into distinct Propositions. [42] PROPOSITION 1 4. Lo deduce the laws of the symbols of Logic from a con- sideration of those operations of the mind which are implied en the strict use of language as an instrument of reasoning. In every discourse, whether of the mind conversing with its own thoughts, or of the individual in his intercourse with others, there is an assumed or expressed limit within which the subjects of its operation are confined. The most un- fettered discourse is that in which the words we use are understood in the widest possible application, and for them the limits of discourse are co-extensive with those of the universe itself. But more usually we confine ourselves to a less spacious field. Sometimes, in discoursing of men we | imply (without expressing the limitation) that it is of men — only under certain circumstances and conditions that we ~ speak, as of civilized men, or of men in the vigour of life, — or of men under some other condition or relation. Now, — whatever may be the extent of the field within which all the — objects of our discourse are found, that field may properly be termed the universe of discourse. 5. Furthermore, this universe of discourse is in the strictest sense the ultimate swdject of the discourse. The office of any | name or descriptive term employed under the limitations supposed is not to raise in the mind the conception of all the beings or objects to which that name or description is applicable, but only of those which exist within the supposed ey Se Le er Ee he ee ee ee ae ee ee i i τὸς κου ον oh tp τ" DERIVATION OF THE. EAWS 47 universe of discourse. If that universe of discourse is the actual universe of things, which it always is when our words are taken in their real and literal sense, then by men we mean all men that exist; but if the universe of discourse is limited by any antecedent implied understanding, then it is of men under the limitation thus introduced that we speak. It is in both cases the business of the word mez to direct a certain operation of the mind, by which, from the proper universe of discourse, we select or fix upon the individuals signified. 6. Exactly of the same kind is the mental operation implied by the use of an adjective. Let, for instance, the universe of discourse be the actual Universe. Then, as the word men directs [43] us to select mentally from that Universe all the beings to which the term ‘‘men” is applicable ; so the ad- jective ‘‘ good,” in the combination ‘‘ good men,” directs us still further to select mentally from the class of mez all those who possess the further quality ‘‘good”; and if another adjective were prefixed to the combination ‘‘ good men,” it would direct a further operation of the same nature, having “reference to that further quality which it might be chosen _ to express. It is important to notice carefully the real nature of the operation here described, for it is conceivable, that it might have been different from what it is. Were the adjective simply attributive in its character, it would seem, that when a particular set of beings is designated by mez, the prefixing of the adjective good would direct us to attach mentally to all those beings the quality of goodness. But this is not the real office of the adjective. The operation which we really perform is one of selectzon according to a prescribed principle or cdea. ‘To what faculties of mind such an opera- _ tion would be referred, according to the received classifica- tion of its powers, it is not important to inquire, but I suppose that it would be considered as dependent upon the two faculties of Conception or Imagination, and Atten- tion. To the one of these faculties might be referred the 48 THE LAWS. OF THOUGH & formation of the general conception; to the other the fixing of the mental regard upon those individuals within the prescribed universe of discourse which answer to the conception. If, however, as seems not improbable, the power of Attention is nothing more than the power of continuing the exercise of any other faculty of the mind, we might properly regard the whole of the mental process above described as referrible to the mental faculty of Imagination or Conception, the first. step of the process being the conception of the Universe itself, and each succeeding step limiting in a definite manner the conception thus formed. Adopting this view, I shall describe each such step, or any definite combination of such steps, as a definite act of conception. And the use of this term I shall extend so as to include in its meaning not only the conception of classes of objects represented by particular | names or simple attributes of quality, but also the combina- tion of such conceptions in any manner consistent with the powers and limitations [44] of the human mind; indeed, any intellectual operation short of that which is involved in the structure of a sentence or proposition. The general laws to which such operations of the mind are subject are now to be considered. 7. Now it will be shown that the laws which in the preceding chapter have been determined a posterior¢ from the constitution of language, for the use of the literal symbols of Logic, are in reality the laws of that definite mental operation which has just been described. We commence our discourse with a certain understanding as _ to the limits of its subject, ze. as to the limits of its | Universe. Every name, every term of description that — we employ, directs him whom we address to the per-_ formance of a certain mental operation upon that subject. And thus is thought communicated. But as each name or descriptive term is in this view but the representative of an intellectual operation, that operation being also prior in the © order of nature, it is clear that the laws of the name or. ee a a i sect tt Stil πῶς Nd 9g a DERIVATION OF THE LAWS 49 symbol must be of a derivative character,—must, in fact, originate in those of the operation which they represent. That the laws of the symbol and of the mental process are identical in expression will now be shown. 8. Let us then suppose that the universe ot our discourse is the actual universe, so that words are to be used in the full extent of their meaning, and let us consider the two mental operations implied by the words ‘‘ white” and ‘*men.” The word ‘‘ men” implies the operation of select- ing in thought from its subject, the universe, all men; and the resulting conception, men, becomes the subject of the next operation. The operation implied by the word ‘‘ white ” is that of selecting from its subject, ‘‘men,” all of that class which are white. The final resulting conception is that of ‘‘white men.” Now it is perfectly apparent that if the operations above described had been performed in a con- verse order, the result would have been the same. Whether we begin by forming the conception of ‘‘ sen,” and then by a second intellectual act limit that conception to ‘‘ white men,” or whether we begin by forming the conception of *< white objects,” and then limit it to such of that class as are ‘‘men,” is perfectly indifferent so far as the result is concerned. It is obvious that the order of the mental pro- cesses would be equally [45] indifferent if for the words *‘white” and ‘‘men” we substituted any other descriptive or appellative terms whatever, provided only that their meaning was fixed and absolute. And thus the indifference of the order of two successive acts of the faculty of Con- ception, the one of which furnishes the subject upon which the other is supposed to operate, is a general condition of the exercise of that faculty. It isa law of the mind, and itis the real origin of that law of the literal symbols of Logic which constitutes its formal expression (1) Chap. II. g. It is equally clear that the mental operation above described is of such a nature that its effect is not altered by repetition. Suppose that by a definite act of conception the attention has been fixed upon men, and that by another 4 50 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT exercise of the same faculty we limit it to those of the race ; who are white. Then any further repetition of the latter : mental act, by which the attention is limited to white ~ objects, does not in any way modify the conception arrived — at, viz., that of white men. This is also an example of at general law of the mind, and it has its formal expression in ἢ the law ((2) Chap. II.) of the literal symbols. : 10, Again, it is manifest that from the conceptions of two. ' distinct classes of things we can form the conception of παῖ collection of things which the two classes taken together compose ; and it is obviously indifferent in what order of position or of priority those classes are presented to the ᾿ mental view. This is another general law of the mind, δπά its expression is found in (3) Chap. II. q 11. It is not necessary to pursue this course of inquiry — and comparison. Sufficient illustration has been given to” render manifest the two following positions, viz. : : First, That the operations of the mind, by which, in the exercise of its power of imagination or conception, it combines and modifies the simple ideas of things or” qualities, not less than those operations of the reason which” are exercised upon truths and propositions, are subject to- general laws. : Secondly, That those laws are mathematical in their form, q and that they are actually developed in the essential laws o ᾿ human language. Wherefore the laws of the symbols of Logic [46] are deducible from a consideration of the opera-_ tions of the mind in reasoning. 12, The remainder of this chapter will be occupied with questions relating to that law of thought whose expression — is #27 =x (II. 9), a law which, as has been implied (IJ. 15} forms the characteristic distinction of the operations of the mind in its ordinary discourse and reasoning, as compared © with its.operations when occupied with the general algebra of quantity. An important part of the following inquiry will consist in proving that the symbols o and 1 occupy 8 place, and are susceptible of an interpretation, among the DERIVATION OF THE LAWS 51 symbols of Logic; and it may first be necessary to show how particular symbols, such as the above, may with pro- priety and advantage be employed in the representation of distinct systems of thought. The ground of this propriety cannot consist in any com- munity of interpretation. For in systems of thought so truly distinct as those of Logic and Arithmetic (I use the latter term in its widest sense as the science of Number), there is, properly speaking, no community of subject. The one of them is conversant with the very conceptions of ‘things, the other takes account solely of their numerical relations. But inasmuch as the forms and methods of any system of reasoning depend immediately upon the laws to which the symbols are subject, and only mediately, through the above link of connexion, upon their interpretation, there may be both propriety and advantage in employing the same symbols in different systems of thought, provided that such interpretations can be assigned to them as shall render their formal laws identical, and their use consistent. The ground of that employment will not then be community of interpre- tation, but the community of the formal laws, to which in their respective systems they are subject. Nor must that community of formal laws be established upon any other ground than that of a careful observation and comparison of those results which are seen to flow independently from the interpretations of the systems under consideration. These observations will explain the process of inquiry adopted in the following Proposition. The literal symbols of Logic are [47] universally subject to the law whose ex- pression is #2=2x, Of the symbols of Number there are two only, o and 1, which satisfy this law. But each of these symbols is also subject to a law peculiar to itself in the ‘system of numerical magnitude, and this suggests the in- quiry, what interpretations must be given to the literal symbols of Logic, in order that the same peculiar and formal laws may be realized in the logical system also. 52 OTT EAS OF THOUGHT τ -- PROPOSITION II 13. 70 determine the logical value and significance of the symbols 0 and 1. eS ee A The symbol Ο, as used in Algebra, satisfies the following formal law, Ox yO) ΟΣ 6)5Ξ0, ) whatever mumber y may represent. That this formal Lavi may be obeyed in the system of Logic, we must assign to. the symbol o such an interpretation that the class repreg sented by oy may be identical with the class represented by oO, whatever the class y may be. Ai little consideration will show that this condition is satisfied if the symbol o reprell sent Nothing. In accordance with a previous definition, we- may term Nothing aclass. In fact, Nothing and Universe are the two limits of class extension, for they are the limits. of the possible interpretations of general names, none of | which can relate to fewer individuals than are comprised in| Nothing, or to more than are comprised in the Universe. Now whatever the class y may be, the individuals which are common to it and to the class ‘‘ Nothing” are identical with) those comprised in the class ‘‘ Nothing,” for they are none. And thus by assigning to Ο the interpretation Nothing, the: law (1) is satisfied ; and it is not otherwise satisfied consis- | tently with the perfectly general character of the class y. : Secondly, The symbol 1 satisfies in the system of Numba the following law, viz. Le ge Onn, γον" whatever number y may represent. And this formal equa-' tion being assumed as equally valid in the system of this: work, in [48] which 1 and y represent classes, it appears: that the symbol 1 must represent such a class that all the in-- dividuals which are found in any proposed class y are also. all the individuals Iy that are common to that class y and} the class represented by 1. A little consideration will here show that the class represented by 1 must be ‘‘ the Uni-' PERV ALTON OR Sih L AWS 53 verse,” since this is the only class in which are found αὐ the individuals that exist in any class. Hence the respective interpretations of the symbols o and 1 in the system of Logic are Nothing and Universe. == 14. As with the idea of any class of objects as ‘‘ men, there is suggested to the mind the idea of the contrary class of beings which are not men; and as the whole Universe is made up of these two classes together, since of every individual which it comprehends we may affirm either that it is a man, or that it is not a man, it becomes important +P ᾿ to inquire how such contrary names are to be expressed. Such is the object of the following Proposition. PROPOSITION III Ὶ Tf x represent any class of objects, then will 1 —%x represent ‘the contrary or supplementary class of objects, 1.6. the class including all objects which are not comprehended in the class x. For greater distinctness of conception let x represent the class men, and let us express, according to the last Pro- position, the Universe by 1; now if from the conception of the Universe, as consisting of ‘‘men” and ‘‘not-men,” we exclude the conception of ‘‘men,” the resulting con- ‘ception is that of the contrary class, ‘‘not-men.” Hence the class ‘‘not-men” will be represented by 1—% And, in general, whatever class of objects is represented i the symbol a, the contrary class will be expressed by I — 1s. Although the following Proposition belongs in strict- ness toa future chapter of this work, devoted to the subject of maxims or necessary truths, yet, on account of the great importance of that law of thought to which it relates, it has been thought proper to introduce it here. [49] PROPOSITION IV That axiom of metaphysicians which is termed the principle Of contradiction, and which affirms that it ἐς tmpossible for $4 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT any being to possess a quality, and at the same time not to” possess it, ἐξ a consequence of the fundamental law of thought, © whose expression ts =X. : Let us write this equation in the form 2 x—x*?=0, whence we have : x(1-—x)=0; (1) both these transformations being justified by the axiomatic — laws of combination and transposition (II. 13). Let us, — for simplicity of conception, give to the symbol ~# the ᾿ particular interpretation of men, then 1 --α will represent — the class of ‘‘not-men” (Prop. III.) Now the formal - product of the expressions of two classes represents that ' class of individuals which is common to them both (II. 6). Hence 2(1 —%) will represent the class whose members are | at once ‘‘ men,” and ‘‘ not men,” and the equation (1) thus 3 express the principle, that a class whose members are at q the same time men and not men does not exist. In other y words, that 22 7s zmpossible for the same individual to be at the same time a man and not aman. Now let the meaning © of the symbol # be extended from the representing of ‘‘ men,” to that of any class of beings characterized by the possession 4 of any quality whatever ; and the equation (1) will then j express that it is impossible for a being to possess a quality . and not to possess that quality at the same time. But this . is identically that ‘‘ principle of contradiction” which , Aristotle has described as the fundamental axiom of all philosophy. ““Τ is impossible that the same quality should — both belong and not belong to the same thing. . . This — is the most certain of all principles. . . Wherefore they who demonstrate refer to this as an ultimate opinion. For ἢ it is by nature the source of all the other axioms.” * ᾿ [50] The above interpretation has been introduced not 7 ns Td yap αὐτὸ ἄμα ὑπάρχειν τε καὶ μὴ ὑπάρχειν ἀδύνατον τῷ αὐτῷ καὶ κατὰ τὸν αὐτὸ. a Αὕτη δὴ πασῶν ἐστὶ βεβαιοτάτη τῶν ἀρχῶν... Διὸ πάντες οἱ ἀποδεικ- νύντες εἰς ταύτην ἀνάγουσιν ἐσχάτην δόξαν᾽ φύσει γὰρ ἀρχὴ καὶ τῶν ἄλλων ἀξιω- — μάτων αὕτη mavtwy.—Metaphysica, III, 3. 2 DERIVATION OF THE LAWS Ἢ on account of its immediate value in the present system, but as an illustration of a significant fact in the philosophy of the intellectual powers, viz., that what has been commonly regarded as the fundamental axiom of metaphysics is but the consequence of a law of thought, mathematical in its form. I desire to direct attention also to the circumstance that the equation (1) in which that fundamental law of thought is expressed is an equation of the second degree. * Without speculating at all in this chapter upon the question, whether that circumstance is necessary in its own nature, we may venture to assert that if it had not existed, the whole procedure of the understanding would have been different from what it is. Thus it is a consequence of the fact that the fundamental equation of thought is of the second degree, that we perform the operation of analysis and classification, by division into pairs of [51] opposites, or, as it is technically said, by dichotomy. Now ifthe equation in question had been of the third degree, still admitting of interpretation as such, the mental division must have been threefold in character, and we must have proceeded by a * Should it here be said that the existence of the equation x°= x necessitates also the existence of the equation «7=., which is of the third degree, and then inquired whether that equation does not indicate a process of ¢rzchotomy ; the answer is, that the equation «*=. is not interpretable in the system of logic. For writing it in either of the forms x(I-x)\I1+x) =o, (2) x(1 —*)(-1I-%)=0, (3) we see that its interpretation, if possible at all, must involve that of the factor I+, or of the factor -1—x. The former is not interpretable, because we cannot conceive of the addition of any class x to the universe 1 ; the latter is not ‘interpretable, because the symbol ~—1 is not subject to the law «(1-.~)=0, to which all class symbols are subject. Hence the equation «*=. admits of no in- terpretation analogous to that of the equation «2=«. Were the former equation, however, true independently of the latter, 2,6. were that act of the mind which is denoted by the symbol .v, such that its second repetition should reproduce the result of a single operation, but not its first or mere repetition, it is presumable that we should be able to interpret one of the forms (2), (3), which under the actual conditions of thought we cannot do. There exist operations, known to the mathematician, the law of which may be adequately expressed by the equa- tion «8=x, But they are of a nature altogether foreign to the province of general reasoning. In saying that it is conceivable that the law of thought might have been different from what it is, I mean only that we can frame such an hypothesis, and study its consequences. The possibility of doing this involves no such doctrine as that the actual law of human reason is the product either of chance or of arbitrary will. 56 THEOL AWS, OF TOUGH]. species of ¢vzchotomy, the real nature of which it is impossible — for us, with our existing faculties, adequately to conceive, | but the laws of which we might still investigate as δῆ object of intellectual speculation. 7 16. The law of thought expressed by the equation (1) will, for reasons which are made apparent by the above discussion, be occasionally referred to as the ‘‘law of — duality.” [52] CHAPTER IV me ΠΗ PLVISION.. OF PROPOSITIONS: INTO: THE TWO CRASSES SOF: “SPRIMARY +°AND = 7OF THE CHARACTERISTIC PROPERTIES OF THOSE CLASSES, AND OF THE LAWS OF THE EXPRESSION OF PRIMARY PROPOSITIONS I. THE laws of those mental operations which are con- cerned in the processes of Conception or Imagination having been investigated, and the corresponding laws of the symbols by which they are represented explained, we are led to con- sider the practical application of the results obtained : first, in the expression of the complex terms of propositions ; secondly, in the expression of propositions ; and lastly, in the construction of a general method of deductive analysis. In the present chapter we shall be chiefly concerned with the first of these objects, as an introduction to which it is necessary to establish the following Proposition : PROPOSITION I All logical propositions may be considered as belonging to one or the other of two great classes, to which the respective names of ‘‘ Primary” or ‘‘ Concrete Propositions,” and ‘‘ Secondary” or ‘‘ Abstract Propositions,” may be given. Every assertion that we make may be referred to one or the other of the two following kinds. Either it expresses a relation among ¢hzmgs, or it expresses, or is equivalent to the expression of, a relation among proposztions. An asser- tion respecting the properties of things, or the phanomena which they manifest, or the circumstances in which they are placed, is, properly speaking, the assertion of a relation 57 58 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT among things. To say that ‘‘snow is white,” is for the ends of logic equivalent to saying, that ‘‘snow is a white thing.” An assertion respecting facts or events, their mutual connexion and dependence, is, for the same ends, generally equivalent to the assertion, that such and such propositions con-[53]cerning those events have a certain relation to each other as respects their mutual truth or falsehood. The former class of propositions, relating to ¢izmgs, I call ‘‘ Primary ” ; the latter class, relating to proposztzons, I call ‘‘ Secondary.” The distinction is in practice nearly but not quite co-extensive with the common logical distinction of propositions as cate- gorical or hypothetical. For instance, the propositions, ‘‘ The sun shines,” ‘‘ The earth is warmed,” are primary ; the proposition, ‘‘ If the sun shines the earth is warmed,” is secondary. To say, ‘‘ The sun shines,” is to say, ‘‘ The sun is that which shines,” and it expresses a relation between two classes of things, viz., ‘‘the sun” and ‘‘things which shine.” The secondary pro- ee re a ee position, however, given above, expresses a relation of de- ἢ pendence between the two primary propositions, ‘‘ The sun shines,” and ‘‘ The earth is warmed.” I do not hereby affirm that the relation between these propositions is, like that which exists between the facts which they express, a relation of causality, but only that the relation among the propositions | so implies, and is so implied by, the relation among the ᾿ facts, that it may for the ends of logic be used as ἃ fit representative of that relation. 2. If instead of the proposition, ‘‘ The sun shines,” νοΐ say, ‘It is true that the sun shines,” we then speak not _ directly of things, but of a proposition concerning things, viz., of the proposition, ‘‘ The sun shines.” And, therefore, the proposition in which we thus speak is a secondary one. | Every primary proposition may thus give rise toa secondary proposition, viz., to that secondary proposition which asserts: its truth, or ee its falsehood. It will usually happen, that the particles 76 ether, or, will indicate that a proposition is secondary ; but they do DIVISTON CF FROPOSIFIONS 59 not necessarily imply that such is the case. The proposition, ‘* Animals are either rational or irrational,” is primary. It cannot be resolved into ‘‘ Either animals are rational or animals are irrational,” and it does not therefore express a relation of dependence between the two propositions con- nected together in the latter disjunctive sentence. The particles, ezther, or, are in fact no criterion of the nature of propositions, although it happens that they are more frequently found in secondary propositions. Even [54] the conjunction 27 may be found in primary propositions. ‘‘ Men are, if wise, then temperate,” is an example of the kind. It cannot be resolved into ‘‘If all men are wise, then all men are temperate. ” 3. As it is not my design to discuss the merits or defects of the ordinary division of propositions, I shall simply remark here, that the principle upon which the present classification is founded is clear and definite in its application, that -it involves a real and fundamental distinction in propositions, and that it is of essential importance to the development of ἃ general method of reasoning. Nor does the fact that a primary proposition may be put into a form in which it _ becomes secondary at all conflict with the views here main- tained. For in the case thus supposed, it is not of the things connected together in the primary proposition that any direct account is taken, but only of the proposition itself considered as true or as false. 4. In the expression both of primary and of secondary propositions, the same symbols, subject, as it will appear, to the same laws, will be employed in this work. The difference between the two cases is a difference not of form but of interpretation. In both cases the actual relation which it is the object of the proposition to express will be _ denoted by the sign =. _ In the expression of primary pro- positions, the members thus connected will usually represent the ‘‘terms” of a proposition, or, as they are more particu- larly designated, its subject and predicate. 60 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT PROPOSITION II 5. To deduce a general method, founded upon the enumera- tion of possible varieties, for the expression of any class or collection of things, which may constitute a ‘‘term” of a Primary Proposttion. First, If the class or collection of things to be expressed | is defined only by names or qualities common to all the indi- viduals of which it consists, its expression will consist of a single term, in which the symbols expressive of those names or qualities will be combined without any connecting sign, as if by the algebraic process of multiplication. Thus, if α' represents opaque substances, y polished substances, ¢ stones, we shall have, [55] «v2 =opaque polished stones ; xy(1—2)=opaque polished substances which are not ἢ stones ; a(1—y)(1 —#%)=opaque substances which are not polished, and are not stones ; and so on for any other combination. Let it be observed, that each of these expressions satisfies the same law οἵ duality, as the individual symbols which it contains. Thus, LYS X LYS = LYS ; χγ(1 --- 2) x xy(1 - 2) =xy(1 - 2); and soon. Any such term as the above we shall designate ͵ as a ‘‘class term,” because it expresses a class of things ΩΣ means of the common properties or names of the individual - members of such class, Secondly, If we speak of a collection of things, different — portions of which are defined by different properties, names, or attributes, the expressions for those different portions must — be separately formed, and then connected by the sign +. — But if the collection of which we desire to speak has been ~ formed by excluding from some wider collection a defined portion of its members, the sign — must be prefixed to the symbolical expression of the excluded portion. Respect-_ ones i DIVISION OF PROPOSITIONS 61 ing the use of these symbols some further observations may be added. 6. Speaking generally, the symbol + is the equivalent of the conjunctions ‘‘and,” ‘‘or,” and the symbol —, the equi- valent of the preposition ‘‘except.” Of the conjunctions ‘‘and” and ‘‘or,” the former is usually employed when the collection to be described forms the subject, the latter when it forms the predicate, of a proposition. ‘‘ The scholar and the man of the world desire happiness,” may be taken as an illustration of one of these cases. ‘‘ Things possessing utility are ezther productive of pleasure ov preventive of pain,” may exemplify the other. Now whenever an expression involv- ing these particles presents itself in a primary proposition, it becomes very important to know whether the groups or classes separated in thought by them are intended to be quite distinct from each other and mutually exclusive, or not. Does the expression, ‘‘Scholars and men of the world,” pinclude or exclude those who are both? Does the ex- ill [56]pression ‘‘ Either productive of pleasure or preventive of pain,” include or exclude things which possess both these qualities ? I apprehend that in strictness of meaning the conjunctions ‘‘and,” ‘‘or,” do possess the power of separa- tion or exclusion here referred to; that the formula, ‘‘ All 2’s are either y’s or 2’s,” rigorously interpreted, means, ‘‘ All 2’s me either y’s, but not 2's,” or, ‘‘a’s but not y’s.” But it must at the same time be admitted, that the ‘‘jus et norma loquendi” seems rather to favour an opposite interpretation. The expression, ‘‘ Either y’s or 2’s,” would generally be understood to include things that are y’s and 2’s at the same time, together with things which come under the one, but not the other. Remembering, however, that the symbol + does possess the separating power which has been the sub- ject of discussion, we must resolve any disjunctive expression which may come before us into elements really separated in thought, and then connect their respective expressions by the symbol +. And thus, according to the meaning implied, the ex- 62 PE LAWS Crt aCUCEr pression, ‘‘ Things which are either 1.5 or y’s,” will have two | different symbolical equivalents. If we mean, ‘‘Things — which are #’s, but not y’s, or y’s, but not 1.5. the expres- sion will be x(t -) +y(1 — x); | the symbol x standing for #’s, y for y’s. If, however, we mean, ‘‘ Things which are either 275, or, if notz’s, then y’s,” the expression will be x+y(1 -- x). This expression supposes the admissibility of things which are both 2.5 and y’s at the same time. It might more fully © be expressed in the form ay + x(t —y) +y(1 - x) ; but this expression, on addition of the two first terms, only — reproduces the former one. Let it be observed that the expressions above given satisfy the fundamental law of duality (III. 16). Thus we have ἢ {a(x -9) +9(1- 0) }2=2(1 =) 49(1 τα), {x+y(1 -—x)}P=x+y(1 - x). : It will be seen hereafter, that this is but a particular ξ manifesta-[57]tion of a general law of expressions represent- ing ‘‘classes or collections of things.” 7 7. The results of these investigations may be embodied ᾿ in the following rule of expression. RULE.—E£apress simple names or qualities by the symbols 4 4, V, 8, &c., thetr contraries by τ --- α, τ τον, 1-2, ὅς; classes” of things defined by common names or qualities, by connecting the corresponding symbols as in multiplication ; collections of things, consisting of portions different from each other, by connecting the expressions of those portions by the sign +. ) In particular, let the expression, ‘‘ Either x's or y’s,” be ll pressed by x1—y)+y(1—x), when the classes denoted by δ᾽ and y are exclusive, by x+y(1 —x) when they are not exclusive, ] Similarly let the expression, ‘‘ Etther x's, or y's, or 3's,” bem expressed by x1 -- γ)(1 -- 2)-ΕζΚ -- ῶῦα -- 2) + 2(1 —+\(1-y), 3 DIVISION OF PROPOSITIONS 63 when the classes denoted by x, y, and 2, are designed to be mutually exclusive, by x+y(1I—*)+2(1 —x)\(1—y), when they are not meant to be exclustve, and so on. 8. On this rule of expression is founded the converse rule of interpretation. Both these will be exemplified with, per- haps, sufficient fulness in the following instances. Omitting for brevity the universal subject ‘‘ things,” or ‘‘ beings,” let us assume tena, y— elastic, ¢= metals - and we shall have the following results : ““ Non-elastic metals,” will be expressed by 2(1 —y) ; ‘« Elastic substances with non-elastic metals,” by y+ 4(1—y) ; ‘‘ Hard substances, except metals,” by r—2; ‘* Metallic substances, except those which are neither hard nor elastic,” by —2(1—+)(1 —y), or by 2{1-(1-4)\(1 —y)}, vide (6), Chap. 11. In the last example, what we had really to express was ' ** Metals, except not hard, not elastic, metals.” Con- junctions used between adjectives are usually superfluous, and, therefore, must not be expressed symbolically. Thus, ‘‘ Metals hard and elastic,” is equivalent to ‘‘ Hard elastic metals,” and expressed by xyz. Take next the expression, ‘‘ [lard substances, except those [58] which are metallic and non-elastic, and those which are elastic and non-metallic.” Here the word ¢hose means hard substances, so that the expression really means, Hard Substances except hard substances, metallic, non-elastic, and hard substances non-metallic, elastic; the word except ex- tending to both the classes which follow it. The complete €xpression is x — {x2(1 —y)+xy(1 -2)}; or, x -- x2(1 —y) -- γᾷ -- 2). 9. The preceding Proposition, with the different illustra- tions which have been given of it, is a necessary preliminary to the following one, which will complete the design of the present chapter. , 64 THE LAWS OF ΤΗσΌσ PROPOSITION III To deduce from an examination of thetr possible varieties a general method for the expression of Primary or Concrete Propositions. A primary proposition, in the most general sense, consists of two terms, between which a relation is asserted to exist. These terms are not necessarily single-worded names, but may represent any collection of objects, such as we have been engaged in considering in the previous sections. The mode of expressing those terms is, therefore, comprehended in the general precepts above given, and it only remains to — discover how the relations between the terms are to be ex- — pressed. This will evidently depend upon the nature of the ἢ relation, and more particularly upon the question whether, — in that relation, the terms are understood to be universal or particular, z.e. whether we speak of the whole of that col-— lection of objects to which a term refers, or indefinitely of — the whole or of a part of it, the usual signification of the prelix some,” Suppose that we wish to express a relation of identity — between the two classes, ‘‘ Fixed Stars” and ‘‘ Suns,” 2.4 to express that ‘‘ All fixed stars are suns,” and ‘‘ All sung are fixed stars.” Here, if x stand for fixed stars, and y for suns, we shall have Salas Ss. sani Baa OK id τεὴν ΛΝ ΤΡ ἡ ΠΣ pear ΡΣ ἼΤΩ - oS for the equation required. [59] In the proposition, ‘‘ All fixed stars are suns,” the term ‘‘all fixed stars” would be called the sadject, and— ‘‘suns” the predicate. Suppose that we extend the mean- | ing of the terms sudject and predicate in the following | manner. By sudject let us mean the first term of any. affirmative proposition, z.e. the term which precedes the copula zs or ave ; and by predicate let us agree to mean the second term, z.e. the one which follows the copula; and let. us admit the assumption that either of these may be universal | or particular, so that, in either case, the whole class may οὐλιβριος, κασι ee ee bated) dT 3 ὃ fh DIVISION OF PROPOSITIONS 65 be implied, or only a part of it. Then we shall have the following Rule for cases such as the one in the last example :— 10. RULE.—When both Subject and Predicate of a Proposition are universal, form the separate expressions for them, and connect them by the sign =. This case will usually present itself in the expression of the definitions of science, or of subjects treated after the manner of pure science. Mr. Senior’s definition of wealth affords a good example of this kind, viz.: ‘‘ Wealth consists of things transferable, limited in supply, and either productive of pleasure or preventive of pain.” Before proceeding to express this definition symbolically, it must be remarked that the conjunction and is superfluous. Wealth is really defined by its possession of three properties or qualities, not by its composition out of three classes or collections of objects. Omitting then the conjunction and, let us make w = wealth. < ¢ =things transferable. s =limited in supply. 2 =productive of pleasure. 7 = preventrye, Ol palit. Now it is plain from the nature of the subject, that the expression, ‘‘ Either productive of pleasure or preventive of pain,” in the above definition, is meant to be equivalent to « Fither productive of pleasure; or, if not productive of ‘Pleasure, preventive of pain.” Thus the class of things which the above expression, taken alone, would define, would consist of all things productive [60] of pleasure, to- gether with all things not productive of pleasure, but pre- -ventive of pain, and its symbolical expression would be p+(1-p)r. If then we attach to this expression placed in brackets to denote that both its terms are referred to, the symbols s and ¢ limiting its application to things ‘‘ transferable” and 5 66 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT ‘‘limited in supply,” we obtain the following symbolical equivalent for the original definition, viz. : w=st{p+r(1 -- 2)}. (1) If the expression, ‘‘ Either productive of pleasure or preven- tive of pain,” were intended to point out merely those things which are productive of pleasure without being preventive of pain, (1 —7), or preventive of pain, without being produc- ; tive of pleasure, r(1—p) (exclusion. being made of those things which are both productive of pleasure and preventive of pain), the expression in symbols of the definition would be w = st(p(1-r)+r(1 ~p)}. (2) All this agrees with what has before been more generally stated. ; The reader may be curious to inquire what effect would be produced if we literally translated the expression, ‘‘ Things. productive of pleasure or preventive of pain,” by p+. i making the symbolical equation of the definition to be f w =st(p+r). (3) The answer is, that this expression would be equivalent to (2), with the additional implication that the classes of things” denoted by s¢p and s¢r are quite distinct, so that of things transferable and limited in supply there exist none in the universe which are at the same time both productive of pleasure and preventive of pain. How the full import da any equation may be determined will be explained hereafter, What has been said may show that before attempting to translate our data into the rigorous language of symbols, it is above all things necessary to ascertain the zztended import of the words we are using. But this necessity cannot e regarded as an evil by those who value correctness of [61] thought, and regard the right employment of language ϑ both its instrument and its safeguard. 3 11. Let us consider next the case in which the predicate of the proposition is particular, e.g. ““ All men are mortal. * In this case it is clear that our meaning is, ‘‘ All mena ¢ ee . ἡ DIVISION OF PROPOSITIONS 67 2) some mortal beings,” and we must seek the expression of the predicate, ‘‘some mortal beings.” Represent then by v, a class indefinite in every respect but this, viz., that some of its members are mortal beings, and let x stand for ‘‘ mortal beings,” then will wr represent ‘‘some mortal beings,” Hence if y represent men, the equation sought will be y= Ux. From such considerations we derive the following Rule, for expressing an affirmative universal Dope ΠΝ whose pre- dicate is particular : RULE.—Express as before the subject and the predicate, attach to the latter the indefinite symbol v, and equate the expressions. It is obvious that v is a symbol of the same kind as x, y, &c., and that it is subject to the general law, w=v, or v1—v)=0. Thus, to express the proposition, ‘‘ The planets are either primary or secondary,” we should, according to the rule, pro- ceed thus : Let x represent planets (the subject) ; y =primary bodies ; g= secondary bodies ; then, assuming the conjunction ‘‘or” to separate absolutely the class of ‘‘ primary” from that of ‘‘secondary ” bodies, so far as they enter into our consideration in the proposition given, we find for the equation of the proposition x =o{y(1— 2) +5(1-9)}- (4) It may be worth while to notice, that in this case the de¢eral translation of the premises into the form — x=0U(y +2) (5) [62] would be exactly equivalent, v being an indefinite class symbol. The form (4) is, however, the better, as the ex- pression JU. - 2) +2(1—- 9) 68 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT consists of terms representing classes quite distinct from. each other, and satisfies the fundamental law of duality. If we take the proposition, ‘‘ The heavenly bodies are either suns, or planets or comets,” representing these classes | of things by w, x, y, 2, respectively, its expression, on the supposition that none of the heavenly bodies belong at once to two of the divisions above mentioned, will be w=v{x(1-y)(1-2)+y1—x)\(1 -2)4+2(1 -- α)α -9}} If, however, it were meant to be implied that the heavenly bodies were either suns, or, if not suns, planets, or, if neither. suns nor planets, fixed stars, a meaning which does not exclude the supposition of some of them belonging at once to two or to all three of the divisions of suns, planets, and fixed stars,—the expression required would be ἢ 4 w= of a+ 3(1— x) +2(4 τ 2)(1 -y)}. (6) The above examples belong to the class of ΠΝ not definitions. Indeed the predicates of propositions are usually particular. When this is not the case, either the predicate is a singular term, or we employ, instead of the copula ‘‘is” or ‘‘are,” some form of connexion, which implies that the predicate is to be taken universally. i 12. Consider next the case of universal negative proposi ie tions, e.g. ‘‘ No men are perfect beings.” ἕ Now it is manifest that in this case we do not speak of Ἢ class termed ‘‘no men,” and assert of this class that all its: members are ‘‘ perfect beings.” But we virtually make an Ei 4 ὴ perfect beings.” Thus the true meaning of the proposition | is this: [ “.ΑἹ] men (subject) are (copula) not perfect (predicate) ” ; whence, ify represent ‘‘men,” and x ‘perfect beings,” we shall have Y=U1-, G8 G VX =0Y. Some minor forms are really included under these. Thus, 4 if Y=o, the second form becomes Ἶ Doe and if Y=1 it becomes ὙΠ Ξ 1: DIVISION OF PROPOSTIIONS vl [65] both which forms admit of interpretation. [1 is further to be noticed, that the expressions X and Y, if founded upon a sufficiently careful analysis of the meaning of the ‘“‘terms” of the proposition, will satisfy the fundamental law of duality which requires that we have ‘Xe Xx Ore XC) 556. Fe Y of 1 — 7) Oo: [66] CHAPTER V OF THE FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASON- ING, AND OF THE EXPANSION OR DEVELOPMENT OF EXPRESSIONS INVOLVING LOGICAL SYMBOLS 1. THE previous Chapters of this work have been devoted to” the investigation of the fundamental laws of the operations” of the mind in reasoning ; of their development in the laws of the symbols of Logic ; and of the principles of expression, ' by which that species of propositions called primary may be represented in the language of symbols. These inquiries - have been in the strictest sense preliminary. They form an indispensable introduction to one of the chief objects of this: treatise—the construction of a system or method of Logic upon the basis of an exact summary of the fundamental laws of thought. There are certain considerations touching the nature of this end, and the means of its attainment, to which I deem it necessary here to direct attention. 2. I would remark in the first place that the generality of a method in Logic must very much depend upon the gener-¥ ality of its elementary processes and laws. We have, for instance, in the previous sections of this work investigated, among other things, the laws of that logical process of addition which is symbolized by the sign +. Now thosey laws have been determined from the study of instances, i all of which it has been a necessary condition, that the classes or things added together in thought should be mutually ex- clusive. The expression ++, seems indeed uninterpretable, unless it be assumed that the things represented by x and the things represented by y are entirely separate ; that they em- brace no individuals in common. And conditions analogous to this have been involved in those acts of conception from 72 | | PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING 73 the study of which the laws of the other symbolical opera- tions have been ascertained. Thequestion then arises, whether [67] it is necessary to restrict the application of these sym- bolical laws and processes by the same conditions of inter- pretability under which the knowledge of them was obtained. If such restriction is necessary, it is manifest that no such thing as a general method in Logic is possible. On the other hand, if such restriction is unnecessary, in what light are we to contemplate processes which appear to be uninter- pretable in that sphere of thought which they are designed to aid? These questions do not belong to the science of Logic alone. They are equally pertinent to every developed form of human reasoning which is based upon the employment of a symbolical language. 3. I would observe in the second place, that this apparent failure of correspondency between process and interpretation does not manifest itself in the ovdixary applications of human reason, For no operations are there performed of which the meaning and the application are not seen ; and to most minds it does not suffice that merely formal reasoning should con- nect their premises and their conclusions ; but every step of the connecting train, every mediate result which is estab- lished in the course of demonstration, must be intelligible also. And without doubt, this is both an actual condition and an important safeguard, in the reasonings and discourses of common life. There are perhaps many who would be disposed to extend the same principle to the general use of symbolical language as an instrument of reasoning. It might be argued, that as the laws or axioms which govern the use of symbols are established upon an investigation of those cases only in which interpretation is possible, we have no right to extend their application to other cases in which interpretation is impossible or doubtful, even though (as should be admitted) such application is employed in the intermediate steps of demonstration only. Were this objection conclusive, it must be acknowledged that slight advantage would accrue from 74 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT the use of a symbolical method in Logic. Perhaps that ad-— vantage would be confined to the mechanical gain of em- ploying short and convenient symbols in the place of more ' cumbrous ones. But the objection itself is fallacious. What- — ever our ὦ priord anticipations might be, it is an unquestion- | able fact that the validity of a conclusion arrived at [68] by any symbolical process of reasoning, does not depend upon our ability to interpret the formal results which have pre- sented themselves in the different stages of the investigation. There exist, in fact, certain general principles relating to the use of symbolical methods, which, as pertaining to the particular subject of Logic, I shall first state, and I shall | then offer some remarks upon the nature and upon the grounds of their claim to acceptance. 4. The conditions of valid reasoning, by the aidof symbols, are— Ist, [hata fixed interpretation be assigned to the symbols © employed in the expression of the data; and that the laws — of the combination of those symbols be correctly determined from that interpretation. 2nd, That the formal processes of solution or demonstra- 4 tion be conducted throughout in obedience to all the laws _ determined as above, without regard to the question of the interpretability of the particular results obtained. 3rd, That the final result be interpretable in form, and that it be actually interpreted in accordance with that system © of interpretation which has been employed in the expres- ἢ sion of the data. Concerning these principles, the following — observations may be made. 5. The necessity of a fixed interpretation of the symbols — has already been sufficiently dwelt upon (II. 3). ΤΠ necessity that the fixed result should be in such a form as % to admit of that interpretation being applied, is founded on ¥ the obvious principle, that the use of symbols is a means © towards an end, that end being the knowledge of some in- | telligible fact or truth. And that this end may be attained, ~ the final result which expresses the symbolical conclusion 4 PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING 75 must be in an interpretable form. It is, however, in con- nexion with the second of the above general principles or conditions (V. 4), that the greatest difficulty is likely to be felt, and upon this point a few additional words are necessary. I would then remark, that the principle in question may be considered as resting upon a general law of the mind, the knowledge of which is not given to us ὦ priorz, 2. 6. antecedently to [69] experience, but is derived, like the knowledge of the other laws of the mind, from the clear manifestation of the general principle in the particular in- stance. A single example of reasoning, in which symbols are employed in obedience to laws founded upon their interpretation, but without any sustained reference to that interpretation, the chain of demonstration conducting us. through intermediate steps which are not interpretable, to a final result which is interpretable, seems not only to establish the validity of the particular application, but to make known to us the general law manifested therein. No accumulation of instances can properly add weight to such evidence. It may furnish us with clearer conceptions of that common element of truth upon which the application of the principle depends, and so prepare the way for its reception. It may, where the immediate force of the evidence is not felt, serve as a verification, a posterzorz, of the practical validity of the principle in question. But this does not affect the position affirmed, viz., that the general principle must be seen in the particular instance,—seen to be general in application as well as true in the special example. The employment of the uninterpretable symbol ,/—1, in the intermediate processes of trigonometry, furnishes an illustra- tion of what has been said. I apprehend that there is no mode of explaining that application which does not covertly assume the very principle in question. But that principle, though not, as I conceive, warranted by formal reasoning based upon other grounds, seems to deserve a place among those axiomatic truths which constitute, in some sense, the 76 IME LAWS OF LHOUGAT foundation of the possibility of general knowledge, and which may properly be regarded as expressions of the mind’s own laws and constitution. ; 6. The following is the mode in which the principle above. stated will be applied inthe present work. It has been seen, that any system of propositions may be expressed by equa- tions involving symbols x, y, z, which, whenever interpreta- tion is possible, are subject to laws identical in form with the laws of a system of quantitative symbols, susceptible only of the values 0 and 1 (II. 15). But as the formal processes of reasoning depend only upon the laws of the symbols, and not upon the nature of their interpretation, we are permitted to treat the above symbols, [70] x, y, 2, as if they were quantitative symbols of the kind above described. We may an fact lay aside the logical interpretation of the symbols in the given equation ; convert them into quantitative symbols, susceptible only of the values 0 and τ, perform upon them as such all the requisite processes of solution; and finally restore to them their logical interpretation. And this is the mode of procedure which will actually be adopted, though it will be deemed unnecessary to restate in every instance the nature of the transformation employed. The processes to which the symbols x, y, 2, regarded as quanti- tative and of the species above described, are subject, are. not limited by those conditions of thought to which they would, if performed upon purely logical symbols, be subject, and a freedom of operation is given to us in the use of them, without which the inquiry after a general method in Logic: would be a hopeless quest. Now the above system of processes would conduct us to. no intelligible result, unless the final equations resulting: therefrom were in a form which should render their inter- pretation, after restoring to the symbols their logical signi- ficance, possible. There exists, however, a general method of reducing equations to such a form, and the remainder of this chapter will be devoted to its consideration. I shall say little concerning the way in which the method renders in- Me RINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING 77 terpretation possible,—this point being reserved for the next chapter,—but shall chiefly confine myself here to the mere process employed, which may be characterized as a process of ‘‘development.” As introductory to the nature of this process, it may be proper first to make a few observations. 7. Suppose that we are considering any class of things with reference to this question, viz., the relation in which its members stand as to the possession or the want of a certain property x As every individual in the proposed class either possesses or does not possess the property in question, we may divide the class into two portions, the former consisting of those individuals which possess, the latter of those which do not possess, the property. This possibility of dividing in thought the whole class into two constituent portions, is antecedent to all knowledge of the constitution of the class derived from any other source ; of [71] which knowledge the effect can only be to inform us, more or less precisely, to what further conditions the portions of the class which possess and which do not possess the given property are subject. Suppose, then, such knowledge is to the following effect, viz., that the members of that portion which possess the property %, possess also a certain property 2, and that these conditions united are a sufficient definition of them. We may then represent that portion of the original class by the expression wx (II. 6). If, further, we obtain information that the members of the original class which do not possess the property x, are subject to a condition v, and are thus defined, it is clear, that those members will be re- presented by the expression v(1—*). Hence the class in its totality will be represented by ux +0(1 — x); which may be considered as a general developed form for the expression of any class of objects considered with refer- ence to the possession or the want of a given property +. The general form thus established upon purely logical grounds may also be deduced from distinct considerations of 78 LHE LAWS CF THOUGHT formal law, applicable to the symbols +, y, 2, equally in — their logical and in their quantitative interpretation already ~ referred.to (V. 6). | ὃ, Definitton.—Any algebraic expression involving a sym-_ bol x is termed a function of x, and may be represented — under the abbreviated general form /(v). Any expression involving two symbols, rand γ, is similarly termed a function | of x and y, and may be represented under the general form | _ f(x, v), and so on for any other case. q Thus the form /(%) would aud represent any of the - following functions, viz., +, 1 — +, —— =, &e.; ; and /(4, v) would | equally represent any of the forms ζ.-Ἐ », x—2y, ΣΦ, On the same principles of notation, if in any function £(2), : we change # into 1, the result will be expressed by the form f/(1); if in the same function we change + into ο, the | result will be expressed oe in form /(0). Thus, if f(x) ari represent the [72] function © -- Fe aCe will se ce and /(0) will represent = 9. Definition.—Any function f(x), in which x is a logical — symbol, or a symbol of quantity susceptible only of the values 0 and 1, is said to be developed, when it is reduced — to the form az+0(1—+), a and ὁ being so determined as to ~ make the result equivalent to the function from which it | was derived. | This definition assumes, that it is possible to represent — any function /(v) in the form supposed. The assumption ~ is vindicated in the following Proposition. | PROPOSITION [Ι 10. Lo develop any function f(x) in which x ts a logical i symbol. : By the principle which has been asserted in this chapter, ᾿ | | } ἢ ; | ἢ 4 ‘ 4 “PRINCIPLES OF SVMBOLICAL REASONING 79 it is lawful to treat x as a quantitative symbol, susceptible only of the values o and I, Assume then, f(x) =ax + b(1 - x), and making +=1, we have Wit. Again, in the same equation making +=0, we have flo) =0. Hence the values of ὦ and ὁ are determined, and substi- tuting them in the first equation, we have Ax) =f 1) + flor — %) 5 (1) as the development sought.* The second member of the equa-['73]tion adequately represents the function /(*), whatever the form of that function may be. For + regarded as a quantitative symbol admits only of the values 0 and 1, and for each of these values the development 7 faye + flo - α), assumes the same value as the function /(*). * To some it may be interesting to remark, that the development of /(x) obtained in this chapter, strictly holds, in the logical system, the place of the expansion of f(x) in ascending powers of « in the system of ordinary algebra. Thus it may be obtained by introducing into the expression of Taylor’s well- known theorem, viz. : : ᾿ .,1.)-- Χο) -)7(ο)α +0) ἘΠ Ὁ ᾿ ἄς. (1) the condition x(1 -.«)=0, whence we find 27=, «=x, &c., and But making in (1), x=1, we get flay=fl0) +7"(0)4 + FOF + 8c. | whence γι). LO) + Be. = f(1)- /(0), ᾿ and (2) becomes, on substitution, S(x*)=S(0) +t SO) - ,(ο) 4 - =f (1)*+ Χο) -- +), the form in question. This demonstration in supposing /(*) to be developable in a series of ascending powers of « is less general than the one in the text. 7 80 THE TAWS OF THOUGHT As an illustration, let it be required to develop the ad Here, when +=1, we find Αυτξ, and function : I _ a when +=0, we find TO) == , or I. Hence the expression required is ἜΣ AEE =—-X+1-X; T+2x 5 and this equation is satisfied for each of the values of which the symbol +x is susceptible. | PROPOSITION II To expand or develop a function tnvolving any number of logical symbols. Let us begin with the case in which there are two sym- bole 2 ang -y, and let us represent the ‘function. to be developed by /(%, 1). First, considering /(%, vy) as a function οἱ + alone, and expanding it by the general theorem (1), we have Λα, Y)=K it, YX +N; YI -- &) 5 (2) [74] wherein /(1, y) represents what the proposed function — becomes, when in it for x we write 1, and /(o, y) what | the said function becomes, when in it for x we write oO. 3 Now, taking the coefficient /(1, v), and regarding it asm a function of y, and expanding it accordingly,. we have ; ἢ Κι, )ξλι, Iy+fA1, o)(1 ἜΝ (3 ᾿ wherein /(1, 1) represents what /(1, γ᾽) becomes when y is made equal to 1, and /(1, 0) what /(1, v) becomes whe 1 y is made equal to o. 4 In like manner, the coefficient /(0, y) gives by expansion, KO, γ)-Άο, τὴν +flo, ογ)( -y). (4) Substitute in (2) for (1, 7), 7χἴο, v), their values given in (3) and (4), and we have ἢ Kx; Y) =f(1, τ)ὰν + fl, ο)χᾷι πον ἡ 1)(1 -- “)» ἥ ἘΛο, χα -- )α -), 6) πὰς PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING 81 for the expansion required. Here /(1, 1) represents what ΠῚ v) becomes when we make therein r=1, y=1; /(1, 0) represents what /(%, vy) becomes when we make therein “τι, y=0, and so on for the rest. I— Thus, if f(x, v) represent the function : τ we find fa, )=2, flt,0)=2=0, flo, 1)=2, Ao, 0)=1, whence the expansion of the given function is ay +on(t —y) + U(r ayy +(1-a)(1 -9). It will in the next chapter be seen that the forms - and = the former of which is known to mathematicians as the symbol of indeterminate quantity, admit, in such ex- pressions as the above, of a very important logical inter- pretation. Suppose, in the next place, that we have three symbols in the function to be expanded, which we may represent under the general form /(4, y, 2). Proceeding as before, we get [75] A, 9; 2) -- 7, τ, raya t+ f(1, τ, ογαγᾷι - 2) +f/(1, 0, 1)a(r—y)2 +f(1, 0, o)x(1 —y)(1 —2)+f(o, 1, 1)(1 -- x)yz +/(0, τ, 0 -- αὐγᾷ -- 5) +f/(0, 0, 1)(1 - αλὰ ~y)s +f(0, 0, ολ(ι -- α)ίι —y)(1 -- δ), in which /(1, 1, 1) represents what the function /(%, y, 2) be- comes when we make therein r=1, y=1, 2=1, and so on for the rest. _ 11. It is now easy to see the general law which determines the expansion of any proposed function, and to reduce the method of effecting the expansion to a rule. But before proceeding to the expression of such a rule, it will be con- venient to premise the following observations :— _ Each form of expansion that we have obtained consists of certain terms, into which the symbols x, y, ἅς. enter, ‘multiplied by coefficients, into which those symbols do not 6 [ rl 82 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT enter. Thus the expansion of /() consists of two terms, + and 1—x, multiplied by the coefficients f(1) and /(0) τες! spectively. And the expansion of /(@%, 7) consists of the four terms xy, *(1—y), (1—*)y, and (1—*)(1-y), multi- plied by the coefficients /(1, 1), (1, ©), F(O, 1), Χο, 0), τοῦ spectively. The terms x, I—4, in the former case, and the terms xy, +(1—y), &c., in the latter, we shall call the con- stituents of the expansion. It is evident that they are in form independent of the form of the function to be expanded, q Of the constituent xy, x and y are termed the factors. } The general rule of development will therefore consist o ᾿ two parts, the first of which will relate to the formation of the constituents of the expansion, the second to the de- termination of their respective coefficients. It is as follows ist. 70 expand any function of the symbols x,y, 2.—Form a series of constituents in the following manner: Let the: first constituent be the product of the symbols; change in this product any symbol z into 1 -- 5, for the second con- stituent. Then in both these change any other symbol y into 1—y, for two more constituents. Then in the four constituents thus obtained change any other symbol » int 0 1 —x, for four new constituents, and so on until the number of possible changes is exhausted. _ | andly. To find the coefficient of any constituent.—lf that con-['76]stituent involves vas a factor, change in the original function ¢ into 1; but if it involves τ τας a factor, change in the original function 4 into o. Apply the same rule with reference to the symbols y, 2, &c.: the final calculated’ value of the function thus transformed will be the coefficie ἰ sought. | δ The sum of the constituents, multiplied each by its re- spective coefficient, will be the expansion required. | 12. It is worthy of observation, that a function may be developed with reference to symbols which it does not explicitly contain. Thus if, proceeding according to the rule, we seek to develop the function 1 -- 2, with referen 8 to the symbols # and y, we have, a a Ὡς ey -PRINCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL REASONING 83 When +=1 and y=I the given function =o. ἄπ oe ») ) τ Ὁ» Ὄπ ΘΙ FoF i) 9 τεὸν ἰς Ma yh ee -- ὸ ” ») τ S Whence the development is ! I—x=oxy +0x(1 -y) + ( -- α)ν Ἐ{ -- α)ᾷ -- )); and this is a true development. The addition of the terms (1 —x)y and (1 —%)(1—y) produces the function 1 -- 1. The symbol 1 thus developed according to the rule, with respect to the symbol 4%, gives X+1-X. Developed with respect to x and y, it gives ay κα -- )) + (α —x)y ἘΚ -- x(t -- 3). Similarly developed with respect to any set of symbols, it produces a series consisting of all possible constituents of those symbols. 13. A few additional remarks concerning the nature of the general expansions may with propriety be added. Let us take, for illustration, the general theorem (5), which presents the type of development for functions of two logical symbols. In the first place, that theorem is perfectly true and in- telligible when x and y are quantitative symbols of the species considered in this chapter, whatever algebraic form may be assigned to the function /(%, y), and it may there- fore be intelligibly em-['77]ployed in any stage of the pro- cess of analysis intermediate between the change of inter- pretation of the symbols from the logical to the quantitative system above referred to, and the final restoration of the logical interpretation. Secondly. The theorem is perfectly true and intelligible when # and y are logical symbols, provided that the form of the function χα, v) is such as to represent a class or col- lection of things, in which case the second member is always logically interpretable. For instance, if /(4, y) represent the | function 1 —7+zy, we obtain on applying the theorem 84 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT 1-x+ay=xy+ox(1 —y)+(1-x)y+(1 ~ x1 -y), =xy+(1-x)y+(1-x)(1-y), and this result is intelligible and true. . Thus we may regard the theorem as true and intelligible 1 for quantitative symbols of the species above described, — always; for logical symbols, always when interpretable, Whensoever therefore it is employed in this work it must be | understood that the symbols +, y are quantitative and of the particular species referred to, if the expansion obtained is not interpretable. But though the expansion is not always immediately interpretable, it always conducts us at once to results which | are interpretable. Thus the expression r—y gives on de-— velopment the form x(t —y) — y(1 4) . which is not generally interpretable. We cannot take, in thought, from the class of things which are 1.5 and not y’s, the class of things which are y’s and not 2#’s, because the latter class is not contained in the former. But if the form — 4—y presented itself as the first member of an equation, © of which the second member was Oo, we should have on development x(t -- )) -- (1 -x)=0., Now it will be shown in the next chapter that the above equation, + and y being regarded as quantitative and of the species described, is resolvable at once into the two equations x(1-y)=0, y(1-x)=0, and these equations are directly interpretable in Logic when lo-[78]gical interpretations are assigned to the symbols 4 and y. And it may be remarked, that though functions do not necessarily become interpretable upon development, yet equations are always reducible by this process to inter-~ pretable forms. i 14. The following Proposition establishes some important properties of constituents. In its enunciation the symbol ¢_ is employed to represent indifferently any constituent of | BAIVNCIPLES OF SYMBOLICAL KEASONING 85 an expansion. Thus if the expansion is that of a function of two symbols x and y, ¢ represents any of the four forms ay, (1—y), (1—*yy, and (1—*x)(1—y). Where it is neces- sary to represent the constituents of an expansion by single symbols, and yet to distinguish them from each other, the distinction will be marked by suffixes. Thus ¢, might be employed to represent ἅν, ¢, to represent 4(1 —y), and so on, PROPOSITION III Any single constituent ἐ of an expansion satisfies the law of duality whose expression ts “#1 -t)=0, The product of any two distinct constituents of an expansion ts equal to 0, and the sum of all the constituents ts equal toji. ist. Consider the particular constituent xy, We have Ἂν Mey ee But =, y?=y, by the fundamental law of class symbols ; hence xy X xy = XY. Or representing xy by Ζ, txt=t, or “(1 ἢ =0. Similarly the constituent +(1—¥) satisfies the same law. For we have Coe (Uy) εν {x(1 —y)}2=a2(1-y), or t(1—-Z)=0. Now every factor of every constituent is either of the form «or of the form 1—%. Hence the square of each factor is equal to that [79] factor, and therefore the square of the product of the factors, z.e. of the constituent, is equal to the constituent ; wherefore ¢ representing any constituent, we have C= or &1—t)=0. 2andly. The product of any two constituents iso. This | | | 86 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT is evident from the general law of the symbols expressed by ~ the equation #(1—*)=0; for whatever constituents in the 4 same expansion we take, there will be at least one factor ~ x in the one, to which will correspond a factor I1—x in the ¥ other. Ἷ 3rdly. The sum of all the constituents of an expansion is unity. This is evident from addition of the two constituents } x and 1—4, or of the four constituents, xy, x(1—y), (1-4), ' (1—2x)(1-y). But it is also, and more generally, proved by 4 expanding 1 in terms of any set of symbols (V. 12). The ' constituents in this case are formed as usual, and all the ᾿ coefficients are unity. j 1s. With the above Proposition we may connect the ~ following. PROPOSITION IV If V represent the sum of any sertes of constituents, the 3 separate coefficients of which are τ, then is the condition — satisfied, ! Κα -- Κ)γΞο. Let ¢,, 4%. . . ¢, be the constituents in question, then Vee ee. Squaring both sides, and observing that 7?=4,, 4,4, =0,| &c., we have V+=4,+4, oe pe ἜΖ: whence Therefore [80] CHAPTER VI OF THE GENERAL INTERPRETATION OF LOGICAL EQUA- TIONS, AND THE RESULTING ANALYSIS OF PROPOSI- TIONS. ALSO, OF THE CONDITION OF INTERPRETA- BILITY OF LOGICAL FUNCTIONS 1. IT has been observed that the complete expansion of any function by the general rule demonstrated in the last chapter, involves two distinct sets of elements, viz., the constituents of the expansion, and their coefficients. I propose in the present chapter to inquire, first, into the interpretation of constituents, and afterwards into the mode in which that interpretation is modified by the coefficients with which they are connected. ne: terms. logical equation,” τ logical function,” :&e., will be employed generally to denote any equation or function involving the symbols x, vy, &c., which may present itself either in the expression of a system of premises, or in the train of symbolical results which intervenes between the premises and the conclusion. If that function or equation is in a form not immediately interpretable in Logic, the symbols x, vy, &c., must be regarded as quantitative symbols of the species described in previous chapters (II. 15), (V. 6), as satisfying the law, x(I — x) =0. By the problem, then, of the interpretation of any such logical function or equation, is meant the reduction of it to a form in which, when logical values are assigned to the symbols +, y, &c., it shall become interpretable, together with the resulting interpretation. These conventional de- finitions are in accordance with the general principles for the 87 88 THe LAWS OF HOGG. conducting of the method of this treatise, laid down in the previous chapter. [81] PROPOSITION I 2. The constituents of the expansion of any function of the logical symbols x, y, &c., are interpretable, and represent the several exclusive divisions of the universe of discourse, formed by the predication and dental in every possible way of the gualities denoted by the symbols x, y, &e. | For greater distinctness of conception, let it be supposed that the function expanded involves two symbols # and y, with reference to which the expansion has been effected, We have then the following constituents, viz. : xy, x(1-y), (1-x)y, (1-x)(1-y). : Of these it is evident, that the first ry represents that class of objects which at the same time possess both the elementary qualities expressed by x and y, and that the second 4(1 ~yy represents the class possessing the property x, but not the property y. In like manner the third constituent represents the class of objects which possess the property represented by y, but not that represented by x; and the fourth con- stituent (I—+)(1—y) represents that class of objects the members of which possess neither of the qualities in question, | Thus the constituents in the case just considered represent all the four classes of objects which can be described by affirmation and denial of the properties expressed by x and y, Those classes are distinct from each other. No member of one is a member of another, for each class possesses some | property or quality contrary to a property or quality possessed by any other class. Again, these classes together make up the universe, for there is no object which may not be de- scribed by the presence or the absence of a proposed quality, and thus each individual thing in the universe may be re- ferred to some one or other of the four classes made by the possible combination of the two given classes x and y, and their contraries. | | | | OF INTERPRETATION 89 The remarks which have here been made with reference to the constituents of /(x, v) are perfectly general in char- acter. The constituents of any expansion represent classes —those classes [82] are mutually distinct, through the possession of contrary qualities, and they together make up the universe of discourse. 3. These properties of constituents have their expression in the theorems demonstrated in the conclusion of the last chapter, and might thence have been deduced. From the fact that every constituent satisfies the fundamental law of the individual symbols, it might have been conjectured that each constituent would represent a class, From the fact that the product of any two constituents of an expansion vanishes, it might have been concluded that the classes they represent are mutually exclusive. Lastly, from the fact that the sum of the constituents of an expansion is unity, it might have been inferred, that the classes which they represent, together make up the universe. 4. Upon the laws of constituents and the mode of their interpretation above determined, are founded the analysis and the interpretation of logical equations. That all such equations admit of interpretation by the theorem of develop- ment has already been stated. I propose here to investigate the forms of possible solution which thus present themselves in the conclusion of a train of reasoning, and to show how those forms arise. Although, properly speaking, they are but manifestations of a single fundamental type or principle of expression, it will conduce to clearness of apprehension if the minor varieties which they exhibit are presented separately to the mind. The forms, which are three in number, are as follows: FORM I 5. The form we shall first consider arises when any logical equation 7 =0 is developed, and the result, after resolution into its component equations, is to be interpreted. The function is. supposed to involve the logical symbols 7, y, &c., go THE LAWS OF THOUGHT ἷ in combinations which are not fractional. Fractional com-_ binations indeed only arise in the class of problems which — will be considered when we come to speak of the third of the forms of solution above referred to. PROPOSITION II | To interpret the logical equation V =o. For simplicity let us suppose that V involves but twall sym-[83]bols, x and y, and let us represent the development οὔ the given equation by axy + bx(1—y)+e(1 —x)y+a(1 -x)1-y)=0; Ἵ a, ὦ, c, and d being definite numerical constants. Now, suppose that any coefficient, as a, does not vanish, — . Then multiplying each side of the equation by the constituent ay, to which that coefficient is attached, we have axy =0, whence, as a does not vanish, Eso). : and this result is quite independent of the nature of the other coefficients of the expansion. Its interpretation, on assign- ing to x and y their logical significance, is ‘‘ No individuals belonging at once to the class represented by x, and the laa represented by y, exist.” But if the coefficient a does vanish, the term ary does rofl appear in the development (1), and, therefore, the equatio 4+y =O cannot thence be deduced. | In like manner, if the coefficient ὁ does not vanish, we have. x(1 -- γ) ΞΞ ο, which admits of the interpretation, ‘‘ There are no individuals which at the same time belong to the class x, and do not belong to the class y.” Either of the above interpretations may, however, as wil subsequently be shown, be exhibited in a different form. The sum of the distinct interpretations thus obtained from i OF INTERPRETATION ΟἹ | the several terms of the expansion whose coefficients do not vanish, will constitute the complete interpretation of the equation V=o. The analysis is essentially independent of | the number of logical symbols involved in the function V, -and the object of the proposition will, therefore, in all in- stances, be attained by the following Rule :— RULE.—Develop the function V, and equate to Ο every con- stituent whose coefficient does not vanish. The interpretation of these results collectively will constitute the interpretation of the given equation. [84] 6. Let us take as an example the definition of **clean beasts,” laid down in the Jewish law, viz., ‘‘ Clean beasts are those which both divide the hoof and chew the cud,” and let us assume “= cleat peasts ; y =beasts dividing the hoof ; = beasts chewing the cud. Then the given proposition will be represented by the equation which we shall reduce to the form x—-ys=0, and seek that form of interpretation to which the present method leads, Fully. developing the first member, we have oxys + xy(1 - 2) +x«(1 -—y)s+ x(t -- )( - 2) τᾷ - αὐτο - αν ~2) 4 0(1 - αὐὰ - γ)ε τοί - α)α -χι - 9). Whence the terms, whose coefficients do not vanish, give νι: -- το, x2(1-y)=0, x(1-y)(1-2z)=0, (1 -- σ)γετξο. These equations express a denial of the existence of certain classes of objects, viz. : _ Ist. Of beasts which are clean, and divide the hoof, but do not chew the cud. 2nd. Of beasts which are clean, and chew the cud, but do not divide the hoof. : ; x= YZ, 92 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT 3rd. Of beasts which are clean, and neither divide the hoof nor chew the cud. Ath. Of beasts which divide the hoof, and chew the cud, | and are not clean. Now all these several denials are really involved in the original proposition. And conversely, if these denials be granted, the original proposition will follow as a necessary consequence. They are, in fact, the separate elements of that proposition. Every primary proposition can thus be resolved into a series of denials of the existence of certain defined classes of things, and may, from that system of denials, be itself reconstructed. It might here be asked, — how it is possible to make an assertative pro-[85]position out of a series of denials or negations? From what source is the positive element derived? I answer, that the mind assumes the existence of a universe not ὦ 271071 as a fact in- dependent of experience, but either a posteriori as a deduc- tion from experience, or hypothetically as a foundation of the possibility of assertive reasoning. Thus from the Proposition, “Ὁ There are no men who are not fallible,” which is a negation or denial of the existence of ‘‘ infallible men,” it may be in- ferred either hypothetically, ‘‘ All men (if men exist) are fallible,” or absolutely, (experience having assured us of the existence of the race), ‘‘ All men are fallible.” The form in which conclusions are exhibited by the method of this Proposition may be termed the form of ‘‘ Single or Conjoint Denial.” FORM II 7. As the previous form was derived from the development and interpretation of an equation whose second member is 0, the present form, which is supplementary to it, will be derived from the development and interpretation of an equation whose second member is 1. It is, however, readily suggested by the analysis of the previous Proposition. Thus in the example last discussed we deduced from the equation Xx -yZ=0 OF INTERPRETATION 93 the conjoint denial of the existence of the classes represented by the constituents xy(t—s), x2(1-y), a(1—y)(x—2), (1 -- αὐνε, whose coefficients were not equal to 0. It follows hence that the remaining constituents represent classes which make up the universe. Hence we shall have ays (1 - αἰνὰ - 2) + (1 - α)α - 7) + (1 -- αὐ --)( 5) =F. This is equivalent to the affirmation that all existing things belong to some one or other of the following classes, viz. : Ist. Clean beasts both dividing the hoof and chewing the cud. [86] 2nd. Unclean beasts dividing the hoof, but not chew- ing the cud. 3rd. Unclean beasts chewing the cud, but not dividing the hoof. 4th. Things which are neither clean beasts, nor chewers of the cud, nor dividers of the hoof. _ This form of conclusion may be termed the form of ‘‘ Single or Disjunctive Affirmation, ”’—single when but one constituent appears in the final equation ; disjunctive when, as above, more constituents than one are there found. Any equation, VY =o, wherein V satisfies the law of duality, may also be made to yield this form of interpretation by re- ducing it to the form 1—V=1, and developing the first member. The case, however, is really included in the next general form. Both the previous forms are of slight import- ance compared with the following one. FORM III 8. In the two preceding cases the functions to be de- veloped were equated to oand I respectively. In the present case I shall suppose the corresponding function equated to any logical symbol w. We are then to endeavour to inter- pret the equation V=w, V being a function of the logical symbols x, v, z, &c. In the first place, however, I deem it 94 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT a necessary to show how the equation V=w, or, as it will usually present itself, w= V, arises. Let us resume the definition of ‘‘clean beasts,” employed in the previous examples, viz., ‘‘Clean beasts are those which both divide the hoof and chew the cud,” and suppose it required to determine the relation in which ‘‘ beasts chew- ing the cud” stand to ‘‘clean beasts” and ‘‘ beasts dividing the hoof.” The equation expressing the given proposition is aes and our object will be accomplished if we can determine ¢ as an interpretable function of x and y. . Now treating x, y, as symbols of quantity subject to a peculiar law, we may deduce from the above equation, by solution, [87] But this equation is not at present in an interpretable ἷ form. If we can reduce it to such a form it will furnish the relation required. | On developing the second member of the above equation, we have a= ay + a(t -y)+o(1 -αὴν τα τὶ x)(1 τ and it will be shown hereafter (Prop. III.) that this admits of the following interpretation : | ‘* Beasts which chew the cud consist of all clean beasts (which also divide the hoof), together with an indefinite re- mainder (some, none, or all) of unclean beasts which do not divide the hoof.” ; 9. Now the above is a particular example of a problem of the utmost generality in Logic, and which may thus be stated :—‘‘ Given any logical equation connecting the sym- bols x, y, , w, required an interpretable expression for the relation of the class represented by w to the classes repre- sented by the other symbols x, y, z, &c.” , The solution of this problem consists in all cases in deter- Se ee ae eee ἐστὸν OF INTERPRETATION 95 mining, from the equation gzven, the expression of the above symbol w, in terms of the other symbols, and rendering that expression interpretable by development. Now the equation given is always of the first degree with respect to each of the symbols involved. The required expression for w can therefore always be found. In fact, if we develop the given equation, whatever its form may be with respect to w, we obtain an equation of the form Ew+ E'(1 -w)=o9, (1) ΠΕ and E’ being functions of the remaining symbols. From the above we have '—(F' —-E)w. Therefore Fos δ να aE SH @) and expanding the second member by the rule of develop- -ment, it will only remain to interpret the result in logic by the next proposition. / [88] If the fraction ἘΠΕ has common factors in its numerator and denominator, we are not permitted to reject them, unless they are mere numerical constants. For the symbols x, vy, &c., regarded as quantitative, may admit of such values 0 and 1 as to cause the common factors to be- come equal to 0, in which case the algebraic rule of reduction fails. This is the case contemplated in our remarks on the failure of the algebraic axiom of division (II. 14). To ex- press the solution in the form (2), and without attempting to perform any unauthorized reductions, to interpret the re- sult by the theorem of development, is a course strictly in accordance with the general principles of this treatise. If the relation of the class expressed by 1—w to the other classes, x, y, &c. is required, we deduce from (1), in like manner as above, es E-£E” to the interpretation of which also the method of the follow- ing Proposition is applicable : 70 96 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT PROPOSITION III 10. 70 determine the interpretation of any logical equation of the formw=V, in which τὸ ts a class symbol, and V a function of other class symbols quite unlimited in rts form. Let the second member of the above equation be fully expanded. Each coefficient of the result will belong to some one of the four classes, which, with their respective interpretations, we proceed to discuss. ist. Let the coefficient be 1. As this is the symbol of the universe, and as the product of any two class symbols represents those individuals which are found in both classes, any constituent which has unity for its coefficient must be interpreted without limitation, z.e. the whole of the class which it represents is implied. 2nd. Let the coefficient be 0. As in Logic, equally with Arithmetic, this is the symbol of Nothing, no part of the class [89] represented by the constituent to which it is pre- fixed must be taken. 3rd. Let the coefficient be of the form τ Now, as in : : O : : Arithmetic, the symbol a represents an zzdefinite number, except when otherwise determined by some special circum- stance, analogy would suggest that in the system of this work the same symbol should represent an zzdefintte class. That this is its true meaning will be made clear from the following example : Let us take the Proposition, ‘‘ Men not mortal do not exist” ; represent this Proposition by symbols ; and seek, in obedience to the laws to which those symbols have been proved to be subject, a reverse definition of ‘‘ mortal beings,” in terms:of-* men,” Now if we represent ‘‘men” by y, and ‘‘ mortal beings,” by x, the Proposition, ‘‘ Men who are not mortals do not exist,” will be expressed by the equation WI - x)=0, OF INTERPRETATION 97 from which we are to seek the value of x Now the above equation gives Yryx=O, OT yx=y. Were this an ordinary algebraic equation, we should, in the next place, divide both sides of it by y. But it has been remarked in Chap. II. that the operation of division cannot be performed with the symbols with which we are now engaged. Our resource, then, is to express the operation, and develop the result by the method of the preceding chapter. We have, then, first, x=, hg and, expanding the second member as directed, 12) χε AE sy): This implies that mortals (7) consist of all men (y), together with such a remainder of beings which are not men (1 -- 7), as will be indicated by the coefficient 5° Now let us inquire what [90] remainder of ‘‘not men” is implied by the premiss. It might happen that the remainder included all the beings who are not men, or it might include only some of them, and not others, or it might include none, and any one of these assumptions wculd be in perfect accordance with our premiss. In other words, whether those beings which are not men are aé/, or some, or none, of them mortal, the truth of the premiss which virtually asserts that all men are mortal, will be equally unaffected, and therefore the ex- ἜΣ Ὁ ae pression 5 here indicates that all, some, or none of the class to whose expression it is affixed must be taken. Although the above determination of the significance of the symbol = is founded only upon the examination of a particular case, yet the principle involved in the demonstra- tion is general, and there are no circumstances under which 7 98 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT the symbol can present itself to which the same mode of | | "ἢ : analysis is inapplicable. We may properly term 5 an in~ definite class symbol, and may, if convenience should require, — replace it by an uncompounded symbol v, subject to the fundamental law, v(1 —v) =O. : 4th. It may happen that the coefficient of a constituent | in an expansion does not belong to any of the previous — cases, To ascertain its true interpretation when this happens, — it will be necessary to premise the following theorem : 11. THEOREM.—J/f a function V, intended to represent any class or collection of objects, w, be expanded, and 17 the numerical coefficient, a, of any constituent in tts development, : do not satisfy the law, α(ι —a)=0, ; then the constituent in question must be made equal to Ο. ᾿ To prove the theorem generally, let us represent the ex= pansion given, under the form woah ae cn (x) in which ¢,, ¢,, ¢;, &c. represent the constituents, and a,, ag) a3, &c. the coefficients ; let us also suppose that a, and Ay do not satisfy the law : αγί(τ -- α]) τε ο, ἀμί! —ay)=0; [91] but that the other coefficients are subject to the law in question, so that we have aes τος --: Re 7 gat a,"=a,, &C. Now multiply each side of the equation (1) by itself. The result will be , pit gS ΡΣ τὺ = A,7t, + apt, + XC (2) AAiseisrevicent toi the fact that ae inst feprescut the development of the equation w= V2, but it may also be proved by actually squaring (1), an¢ observing that we have τ, t2=t, %t%44=0, ἄχεα. a ys 2. OF INTERPRETATION 99 by the properties of constituents. Now subtracting (2) from (1), we have (ay — @y")4 + (ας — ἀφ") = 0. Or, a,(I — a,)t, +.a,(1 — ay)t, =0. Multiply the last equation by ¢,; then since ¢,¢,=0, we have αι —a,)¢,=0, whence 4, =o. In like manner multiplying the same equation by 4,, we have a1 —@_)t,=0, whence ¢,=0. Thus it may be shown generally than any constituent whose coefficient is not subject to the same fundamental law as the symbols themselves must be separately equated too. The usual form under which such coefficients occur is =. This is the algebraic symbol of infinity. Now the nearer any number approaches to infinity (allowing such an expression), the more does it depart from the condition of satisfying the fundamental law above referred to. The symbol = , whose interpretation was previously dis- cussed, does not necessarily disobey the law we are here considering, for it admits of the numerical values Oo and 1 indifferently. Its actual interpretation, however, as an indefinite class symbol, cannot, I conceive, except upon ‘the ground of analogy, be de-[92]duced from its arith- metical properties, but must be established experimentally. ' 12, We may now collect the results to which we have been led, into the following summary : ist -bhe«symbol 414.45 -the scociicicnt.o1 ἃ terin.in, ‘a development, indicates that the whole of the class which that constituent represents, is to be taken. 2nd. The coefficient o indicates that none of the class are to be taken. 3rd. The symbol indicates that a perfectly zudefinite \ 100 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT portion of the class, 2.6. some, mone, OF all of its members are to be taken. 4th. Any other symbol as a coefficient indicates that the constituent to which it is prefixed must be equated to Ο. It follows hence that if the solution of a problem, ob- tained by development, be of the form SOY ney ste Once 8 Ov 70 that solution may be resolved into the two following equa- tions, viz., Ὁ w= A+uC, (3) DO; (4) ee ee re one v being an indefinite class symbol. The interpretation of : (3) shows what elements enter, or may enter, into the com- position of w, the class of things whose definition is re- quired ; and the interpretation of (4) shows what relations exist among the elements of the original problem, in perfect independence of w. Such are the canons of interpretation. It may be added, that they are universal in their application, and that their use is always unembarrassed by exception or failure. 13. Corollary. —\f V be an independently interpretable logi- cal function, it will satisfy the symbolicallaw, V(1— V)=0. By an independently interpretable logical function, I mean one which is interpretable, without presupposing any ; relation among the things represented by the symbols which : it involves. Thus #(1—y) is independently interpretable, but x—y is not so. [93] The latter function presupposes, — as a condition of its interpretation, that the class represented by y is wholly contained in the class represented by x; the ) former function does not imply any such requirement. Now if V be independently interpretable, and if w represent the collection of individuals which it contains, the equation w= V will hold true without entailing as a con- ' sequence the vanishing of any of the constituents in ἴῃ6 development of V; since such vanishing of constituents : OF INTERPRETATION IOI would imply relations among the classes of things denoted by the symbols in V. Hence the development of V will be of the form a,t, + ant, + &c. the coefficients a,, a, &c. all satisfying the condition a(i—a@,)=0, a (1-a,)=0, &c. Hence by the reasoning of Prop. [V., Chap. V., the function V will be subject to the law Vii -- V)=0. This result, though evident @ przorz from the fact that V is supposed to represent a class or collection of things, is thus seen to follow also from the properties of the con- stituents of which it is composed. The condition V(1— V) =O may be termed ‘‘the condition of interpretability of logical functions.” 14. The general form of solutions, or logical conclusions developed in the last Proposition, may be designated as a Ε΄ Relation between terms.” I use, as before, the word “*terms” to denote the parts of a proposition, whether simple or complex, which are connected by the copula eis” or ‘‘are.” The classes of things represented by the iadividual symbols may be called the elements of the proposition. 15. Ex. 1.—Resuming the definition of ‘‘clean beasts,” (VI. 6), required a description of ‘‘ unclean beasts.” phere, as belore,.4 standing for “clean beasts, 7 for ‘beasts dividing the hoof,” z for ‘‘ beasts chewing the cud,” we have ! X= VE 5 (5) whence I-xX=1-Yyz; and developing the second member, [94] rx yr 2) 21 9) Hy) ) 5 which is interpretableinto the following Proposition: Unclean beasts are all which divide the hoof without chewing the cud, dese ea aaa 102 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT all which chew the cud without dividing the hoof, and all which neither divide the hoof nor chew the cud. Ex. 2.—The same definition being given, required a description of beasts which do not divide the hoof. From the equation + =yz we have Ζ therefore ZB-X, and developing the second member, I — y= 0005 + —— (1 —z)+(1 —x)e+o(t -- γᾷ - 2). Here, according to the Rule, the term whose coefficient | . πὶο'Ἐ iS eae must be separately equated to 0, whence we have I-y=(1-x)s+v(1-x)(1—2), χίι -- 2) το; whereof the first equation gives by interpretation the Pro-_ position: Beasts which do not divide the hoof consist of all unclean beasts which chew the cud, and an indefinite γὲ6- mainder (some, none, or all) of unclean beasts which do not — chew the cud. The second equation gives the Proposition: There are no clean beasts which do not chew the cud. This is one of © the independent relations above referred to. We sought the ~ direct relation of ‘‘ Beasts not dividing the hoof,” to ‘‘ Clean beasts and beasts which chew the cud.” It happens, how- ; ever, that independently of any relation to beasts not ; dividing the hoof, there exists, in virtue of the premiss, a Ἷ separate relation between clean beasts and beasts which chew the cud. This relation is also necessarily given by — the process. Ex. 3.—Let us take the following definition, Viz. 4 ‘“ Responsible beings are all rational beings who are either — free to act, or [95] have voluntarily sacrificed their freedom,” — and apply to it the preceding analysis, OF INTERPRETATION 103 Let x stand for responsible beings. y i rational beings. Ζ a those who are free to act, We those who have voluntarily sacrificed their freedom of action. In the expression of this definition I shall assume, that the two alternatives which it presents, viz.: ‘‘ Rational beings free to act,” and ‘‘ Rational beings whose freedom of action has been voluntarily sacrificed,” are mutually exclusive, so _ that no individuals are found at once in both these divisions. This will permit us to interpret the proposition literally into the language of symbols, as follows: x= yZ+yw. (6) Let us first determine hence the relation of ‘‘ rational beings” to responsible beings, beings free to act, and beings whose freedom of action has been voluntarily abjured. Perhaps this object will be better stated by saying, that we desire to express the relation among the elements of the pre- Β miss in such a form as will enable us to determine how far ‘rationality may be inferred from responsibility, freedom of action, a voluntary sacrifice of freedom, and their contraries. From (6) we have x sw’ and developing the second member, but rejecting terms whose coefficients are 0, »-- wesw + απ =) + (τ -- 8)20 + χα - z)(1 — τ) +2(1-2)(1=3)(1- ἡ, whence, equating to o the terms whose coefficients are I I - and —, we have 2 O y=x2(1 —w)+xw(1 —2)+0(1-x)(1- 2)(Α -- τ); (7) oo; (8) [96] a(1 —2)(1-w)=0; (9) whence by interpretation— 104 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT DIRECT CONCLUSION. —Rational beings are all responsible beings who are either free to act, not having voluntarily sacrificed thetr freedom, or not free to act, having voluntarily sacrificed their freedom, together with an indefinite remainder (some, none, or all) of beings not responstble, not free, and not having voluntarily sacrificed their freedom. First INDEPENDENT RELATION.—wVo responsible beings are at the same time free to act, and tn the condition of having voluntarily sacrificed their freedom. SECOND.—Wo responsible beings are not free to act, and 3 2 4 ᾿ g at the same time in the condition of not having sacrificed — their freedom. The independent relations above determined may, however, { be put in another and more convenient form. Thus (8) gives ο ο xwW = —=02+4-(1—2), on development ; Ζ ο or, xw=v(I - 2); (10) © and in like manner (9) gives 12) (9) Ἰ- — -ὐἷὔς Ὁ ΘΙ - σ᾽)" m1 τ 2) = 5. 9 σε oft -); or, wl — 2) oe: (11) and (10) and (11) interpreted give the following Propositions : ist. Responsible beings who have voluntarily sacrificed their freedom are not free. 2nd. Responsible beings who have not voluntarily sacrificed ᾿ their freedom are free. These, however, are merely different forms of the relations before determined. 16. In examining these results, the reader must bear in mind, that the sole province of a method of inference or analysis, is to determine those relations which are necessitated by the connexion of the terms in the original proposition. Accordingly, in estimating the completeness with which this object is effected, we have nothing whatever to do with those other relations which [97] may be suggested to our minds by the meaning of the terms employed, as distinct from their ; OF INTERPRETATION 105 expressed connexion. Thus it seems obvious to remark, that ‘‘ They who have voluntarily sacrificed their freedom are not free,” this being a relation implied in the very mean- ing of the terms. And hence it might appear, that the first of the two independent relations assigned by the method is on the one hand needlessly limited, and on the other hand superfluous. However, if regard be had merely to the con- nexion of the terms in the original premiss, it will be seen that the relation in question is not liable to either of these charges. The solution, as expressed in the direct conclusion and the independent relations, conjointly, is perfectly com- plete, without being in any way superfluous. If we wish to take into account the implicit relation above referred to, viz., ‘‘ They who have voluntarily sacrificed their freedom are not free,” we can do so by making this a distinct proposition, the proper expression of which would be w=v(I — 2). This equation we should have to employ together with ‘that expressive of the original premiss. The mode in which such an examination must be conducted will appear when we enter upon the theory of systems of propositions in a future Chapter. The sole difference of result to which the analysis leads is, that the first of the independent relations deduced above is superseded. 17. Ex. 4.—Assuming the same definition as in Ex- ample 2, let it be required to obtain a description of irrational persons. We have PS Vi aie Ζ- τ΄ Z+tWw—X ~ g++ I =p xe + oxs(1 — το) +ox(1 —2)w -- ~ «(1 —z)(1 -- 20) Ὁ (τ - x)zw +(1-x)2(1-w)+(1-x)(1 — a) +=(1 —x)(1 —2)\(1 -- τυ) | ec ~ x)ew +(1 - x)2(1 - w) + (1 —x)(1 -- ὅ)0 + σα -- x)(1 -- 2) - το) = (1 ~x)s+ (1 γα - s)w +o(r —a)(1— 2)(1~ 0), with xzw=0, x(1-3)(1 -w)=o. 106 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT [98] The independent relations here given are the same 1 ‘ 4 as we before arrived at, as they evidently ought to be, since © whatever relations prevail independently of the existence of ᾿ a given class of objects y, prevail independently also of ἴπθ existence of the contrary class I —¥y. The direct solution afforded by the first equation is :— : Irrational persons consist of all irresponsible beings who are either free to act, or have voluntarily sacrificed ther liberty, : and are not free to act ; together with an indefinite remainder of irresponsible beings who have not sacrificed their liberty, | and are not free to act. 18. The propositions analyzed in this Chapter have been . of that species called definitions. I have discussed none of — which the second or predicate term is particular, and of which — the general type is Y=vX, Y and X being functions of the © logical symbols x, y, 2, &c., and Ὁ an indefinite class symbol. — The analysis of such Pct is greatly facilitated (thougill the step is not an essential one) by the elimination of the | ᾿ symbol v, and this process depends upon the method of thell next Chapter. I postpone also the consideration of another important problem necessary to complete the theory ot single propositions, but of which the analysis really depends upon the method of the reduction of systems of propositions to be developed in a future page of this work. [99] CHAPTER VII OF ELIMINATION 1. IN the examples discussed in the last Chapter, all the ele- “ments of the original premiss re-appeared in the conclusion, only in a different order, and with a different connexion. But it more usually happens in common reasoning, and especially when we have more than one premiss, that some of the elements are required not to appear in the conclusion. Such elements, or, as they are commonly called, ‘‘ middle terms,” may be considered as introduced into the original propositions only for the sake of that connexion which they assist to establish among the other elements, which are alone designed to enter into the expression of the conclusion. 2. Respecting such intermediate elements, or middle terms, some erroneous notions prevail. It is a general opinion, to which, however, the examples contained in the Jast Chapter furnish a contradiction, that inference consists peculiarly in the elimination of such terms, and that the ele- mentary type of this process is exhibited in the elimination of one middle term from two premises, so as to produce a single resulting conclusion into which that term does not enter. Hence it is commonly held, that syllogism is the basis, or else the common type, of all inference, which may thus, however complex its form and structure, be resolved into a series of syllogisms. The propriety of this view will be considered in a subsequent Chapter. At present I wish to direct attention to an important, but hitherto unnoticed, point of difference between the system of Logic, as expressed by symbols, and that of common algebra, with reference to the subject of elimination. In the algebraic system we are able to eliminate one symbol from two equations, two symbols 107 108 THE LAWS OF, THOUGHT from three equations, and generally 2—1 symbols from x equations. There thus exists a definite connexion between ~ the number of independent equations given, [100] and the — παν a es number of symbols of quantity which it is possible to eliminate ~ from them. But it is otherwise with the system of Logic, ‘ No fixed connexion there prevails between the number of — equations given representing propositions or premises, and — the number of typical symbols of which the elimination can — be effected. From a single equation an indefinite number — of such symbols may be eliminated. On the other hand, ; from an indefinite number of equations, a single class sym- bol only may be eliminated. We may affirm, that in this — peculiar system, the problem of elimination is resolvable | under all circumstances alike. This is a consequence of that | remarkable law of duality to which the symbols of Logic — are subject. To the equations furnished by the premises ; given, there is added another equation or system of equations : drawn from the fundamental laws of thought itself, and | supplying the necessary means for the solution of the problem ἱ in question. Of the many consequences which flow from ἢ the law of duality, this is perhaps the most deserving of — attention. 3. As in Algebra it often happens, that the elimination ~ of symbols from a given system of equations conducts to ἃ mere identity in the form O=0, no independent relations | connecting the symbols which remain; so in the system of © Logic, a like result, admitting of a similar interpretation, : may present itself. Such a circumstance does not detract % from the generality of the principle before stated. The | object of the method upon which we are about to enter is — to eliminate any number of symbols from any number οὗ logical equations, and to exhibit in the result the actual relations which remain. Now it may be, that no such— residual relations exist. In such a case the truth of the_ method is shown by its leading us to a merely identical proposition. 4. The notation adopted in the following Propositions is OF ELIMINATION 109 similar to that of the last chapter. By /(%) is meant any expression involving the logical symbol x, with or without other logical symbols. By /(1) is meant what /(7) becomes when x is therein changed into 1; by /(0) what the same function becomes when + is changed into o. [101] PROPOSITION I 5. 77 f(x)=0 be any logical equation tnvolving the class symbol x, with or without other class symbols, then will the equatton F(x) fo) =0 be true, independently of the interpretation of x; and tt will be the complete result of the elimination of x from the above equation. _ In other words, the eliminationof x from any given equatton, f(a) =0, will be effected by successtvely changing tn that equa- tion x into τ, and x into Ο, and multiplying the two resulting equations together. Similarly the complete result of the elimination of any class symbols, x,y, &c., from any equation of the form V =o, will be obtained by completely expanding the first member of that eguation in constituents of the given symbols, and multiplying together all the coefficients of those constituents, and equating the product to Ο. Developing the first member of the equation ((v)=0, we have (V. το), A(r)x +flo)(t — x) =0 5 or, { f(t) —f(0) }# +/(2) = 0. (1) le Ho) - fa)" and © ee ree igs (0) —/(1) | Substitute these expressions for # and 1—~# in the funda- mental equation x(1 —x)=0, a 110 Toe LAWS Ole THOCGHT and there results | Peg OO. | iC) AG 9] ce or (1) f(0) -- ο, (2) the form required. : , 6. It is seen in this process, that the elimination is really effected between the given equation /(7)=o and the uni- versally true equation 4(1—*)=0, expressing the funda- mental law of logical symbols, χα logical. There exists, therefore, no need of more [102] than one premiss or equa- tion, in order to render possible the elimination of a term, the necessary law of thought virtually supplying the other premiss or equation. And though the demonstration of this conclusion may be exhibited in other forms, yet the same element furnished by the mind itself will still be virtualli™ present. Thus we might proceed as follows: Multiply (1) by x, and we have f(t)x= 0, (3) and let us seek by the forms of ordinary algebra to eliminate a from this equation and (1). Now if we have two algebraic equations of the form ax+b=0, ax+b'=0; it is well known that the result of the elimination of x is ab’ —ab=o, (4) But comparing the above pair of equations with (1) and (3) | respectively, we find a=f(1)-f(0), b=f(0); co 01) eo which, substituted in (4), give S(1)f(2) = 09, as before, In this form of the demonstration, the funda- mental equation #(1—+)=0, makes its appearance in the derivation of (3) from (1). OF ELIMINATION Tit 7, 1 shall add yet another form of the demonstration, partaking of a half logical character, and which may set the demonstration of this important theorem in a clearer light. We have as before S(1)x +f(0)(1 -- x) =0. Multiply this equation first by x, and secondly by 1 -- , we get fir)x=0, f(o)(1-x)=0. From these we have by solution and development, [103] S(2 -Ξ-τα - x), on development, The direct interpretation of these equations is— ist. Whatever individuals are included in the class repre- sented by /(1), are not 7's. 2nd. Whatever individuals are included in the class repre- sented by /(0), are vs. Whence by common logic, there are no individuals at once in the class f(1) and in the class /(O), z.e. there are no indivi- duals in the class f(1)/(0). Hence, f(1)f(0) --ο. (5) Or it would suffice to multiply together the developed equations, whence the result would immediately follow. 8. The theorem (5) furnishes us with the following Rule: TO ELIMINATE ANY SYMBOL FROM A PROPOSED EQUATION RULE.—The terms of the equation having been brought, by transposition if necessary, to the first side, give to the symbol successively the values τ and Ο, and multiply the resulting equations together. The first part of the Proposition is now proved. 9. Consider in the next place the general equation 72, Y) = 93 12 LHE LAWS OF THOUGHT the first member of which represents any function of x, y, and other symbols. By what has been shown, the result of the elimination of y from this equation will be T(x, 1) f(x, 0) =0; for such is the form to which we are conducted by successively changing in the given equation y into 1, and y into 0, and multiplying the results together. Again, if in the result obtained we change successively xinto 1, and + into o, and multiply the results together, we have A(t, DS; ολ)ο, 1)/(0, 0) =0 ; (6) as the final result of elimination. [104] But the four factors of the first member of this equa- tion are the four coefficients of the complete expansion of | 7, y), the first member of the original equation ; whence — the second part of the Proposition is manifest. q EX SWIPES 10, Ex, 1.—Having given the Proposition, ‘‘ All men are mortal,” and its symbolical expression, in the equation, J) = 0X, in which y represents ‘‘ men,” and x ‘‘ mortals,” it is required to eliminate the indefinite class symbol v, and to interpret the result, Here bringing the terms to the first side, we have y —-Ux =o, When v=1 this becomes )πτ στο; and when v=o it becomes Os and these two equations multiplied together, give »-τγατεο, or (I -- x) =0, it being observed that y?= y, OF ELIMINATION 113 The above equation is the required result of elimination, and its interpretation is, Jen who are not mortal do not exist, —an obvious conclusion. If from the equation last obtained we seek a description of beings who are not mortal, we have Whence, by expansion, ιττ σεται —y), which interpreted gives, They who are not mortal are not men. This is an example of [105] what in the common logic is called con- version by contraposition, or negative conversion. * Ex. 2.—Taking the Proposition, ‘‘ No men are perfect,” as represented by the equation yout — x), menerein y represents ‘‘ men,” and x ‘‘ perfect beings,” 1t is re- quired to eliminate v, and find from the result a description both of perfect beings and of cmperfect beings. We have y-Ui-—x)=0. Whence, by the rule of elimination, στα - ὦ} xy=0, or Y-YWI - x)= 0, or Ἤχ 0. which is interpreted by the Proposition, Perfect men do not exist. From the above equation we have OO aro) ὃν αν αὶ t; x ᾿ ὦ y) by developmen whence, by interpretation, Mo perfect beings are men. Similarly, Ὁ, ἢ ο I-x=1-—--=-+=j)+- ey ἢ ἢ ΠΣ ay) * Whately’s ZLogzc, Book II. Chap, ii. sec. 4. 114 THE LAWS. CF THOUGHT which, on interpretation, gives, /iperfect beings are all men with an indefinite remainder of beings, which are not men. 11. It will generally be the most convenient course, in the © treatment of propositions, to eliminate first the indefinite class _ symbol v, wherever it occurs in the corresponding equations, This will only modify their form, without impairing their significance. Let us apply this process to one of the examples } of Chap. IV. For the Proposition, ‘‘ No men are placed ἸΗ͂Ν exalted stations and free from envious regards,” we found the expression y=U(1 — x2), and for the equivalent Proposition, ‘‘ Men in exalted stations | are not free from envious regards,” the expression yx =0(1 = 2) 5 [106] and it was observed that these equations, v being an indefinite class symbol, were themselves equivalent. To prove this, it is only necessary to eliminate from each the symbol wv. The first equation is y—v(i -- x2)=0, whence, first making v=1, and then v=o, and multiplying - the results, we have Oe I + x2) =0, or XS =O. Now the second of the given equations becomes on trans- position yx -Ui-2)=0; whence (yx -14+2)yx=0, or YXZ=0, as before. The reader will easily interpret the result. 12, Ex, 3.—As a subject for the general method of this chapter, we will resume Mr. Senior’s definition of wealth, viz. : ‘Wealth consists of things transferable, limited in supply, and either productive of pleasure or preventive of pain.” We shall consider this definition, agreeably to a former remark, as including all things which possess at once a OF ELIMINATION 11s both the qualities expressed in the last part of the definition, upon which assumption we have, as our representative equation, w=st{ pr+p(1—7r)+r(1 -- 2)}, or w=st{p+r(1 —p)}, wherein w stands for wealth. ὃ τ things limited in supply. t - things transferable. 2 a things productive of pleasure. A a things preventive of pain. From the above equation we can eliminate any symbols that we do not desire to take into account, and express the result by solution and development, according to any pro- posed arrangement of subject and predicate. Let us first consider what the expression for w, wealth, would [107] be if the element 7, referring to prevention of pain, were eliminated. Now bringing the terms of the equation to the first side, we get w—st( pt+r—rp)=o. Making r=1, the first member becomes w — 57, and making y=0 it becomes w—stp ; whence we have by the Rule, (w — st)(w -- sip) =o, (7) or w—wstp —wst+ sip=o; (8) whence stp w=; st+ stp -τ the development of the second member of which equation gives w = stp Ὁ 5 st(t -- 2). (9) Whence we have the conclusion,— Wealth consists of all things limited in supply, transferable, and productive of pleasure, and an indefinite remainder of things limited in supply, transferable, and not productive of pleasure. ‘This is sufficiently obvious. Let it be remarked that it is not necessary to perform 116 RAE LAWS OF THOUGHT the multiplication indicated in (7), and reduce that equation to the form (8), in order to determine the expression of w in terms of the other symbols. The process of development may in all cases be made to supersede that of multiplication. Thus if we develop (7) in terms of w, we find (1 -- «δ — stp)w + stp(1 -- το) Ξε ο, whence stp = stp — (1 - sia — sip)’ and this equation developed will give, as before, w= stp +— st - 2). 13. Suppose next that we seek a description of things limited in supply, as dependent upon their relation to ἢ wealth, transferableness, and tendency to pro duce pleasure, omitting all reference to the prevention of pain. [108] From equation (8), which is the result of the ἢ elimination of ~ from the original equation, we have w — «(τοί + wip — tp) = ο. whence a τυ wet + wip — ip = wip + wit - 2). w(t 1)p+~ (1-11 - 2) + o(1 — w)tp + = (1 — w)t(1 ~pA)+=(1 —w)(1—t)p Ἐς τα - δῷ -9). We will first give the direct interpretation of the above solution, term by term; afterwards we shall offer some ἢ general remarks which it suggests; and, finally, show how the expression of the conclusion may be somewhat ab- | breviated. First, then, the direct interpretation is, Things limited in supply consist of AW wealth transferable and productive of pleasure—all wealth transferable, and not productive of — pleasure,—an indefinite amount of what ts not wealth, but as etther transferable, and not productive of pleasure, or in- OF ELIMINATION 117 transferable and productive of pleasure, or neither trans- ferable nor productive of pleasure. I ' To which the terms whose coefficients are ε: permit us to add the following independent relations, viz. : Ist. Wealth that ts intransferable, and productive of pleasure, does not exist. 2ndly. Wealth that ts intransferable, and not productive of pleasure, does not extst. 14. Respecting this solution I suppose the following re- marks are likely to be made. First, it may be said, that in the expression above ob- tained for ‘‘ things limited in supply,” the term ‘‘ All wealth transferable,” &c., is in part redundant ; since all wealth is (as implied in the original proposition, and directly asserted in the zndependent relations) necessarily transferable. I answer, that although in ordinary speech we should not [109] deem it necessary to add to ‘‘ wealth” the epithet ‘‘transferable,” if another part of our reasoning had led us to express the conclusion, that there is no wealth which is not transferable, yet it pertains to the perfection of this method that it in all cases fully defines the objects represented by each term of the conclusion, by stating the relation they bear to each quality or element of distinction that we have chosen to employ. This is necessary in order to keep the different parts of the solution really distinct and independent, and actually prevents redundancy. Suppose that the pair of terms we have been considering had not contained the word ‘‘ transferable,” and had unitedly been ‘‘ All wealth,” we could then logically resolve the single term ‘‘ All wealth” into the two terms ‘‘ All wealth transferable,” and ‘‘ All wealth intransferable.” But the latter term is shown to disappear by the ‘‘independent relations.” Hence it forms no part of the description required, and is therefore re- dundant. The remaining term agrees with the conclusion actually obtained. Solutions in which there cannot, by logical divisions, 118 iii TANS (OL) 100 Gain be produced any superfluous or redundant terms, may be termed pure solutions. Such are all the solutions obtained by the method of development and elimination above ex- plained. Itis proper to notice, that if the common algebraic method of elimination were adopted in the cases in which that method is possible in the present system, we should not be able to depend upon the purity of the solutions ob- tained. Its want of generality would not be its only defect. 15. In the second; place, it will be remarked, that the conclusion contains two terms, the aggregate significance of which would be more conveniently expressed by a single term. Instead of ‘* All wealth productive of pleasure, and transferable,” and ‘‘ All wealth not productive of pleasure, and transferable,” we might simply say, ‘‘ All wealth trans- ferable.” This remark is quite just. But it must be noticed that whenever any such simplifications are possible, they are immediately suggested by the form of the equa- tion we have to interpret ; and if that equation be reduced to its simplest form, then the interpretation to which it conducts will be in its simplest form also. Thus in the original solution the terms wp and w¢(1—p), which have unity for their [110] coefficient, give, on addition, wz; the terms w(1—Z)p and w(1—z)(1—f), which have Ξ for their coefficient give w(1—¢); and the terms (1 —w)1i—t)p and — - O : ; , (I —w)(1—Z)(1—p), which have 5 for their coefficient, give (I—w)(1—2). Whence the complete solution is ο ο Στ 7 — w)(1 eG - w)t(1—/P), with the independent relation, w(1—t)=0, or oe re) The interpretation would now stand thus :— Ist. Things limited in supply consist of all wealth trans- Serable, wtth an endefinite remainder of what ts not wealth OF ELIMINATION 119 and not transferable, and of transferable articles which are not wealth, and are not productive of pleasure. 2nd. All wealth ts transferable. This is the simplest form under which the general con- clusion, with its attendant condition, can be put. 16. When it is required to eliminate two or more symbols from a proposed equation we can either employ (6) Prop. I., or eliminate them in succession, the order of the process being indifferent. From the equation w=st(p+r-—fpr), we have eliminated 7, and found the result, τὺ —wst — wstp + sip =o. Suppose that it had been required to eliminate both r and ¢, then taking the above as the first step of the process, it remains to eliminate from the last equation 7. Now when ¢t=1 the first member of the equation becomes WwW — Ws — wsp + 5, and when ¢=o the same member becomes w. Whence “we have zy(w — ws — wsp + 52) =0, or W — WS =O, for the required result of elimination. [1117 If from the last result we determine w, we have = ἘΣ πος τσ Ὁ whence “44 wealth is limited in supply.” As p does not enter into the equation, it is evident that the above is true, irrespectively of any relation which the elements of the conclusion bear to the quality ‘‘ productive of pleasure.” Resuming the original equation, let it be required to eliminate s and ΖΦ We have τὺ -- εί(2 τ 7 -- 27). Instead, however, of separately eliminating s and ¢ accord- ing to the Rule, it will suffice to treat s¢ as a single symbol, oe DTH LAWS OF THOUGHT seeing that it satisfies the fundamental law of the symbols ; by the equation st(1 — st) =0. Placing, therefore, the given equation under the form w—st(pt+r—-pr)=o; and making s¢ successively equal to 1 and to 0, and taking ἡ the product of the results, we have (w—-p—r+pr)w=o, or w—wp—wr+wpr=o, for the result sought. . Asa particular illustration, let it be required to deduce Ὁ an expression for ‘‘things productive of pleasure” (2), in terms of ‘‘wealth” (w), and ‘‘things preventive of pain” (7). ἢ We have, on solving the equation, Ἢ τα τς 7) “φύ(ι -- 2) 7 Θ ro) Ὁ ᾿ —_wrt+wi-7 I-w ἘΠῚ ιν 7 wr twa =r) 4 2(1 - wr 42 (1 ται -ν) = w(t ~r)4 creo (1 —w). ο ο Whence the following conclusion :—7Things productive of plea-[112|sure are, all wealth not preventive of pain, an in- definite amount of wealth that ἐς preventive of pain, and an in- ᾿ definite amount of what ts not wealth. From the same equation we get Wi 7) 9 w(t-r) wii—7r)’ I-p=1-— which developed, gives zw(1 -p) == wr +2 (1 —w) σε σα —w). (1-7) =Swr+2(1—-w), Ee ee ee eee MARI ον Sa OTN ὙΠ ΗΠ ας Whence, Things not productive of pleasure are either wealth, preventive of pain, or what ts not wealth. Equally easy would be the discussion of any similar case. — 17. Inthe last example of elimination, we have eliminated — the compound symbol s¢ from the given equation, by treat- OF ELIMINATION 121 ing it as asingle symbol. The same method is applicable to any combination of symbols which satisfies the funda- mental law of individual symbols. Thus the expression pt+r—~pr will, on being multiplied by itself, reproduce itself, so that if we represent p+r—pr by a single symbol as y, we shall have the fundamental law obeyed, the equation y=y", or γ( - ))Ξ ο, being satisfied. For the rule of elimination for symbols is founded upon the supposition that each individual symbol is subject to that law; and hence the elimination of any function or combination of such symbols from an equation, may be effected by a single operation, whenever that law is satisfied by the function. Though the forms of interpretation adopted in this and the previous chapter show, perhaps better than any others, the direct significance of the symbols 1 and =, modes of expression more agreeable to those of common discourse may, with equal truth and propriety, be employed. Thus the equation (9) may be interpreted in the following manner : Wealth ts etther limited in supply, transferable, and pro- ductive of pleasure, or limited in sup-[113|py, transferable, and not productive of pleasure. And reversely, Whatever as limited tn supply, transferable, and productive of pleasure, is wealth, Reverse interpretations, similar to the above, are always furnished when the final development introduces terms having unity as a coefficient. 18. NOTE.—The fundamental equation /(1)/(0)=0, ex- pressing the result of the elimination of the symbol + from any equation 2 =o, admits of a remarkable interpretation. It isto be remembered, that by the equation /(7)=0 is implied some proposition in which the individuals repre- ‘sented by the class x, suppose ‘‘men,” are referred to, ‘together, it may be, with other individuals ; and it is our object to ascertain whether there is implied in the pro- position any relation among the other individuals, inde- 122 THE LAWS OF FiOlUGH i pendently of those found in the class men. Now the equa- tion /(1)=o expresses what the original proposition would become if men made up the universe, and the equation #(0)=0 expresses what that original proposition would ἡ become if men ceased to exist, wherefore the equation — (1) f(0) =0 expresses what in virtue of the original proposi- — tion would be equally true on either assumption, z.e. equally ὶ ) ite -whether “men ’ were “<‘all things” or. “nothing, > ὁ Wherefore the theorem expresses that what zs equally true, | whether a given class of objects embraces the whole universe or disappears from existence, ts independent of that class αἰ- together, and vice versa. Herein we see another example - of the interpretation of formal results, immediately deduced from the mathematical laws of thought, into general axioms of philosophy. ty ἘΠ : ¢ [114] CHAPTER VIII OF THE REDUCTION OF SYSTEMS OF PROPOSITIONS 1. IN the preceding Chapters we have determined sufficiently for the most essential purposes the theory of single primary propositions, or, to speak more accurately, of primary pro- positions expressed by a single equation. And we have established upon that theory an adequate method. We have shown how any element involved in the given system of equations may be eliminated, and the relation which con- nects the remaining elements deduced in any proposed form, whether of denial, of affirmation, or of the more usual relation of subject and predicate. It remains that we proceed to the consideration of systems of propositions, and institute with respect to them a similar series of investigations. We are to inquire whether it is possible from the equations by which a system of propositions is expressed to eliminate, ad /zbztum, “any number of the symbols involved; to deduce by inter- pretation. of the result the whole of the relations implied among the remaining symbols ; and to determine in particular the expression of any single element, or of any interpretable combination of elements, in terms of the other elements, so as to present the conclusion in any admissible form that may be required. These questions will be answered by showing that it is possible to reduce any system of equations, or any _of the equations involved in a system, to an equivalent single equation, to which the methods of the previous chapters may be immediately applied. It will be seen also, that in this reduction is involved an important extension of the theory of single propositions, which in the previous discussion of the subject we were compelled to forego. This circumstance is not peculiar in its nature. There are many special depart- {23 124 CAE LAWS CF ,HOCGHT ments of science which cannot be completely surveyed from within, but require to be studied also from an external point — of view, and to be regarded in connexion with [115] other ina aenealial pont and kindred subjects, in order that their full proportions | may be understood. This Chapter will exhibit two distinct modes of reducing Sante τ systems of equations to equivalent single equations. The first of these rests upon the employment of arbitrary constant — multipliers. It is a method sufficiently simple in theory, but — it has the inconvenience of rendering the subsequent pro-_ cesses of elimination and development, when they occur, — somewhat tedious. It was, however, the method of reduction — first discovered, and partly on this account, and partly on | account of its simplicity, it has been thought proper to retain — it. The second method does not require the introduction of . arbitrary constants, and is in nearly all respects preferable — to the preceding one. It will, therefore, generally be adopted © in the subsequent investigations of this work. 2. We proceed to the consideration of the first method. PROPOSITION [ Se ee gO Os ee τ ον τ ee ed Any system of logical equations may be reduced to a single : equivalent equation, by multiplying each equation after the — jirst by a distinct arbitrary constant quantity, and adding all” the results, including the first equation, together. By Prop. II., Chap. VI., the interpretation of any single — equation, /(z, vy. .)=0O is obtained by equating to o those Ἷ constituents of the development of the first member, whose — coefficients do not vanish. And hence, if there be given two — equations, χα, y..)=o0, and A(x, y..)=o, their united 7 import will be contained in the system of results formed by — equating to Ο all those constituents which thus present them- — selves in both, or in either, of the given equations developed according to the Rule of Chap. VI. Thus let it be supposed, ~ that we have the two equations xY —-2X=0, (1) ; x-Y=0; (2)% OF REDUCTION 125 The development of the first gives —xy-2x(1-y)=0; whence, xy=0, χίι -y)=0. (3) [116] The development of the second equation gives x(1 —y)-— (I ὦ) whence, x(I-y)=0, y(1-x)=0. (4) The constituents whose coefficients do not vanish in both de- velopments are xy, x(1—y), and (I1—~*)y, and these would together give the system Dao; αἰ) ὁ; (Ue xy eo, (5) which is equivalent to the two systems given by the develop- ments separately, seeing that in those systems the equation ΠῚ -- γ)ΞΞο is repeated. Confining ourselves to the case of binary systems of equations, it remains then to determine a single equation, which on development shall yield the same constituents with coefficients which do not vanish, as the given equations produce. Now if we represent by : V,=0, V,=0, the given equations, Κ΄, and V, being functions of the logical symbols x, y, 2, &c. ; then the single equation V,+cV,=0, (6) ¢ being an arbitrary constant quantity, will accomplish the ‘required object. For let Af represent any term in the full development V, wherein Ζ is a constituent and 4 its numerical coefficient, and let 282 represent the corresponding term in the full development of V,, then will the corresponding term in the development of (6) be | (A+cB)t. ‘The coefficient of ¢ vanishes if A and B both vanish, but not otherwise. For if we assume that A and B do not both vanish, and at the same time make , A+cB=0, 7) the following cases alone can present themselves. 126 PHE LAWS OF PhO Gia ist. That A vanishes and B does not vanish. In this case the above equation becomes 2.9. -Ὁ. [117] and requires thatc=o. But this contradicts the hypo- thesis that c is an arbztrary constant. and. That B vanishes and A does not vanish. This assump- tion reduces (7) to AO. by which the assumption is itself violated. 3rd. That neither A nor B vanishes. The equation (7) then gives —A B 2 which is a definite value, and, therefore, conflicts with the a hypothesis that ¢ is arbitrary. Hence the coefficient 4+ cB vanishes when A and & both vanish, but not otherwise. Therefore, the same constituents will appear in the development of (6), with coefficients which do not vanish, as in the equations V,=0, V,=0, singly or together. And the equation V,+cV,=0, will be equivalent to the system V,=0, V,=0. By similar reasoning it appears, that the general system of equations Kio πὸ a0, we. may be replaced by the single equation Vi +¢cV,+¢V,+ &c. =0, c, ¢, &c., being arbitrary constants. The equation thus formed may be treated in all respects as the ordinary logical equations of the previous chapters. The arbitrary constants C1) Cg, &c., are not logical symbols. They do not satisfy the law, GA iC) 0; (1-6) — Ὁ. But their introduction is justified by that general principle which has been stated in (11. 15) and (V. 6), and exemplified in nearly all our subsequent investigations, viz., that equa- tions involving the symbols of Logic may be treated in all OF REDUCTION 127 respects as if those symbols were symbols of quantity, subject to the special law 2(1—2)=0, until in the final stage of solution they assume a form interpretable in that system of thought with which Logic is conversant. [118] 3. The following example will serve to illustrate the above method. Ex. 1.—Suppose that an analysis of the properties of a particular class of substances has led to the following general conclusions, viz. : ist. That wherever the properties A and & are combined, “either the property C, or the property D, is present also ; but they are not jointly present. 2nd. That wherever the properties B and C are combined, the properties A and D are cither both present with them, or both absent. 3rd. That wherever the properties A and ὦ are both absent, the properties C and D are both absent also; and vice versd, where the properties C and D are both absent, A and B# are both absent also. Let it then be required from the above to determine what may be concluded in any particular instance from the presence of the property A with respect to the presence or absence of the properties B and C, paying no regard to the property D. Represent the property 4 by 7; ne the property B by y ; ᾿ the property C by 2; | τ the property D by w. _ Then the symbolical expression of the premises will be | xy =v{w(t -- 5) -Ἐ 2(1 -- 20}} ; γε-ε υχτυ Ὁ (τ -- α)(1 --- 29}} ; ἀντ τ τε 2)(1 - ®). From the first two of these equations, separately eliminating | the indefinite class symbol v, we have xy{1 -- τυ(τ -- 2) -- ζ(1 -- 20}} =0; y2{t -- χτῦ -- (- -- α)( -- τ9}} -- ο. Now if we observe that by development 128 PAE LAWs Of THOUGHT, 1 --w(1 -2)—2(1 -- 10) Ξε τῦς -Ἑ (τ -- w)(1 -- 2), and 1—xw—(1—x)(1 -- w)=x(1 -- 29) τσ -- α); [119] and in these expressions replace, for simplicity, 1-xbyx, 1-ybyy, &c, we shall have from the three last equations, xy(w2z + WZ) =0; (x) y2(xt + XW) = ; (2)} ny 02: (3)a and from this system we must eliminate zw. Multiplying the second of the above equations by ς, and ' the third by c, and adding the results to the first, we have xy(we + 2) + ἐντ(ατο + Xw) + ¢(LY — WZ) -- ο. When w is made equal to 1, and therefore @ to o, the first — member of the above equation becomes Lys + XYZ HORS. | And when in the same member w is made 0 and τὺ =1, it. becomes xyz +exys + xy — ἐξ. Hence the result of the elimination of w may be expressed in the form ᾿ (xyz + cays + ἐχ))(αγξ + crys + ἐὰν -- CZ) =0; (4) and from this equation x is to be determined. | Were we now to proceed as in former instances, we . should multiply together the factors in the first member οὗ. the above equation ; but it may be well to show that such ' a course is not at all necessary. Let us develop the first member of (4) with reference to x, the symbol whose ex-_ pression is sought, we find ’ yal p2 toys — e2)w + (cyz + ἐγ) - ἐγ -- x) =O; or cyax + (cyz + y)(c'y — ἐξ)γᾳ — x) =0; whence we find, lost em(ep— 23) (cya + ἐγ)(εν -- 5) — cys’ and developing the second member with respect to y and 2, OF REDUCTION 129 ὦ» Po! w= OY +O y8 + IE + OIE; Ο A Ο τὰ στοᾷ -)6 —y(1- 2) 4=(1 -)α - 2); or, = (1 —y)B +2 (1-5); the interpretation of which is, Wherever the property A ἐς present, there etther C ts present and B absent, or C ts absent. And inversely, Wherever the property C ts present, and the property B absent, there the property A ts present. These results may be much more readily obtained by the method next to be explained. It is, however, satisfactory to possess different modes, serving for mutual verification, of arriving at the same conclusion. 4. We proceed to the second method. PROPOSITION II Tf any equations, V,=0, V,=0, &c., are such that the developments of their first members consist only of constituents with positive coefficients, those equations may be combined together into a single equivalent equation by addition. For, as before, let A¢ represent any term in the develop- ment of the function V,, δὲ the corresponding term in the development of Y,, and soon. Then will the correspond- ing term in the development of the equation V,+ V+ &c.=0, (1) formed by the addition of the several given equations, be (4+ B+&c.)é. But as by hypothesis the coefficients A, 8, &c. are none of them negative, the aggregate coefficient A+B, &c. in the derived equation will only vanish when the separate co- efficients A, B, ἄς. vanish together. Hence the same con- stituents will appear in the development of the equation (1) as in the several equations V,=0, V,=0, &c. of the original system taken collectively, and therefore the interpretation of the equation (1) will be equiva-[121]lent to the collective ϑ 130 RHE LAWS OF THOUGH? interpretations of the several equations from which it is derived. Proposition III s. If V,=0, V,=0, Se. represent any system of equations, the terms of which have by transposition been brought to the first side, then the combined interpretation of the system will be involved in the single equation, Vit Vit Se. =0, formed by adding together the squares of the given equations. For let any equation of the system, as V,=0, produce on development an equation at, + at, + &C. Ξε ο, in which ¢,, Z, &c. are constituents, and a, a, &c. their corresponding coefficients. Then the equation V,?=o will produce on development an equation a,*t, + a,7t, + &c. = 9, as may be proved either from the law of the development or by squaring the function a,¢,+a@,¢,, &c. in subjection to the conditions teat, t2=ty tl=0, assigned in Prop. III., Chap. V. Hence the constituents which appear in the expansion of the equation V,?=o0, are the same as those which appear in the expansion of the equation /7,=0, and they have positive coefficients. And the same remark applies to the equations V,=0, &q¢& Whence, by the last Proposition, the equation Vi2+ V2 + &c.=0 will be equivalent in interpretation to the system of equations V,=0, V,=0, ὅσ, Corollary.—Any equation, VY =o, of which the first mem- ber already satisfies the condition i= Vor Vir VY) —o, [122] does not need (as it would remain unaffected by) the ] OF REDUCTION 131 process of squaring. Such equations are, indeed, immedi- ately developable into a series of constituents, with co- efficients equal to 1, Chap. V. Prop. IV. PROPOSITION IV 6. Whenever the equations of a system have by the above process of squaring, or by any other process, been reduced to a form such that all the constituents exhibited in thetr de- velopment have positive coeffictents, any derived equations obtained by elimination will possess the same character, and may be combined with the other equations by addition. Suppose that we have to eliminate a symbol + from any equation / =o, which is such that none of the constituents, in the full development of its first member, have negative coefficients. That expansion may be written in the form Vix +V,(1 - x) =09, V, and V, being each of the form Ab, + Agly . ΤΟΤΕ in which ¢,, ¢,, . . ¢, are constituents of the other symbols, and ay, a, - . a, in each case positive or vanishing quantities. The result of elimination is ΚΤ ΞΟ: and as the coefficients in VY, and V, are none of them negative, there can be no negative coefficients in the product VV. Hence the equation V,V,=0 may be added to any other equation, the coefficients of whose constituents are positive, and the resulting equation will combine the full significance of those from which it was obtained. PROPOSITION V 7. To deduce from the previous Proposttions a practical rule or method for the reduction of systems of equations ex- pressing propositions in Logtc. We have by the previous investigations established the following points, viz. : 132 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT “a [123] 1st. That any equations which are of the form q V =o, V satisfying the fundamental law of duality Κα -- Κ) --ο, may be combined together by simple addition. ; andly. That any other equations of the form V =o may be : reduced, by the process of squaring, to a form in which the ; same principle of combination by mere addition is applicable. — It remains then only to determine what equations in the : actual expression of propositions belong to the former, and ᾿ what to the latter, class. Now the general types of propositions have been set forth in the conclusion of Chap. IV. The division of propositions q which they represent is as follows : . Ist. Propositions, of which the subject is universal, and , the predicate particular. The symbolical type (IV. 15) is IG 51) X and Y satisfying the law of duality. Eliminating v, we j have ‘ X(1 -- Y)=0, (1) q and this will be found also to satisfy the same law. No ; further reduction by the process of squaring is needed. ‘ 2nd. Propositions of which both terms are universal, and ; of which the symbolical type is : 2G) X and Y separately satisfying the law of duality. Writing : the equation in the form XY — Y=o, and squaring, we have 2X Vi Vo: or X(1- Y)+ Κα -- Χ)γτο. (2) The first member of this equation satisfies the law of duality, ὦ as is evident from its very form. We may arrive at the same equation in a different manner. — The equation 1G % is equivalent to the two equations A=DY, Vox, OF REDUCTION 138 ; [124] (for to affirm that X’s are identical with Y’s is to _ affirm both that All X’s are Y’s, and that All Y’s are X’s), Now these equations give, on elimination of v, Χίι -- Y)=0, YV(r-—X)=0, which added, produce (2). 3rd. Propositions of which both terms are particular. The form of such propositions is 7 ΞΖ but v is not quite arbitrary, and therefore must not be eliminated. For v is the representative of some, which, though it may include in its meaning αὐ, does not include none. We must therefore transpose the second member to the first side, and square the resulting equation according to the rule. The result will obviously be vX(1- Y)+0V1-X)=0., The above conclusions it may be convenient to embody in a Rule, which will serve for constant future direction. ὃ. RULE.—The equations being so expressed as that the terms X and Υ in the following typical forms obey the law of duality, change the equations X=vVinto X(1 - Y)=0, X= VYinto X(1- VY)+ V(1-X)=0. vX =vY into vX(1 -- Y)+uV(1-X)=0. Any equation whitch ts given in the form X =o will not need transformation, and any equation which presents itself in the form X =1 may be replaced by 1 —X =0, as appears from the second of the above transformations. When the equations of the system have thus been reduced, _ any of them, as well as any equations derived from them by the process of elimination, may be combined by addition. 9. Norr.—It has been seen in Chapter IV. that in literally translating the terms of a proposition, without attending to its real meaning, into the language of symbols, we may pro- 134 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT duce equations in which the terms XY and Y do not obey the law of duality. The equation w=st(p+7), given in (3) Prop. III. of [125] the Chapter referred to, is of this kind. Such equations, however, as it has been seen, have a mean- ing. Should it, for curiosity, or for any other motive, be determined to employ them, it will be best to reduce them by the Rule (VI. 5). | 10. Ex. 2.—Let us take the following Propositions of E Elementary Geometry : : ist. Similar figures consist of all whose corresponding ~ angles are equal, and whose corresponding sides are pro- 3 portional. 7 2nd. Triangles whose corresponding angles are equal have : their corresponding sides proportional, and vzce versd. . To represent these premises, let us make ὅτε oiinilar. ¢= triangles. g =having corresponding angles equal. y=having corresponding sides proportional. Then the premises are expressed by the following equations : 4 S= 272, (1) 5 tq = tr. (2) Γ Reducing by the Rule, or, which amounts to the same thing, ; bringing the terms of these equations to the first side, squar- — ing each equation, and then adding, we have S+qr—29grs+igt+tr—2tgr=o. (3) 4 Let it be required to deduce a description of dissimilar figures q formed out of the elements expressed by the terms, ér7- ~ angles, having corresponding angles equal, having correspond- ~ ing sides proportional. We have from (3), ee Ue ian, 2tgr 297 --ἶ ' tie Was Ch ASI Ξ 297 --τ bas (4) OF REDUCTION 135 And fully developing the second member, we find I—s=olgr Ὁ 2tg(1 -- 7) 2¢r(1 —g) +41 -- φ)ᾷ -- 2) Ἐ ο(ι - Agr +(1 = λίτ )} (1 -A)r(1—g) + (1 - 21-947). (5) [126] In the above development two of the terms have the coefficient 2, these must be equated to o by the Rule, then those terms whose coefficients are o being rejected, we have 1-s=A1-g)(1—7)+(1-Ag(1 -7) + (1 -διίε -9) (7 ΗΠ ΠΥ ~~ (6) tg(1—7)=0; (7) tr(1—g)=0; (8) the direct interpretation of which is Ist. Dessimilar figures consist of all triangles which have not thetr corresponding angles equal and sides proportional, and of all figures not being triangles which have etther thetr angles equal, and sides not proportional, or thetr corresponding sides proportional, and angles not equal, or netther thetr corre- sponding angles equal nor corresponding sides proportional. 2nd, There are no triangles whose corresponding angles are equal, and sides not proportional. 3rd. There are no triangles whose corresponding stdes are proportional and angles not equal. 11. Such are the immediate interpretations of the final equation. It is seen, in accordance with the general theory, that in deducing a description of a particular class of objects, viz., dissimilar figures, in terms of certain other elements of the original premises, we obtain also the independent rela- tions which exist among those elements in virtue of the same premises. And that this is not superfluous information, even as respects the immediate object of inquiry, may easily be shown. For example, the independent relations may always be made use of to reduce, if it be thought desirable, to a briefer form, the expression of that relation which is directly sought. Thus if we write (7) in the form o=“g(1 -- 7), 136 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT and add it to (6), we get, since H1-g)(i—-7)+M(i—r)=H(1 —7), 1—s=H1—7)+(1- Ag —7) + (1 — Ar (1-9) + (1-1 - g)(1—-1), [127] which, on interpretation, would give for the first term of the description of dissimilar figures, ‘‘ Triangles whose corresponding sides are not proportional,” instead of the fuller description originally obtained. A regard to con- venience must always determine the propriety of such reduction. 12, A reduction which is always advantageous (VII. 15) consists in collecting the terms of the immediate description sought, as of the second member of (5) or (6), into as few groups as possible. Thus the third and fourth terms of the second member of (6) produce by addition the single term ( -- δά --φ). If this reduction be combined with the last, we have 1-s=1-v)+(1-Ag(i-7)+(1 -- δὲ - 9), the interpretation of which is Dissimtlar figures consist of all triangles whose corresponda- ing sides are not proportional, and all figures not being trt- angles which have etther their corresponding angles unequal, or thetr corresponding angles equal, but sides not proportional. The fulness of the general solution is therefore not a super- fluity. While it gives us all the information that we seek, it provides us also with the means of expressing that informa- tion in the mode that is most advantageous. 13. Another observation, illustrative of a principle which has already been stated, remains to be made. Two of the terms in the full development of 1—s in (5) have 2 for their I she coefficients, instead of a It will hereafter be shown that this circumstance indicates that the two premises were not independent. To verify this, let us resume the equations of the premises in their reduced forms, viz., s(1 — gr) +97(1 - 5) =0, ig(1 -r)+tr(1-¢9)=0. eee 7 ἘΠῚ OF REDUCTION 137 Now if the first members of these equations have any common constituents, they will appear on multiplying the equations together. If we do this we obtain stg(1 -- 7) + str(1 -- φ) =0. [128] Whence there will result stg(1 -r)=0, str(1 -- 7) =9, these being equations which are deducible from either of the primitive ones. Their interpretations are— Similar triangles which have thetr corresponding angles equal have their corresponding sides proportional. Similar triangles which have thetr corresponding sides proportional have their corresponding angles equal. _ And these conclusions are equally deducible from either premiss sézgly. In this respect, according to the definitions laid down, the premises are not independent. 14. Let us, in conclusion, resume the problem discussed in illustration of the first method of this Chapter, and endeavour to ascertain, by the present method, what may be concluded from the presence of the property C, with reference to the properties A and Ρ. We found on eliminating the symbols v the following equations, viz. : xy(ws + WZ) =o, (1) y2(xi + xw) =o, (2) ap = wi (3) From these we are to eliminate w and determine z. Now (1) and (2) already satisfy the condition V(1— V)=0. The third equation gives, on. bringing the terms to the first side, and squaring ἀγα -- WZ) + WH -- KV) =0. (4) Adding (1) (2) and (4) together, we have ay(we + WZ) -- γε(ατ + Xw) + ἄγ — WZ) + WAI ~ XY) =O. Eliminating w, we get (xyz +y2e + £9) { cys + you + ἄγε + 2(1 -- Χ))} =0. 138 LHe bPAWS. Of THOOGH YT Now, on multiplying the terms in the second factor by those in the first successively, observing that XX=0, YY=O, 2ξ-Ξ-ο, [129] nearly all disappear, and we have only left XYZ + XYZ=O; (5) whence oa KY + XY One ΘΟ. ae = OXY + — XY 4 — KY + OXY ©) [9] oat eat χα τ τῶν τ 4), Ο [9] furnishing the interpretation. Wherever the property C ts found, either the property A or the property B will be found with it, but not both of them together. From the equation (5) we may readily deduce the result ὦ arrived at in the previous investigation by the method of arbitrary constant multipliers, as well as any other proposed forms of the relation between x, y, and z; e.g. [f the property B ts absent, either A and C will be jotntly present, or C will be absent. And conversely, [f A and C are jointly present, B will be absent. The converse part of this conclusion is founded on the presence of a term xz with unity for its co- efficient in the developed value of 7. [130] ΠΕ ΕΝ ΙΧ OF CERTAIN METHODS OF ABBREVIATION 1. THOUGH the three fundamental methods of development, elimination, and reduction, established and illustrated in the previous Chapters, are sufficient for all the practical ends of Logic, yet there are certain cases in which they admit, and especially the method of elimination, of being simplified in an important degree ; and to these 1 wish to direct attention in the present Chapter. I shall first demonstrate some proposi- tions in which the principles of the above methods of abbrevia- tion are contained, and 1 shall afterwards apply them to particular examples. τς Let us designate as class terms any terms which satisfy the fundamental law V(1— V)=0. Such terms will individu- ally be constituents ; but, when occurring together, will not, as do the terms of a development, necessarily involve the same symbols in each. Thus ax+6xy+cyg may be described as an expression consisting of three class terms, 7, zy, and yz, multiplied by the coefficients a, 0, c respectively. The prin- ciple applied in the two following Propositions, and which, _ in some instances, greatly abbreviates the process of elimina- tion, is that of the resectzon of superfluous class terms ; those being regarded as superfluous which do not add to the constituents of the final result. PROPOSITION I 2. From any equation, V=o, in whitch V consists of a sertes of class terms having positive coeffictents, we are per- mitted to reject any term which contains another term as a factor, and to change every posttive coeffictent to unity. For the significance of this series of positive terms depends 139 140 THE LAWS*OP 1 OCG FE only upon the number and nature of the constituents of its — final expansion, z.e. of its expansion with reference to all the : symbols [131] which it involves, and not at all upon the actual values of the coefficients (VI. 5). Now let x be any term of the series, and xy any other term having + as a factor. The expansion of x with reference to the symbols + and y will be xy + «(1 -- 4), and the expansion of the sum of the terms x and xy will be 2xy + x(1 —y). But by what has been said, these expressions occurring in the first member of an equation, of which the second member is Ο, and of which all the coefficients of the first member are positive, are equivalent ; since there must exist simply the — two constituents vy and x#(1—y) in the final expansion, whence will simply arise the resulting equations or AT =) ὃ; And, therefore, the aggregate of terms ++zy may be re- placed by the single term ~. The same reasoning applies to all the cases contemplated in the Proposition. Thus if the term x is repeated, the aggregate 2% may be replaced by x, because under the circum- stances the equation r=0 must appear in the final reduction. PROPOSITION [1 3. Whenever in the process of elimination we have to mulliply together two factors, each consisting solely of positive terms, satisfying the fundamental law of logical symbols, it ts permitted to reject from both factors any common term, or Jrom either factor any term whitch ἐς divisible by a term in the other factor ; provided always, that the rejected term be added to the product of the resulting factors. In the enunciation of this Proposition, the word ‘‘ divisible ” is a term of convenience, used in the algebraic sense, in which xy and χ( -- )}) are said to be divisible by *. a ee a a iss ‘he -. METHODS OF ABBREVIATION [41 To render more clear the import of this Proposition, let it be supposed that the factors to be multiplied together are aty+eand%+yw+é. It is then asserted, that from these two factors we may reject the term x, and that from the second factor we may reject the term yw, provided that these terms be transferred [132] to the final product. Thus, the resulting factors being y+ time in which they are either true or false together. The general principles of interpretation involved in the ~ above examples do not need any further illustrations or more explicit statement. 11. The laws of the expression of propositions may now be exhibited and studied in the distinct cases in which they present themselves. There is, however, one principle of! fundamental importance to which I wish in the first place to— direct attention. Although the principles of expression Pe 4. ἢ which have been laid down are perfectly general, and enable — us to limit our assertions of the truth or falsehood of pro- ἢ positions to any particular portions of that whole of time — (whether it be an unlimited eternity, or a period whose beginning and whose end are definitely fixed, or the passing moment) which constitutes the universe of our discourse, | yet, in the actual procedure of human reasoning, such limita- tion is not commonly employed. When we assert that a_ proposition is true, we generally mean that it is true through- out the whole [169] duration of the time to which our | discourse refers; and when different assertions of the OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS © 179 i unconditional truth or falsehood of propositions are jointly _ made as the premises of a logical demonstration, it is to the same universe of time that those assertions are referred, and not to particular and limited parts of it. In that necessary matter which is the object or field of the exact sciences every assertion of a truth may be the assertion of an ‘‘ eternal truth.” In reasoning upon transient phenomena (as of some social conjuncture) each assertion may be qualified by an immediate reference to the present time, ‘‘ Now.” But in both cases, unless there is a distinct expression to the con- trary, it is to the same period of duration that each separate proposition relates. The cases which then arise for our con- sideration are the following : ist. Zo express the Proposition, ‘‘ The proposition X ts true.” Weare here required to express that within those limits of time to which the matter of our discourse is confined the pro- position XY is true. Now the time for which the proposition X is true is denoted by x, and the extent of time to which our discourse refers is represented by 1. Hence we have ατεὶ (4) as the expression required. 2nd. 70 express the Proposttion, ‘‘ The proposition X ts false.” We are here to express that within the limits of time to which our discourse relates, the proposition YX is false ; or that within those limits there is no portion of time for which it is true. Now the portion of time for which it is true is 4. Hence the required equation will be x= 0. (5) This result might also be obtained by equating to the whole duration of time 1, the expression for the time during which the proposition X is false, viz, 1-#. This gives I-x=I, whence x= 0. 180 THE LAWS: OF ΤΗΝ 3rd. 70 express the disjunctive Proposttion, ‘‘ Either the pro-[170] position X ἐς true or the proposition Υ ts true”; wt © being thereby implied that the said propositions are mutually exclusive, that ts to say, that one only of them ts true. The time for which either the proposition X is true or the proposition Y is true, but not both, is represented by the expression 4(1—y)+y(1—*). Hence we have x(1 —y) + y(t - x)= 1, (6) for the equation required. If in the above Proposition the particles ezther, or, are supposed not to possess an absolutely disjunctive power, so that the possibility of the simultaneous truth of the proposi- tions X and Y is not excluded, we must add to the first member of the above equations the term xy. We shall thus have xy χᾷι -- )) Ὁ (α -- α)ν Ξε, or x+(1-x)yy=t. (7) Ath. To express the conditional Proposition, ‘‘ If the pro- position Y ts true, the proposttion X ts true.” Since whenever the proposition Y is true, the proposition X is true, it is necessary and sufficient here to express, that the time in which the proposition Y is true is time in which the proposition XY is true ; that is to say, that it is some in- definite portion of the whole time in which the proposition X is true. Now the time in which the proposition Y is true is y, and the whole time in which the proposition YX is true is x Let v be a symbol of time indefinite, then will vx re- present an indefinite portion of the whole time x Accord- ingly, we shall have Y=Ux as the expression of the proposition given. 12. When v is thus regarded as a symbol of time indefinite, vx may be understood to represent the whole, or an indefinite part, or no part, of the whole time +; for any one of these meanings may be realized by a particular determination of i P OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 181 the arbitrary symbol v. Thus, if v be determined to repre- sent a time in which the whole time + is included, vx will represent the whole time x. If v be determined to represent a time, some part of which is in-[1’71]cluded in the time 2, but which does not fill up the measure of that time, vx will represent a part of the time x If, lastly, v is determined to represent a time, of which no part is common with any part of the time +, vx will assume the value o, and will be equivalent to ‘‘no time,” or ‘‘ never.” Now it is to be observed that the proposition, ‘‘lf Y is true, X is true,” contains no assertion of the truth of either of the propositions X and Y. It may equally consist with the supposition that the truth of the proposition Y is a con- dition indispensable to the truth of the proposition α΄, in which case we shall have v=1 ; or with the supposition that although Y expresses a condition which, when realized, assures us of the truth of Y, yet X may be true without implying the fulfilment of that condition, in which case v denotes a time, some part of which is contained in the whole time x; or, lastly, with the supposition that the proposition Y is not true at all, in which case v represents some time, no part of which is common with any part of the time Ὁ All these cases are involved in the general supposition that Εν is a symbol of time indefinite. 5th. 70 express a proposition in which the condztional and the disjunctive characters both exist. The general form of a conditional proposition is, ‘‘If Y is true, X is true,” and its expression is, by the last section, y=vx, We may properly, in analogy with the usage which has been established in primary propositions, designate Y and X as the terms of the conditional proposition into which they enter ; and we may further adopt the language of the ordinary Logic, which designates the term Y, to which the particle if is attached, the ‘‘ antecedent” of the proposition, and the term X the ‘‘ consequent.” Now instead of the terms, as in the above case, being simple 182 THE LAWS OF THOUGHAT propositions, let each or either of them be a disjunctive pro- | position involving different terms connected by the particles _ either, or, as in the following illustrative examples, in which — X, Y, Z, &c. denote simple propositions. Ist. If either XY is true or Y is true, then Z is true. 2nd. If X is true, then either Y is true or Z true. [172] 3rd. If either XY is true or Y is true, then either Z — and W are both true, or they are both false. It is evident that in the above cases the relation of the — antecedent to the consequent is not affected by the circum-_ stance that one of those terms or both are of a disjunctive » character. Accordingly it is only necessary to obtain, in con-_ formity with the principles already established, the proper expressions for the antecedent and the consequent, to affect — the latter with the indefinite symbol Ὁ, and to equate the — results. Thus for the propositions above stated we shall have © the respective equations, Ist. x(1 -- γ) - (1 - x)y=02. 2nd. x=o{ y(1-2)+2(1-y)}. 3rd, x(1 —y) +y(1 -- x) = σευ 4+ (1 -2){1 -- w)}. The rule here exemplified is of general application. Cases in which the disjunctive and the conditional elements | enter ina manner different from the above into the expression — of a compound proposition are conceivable, but I am not aware that they are ever presented to us by the natural © exigencies of human reason, and 1 shall therefore refrain — from any discussion of them. No serious difficulty will arise from this omission, as the general principles which have formed the basis of the above applications are perfectly general, and a slight effort of thought will adapt them to any imaginable case. , 13. In the laws of expression above stated those of inter- pretation are implicitly involved. The equation x=I = “ OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 183 must be understood to express that the proposition X is true ; the equation a -0 Φ that the proposition X is false. The equation Gy a will express that the propositions Y and Y are both true together ; and the equation xy=0 that they are not both together true. [173] In like manner the equations x(t -y) +y(t-@)=1, x(t —y) + H(t — 4) =0, will respectively assert the truth and the falsehood of the disjunctive Proposition, ‘‘ Either X is true or Y is true.” The equations y=UX y= (1 -- x) will respectively express the Propositions, ‘‘If the proposi- tion Y is true, the proposition X is true.” ‘‘If the proposi- tion Y is true, the’ proposition 1 is false.” Examples will frequently present themselves, in the suc- ceeding chapters of this work, of a case in which some terms of a particular member of an equation are affected by the in- definite symbol v, and others not so affected. The following instance will serve for illustration. Suppose that we have Y =XZ+UxK(I — 2). Here it is implied that the time for which the proposition VG is true consists of all the time for which X and Z are together true, together with an indefinite portion of the time for which X is true and Z false. From this it may be seen, 1st, That if Vis true, either Y and Z are together true, or X is true and Z false ; 2ndly, If X and Z are together true, Y is true. The latter of these may be called the reverse interpretation, and it consists in taking the antecedent out of the second 184 THE LAWS, Of ΟΥΑΙ. member, and the consequent from the first member of the — equation. The existence of a term in the second member, whose coéfficient is unity, renders this latter mode of in- | terpretation possible. The general principle which it involves may be thus stated: 14. PRINCIPLE.—Axny constituent term or terms in a par- ticular member of an equation which have for their coeffictent unity, may be taken as the antecedent of a proposition, of which all the terms tn the other member form the consequent. Thus the equation YHHZ+OK(T = 2) + (1 $%)(1 -- 2) would have the following interpretations : [174] DrrECT INTERPRETATION. —/J/ the proposttion Y is true, then either X and Z are true, or X ts trueand Z false, or X and Z are both false. REVERSE INTERPRETATION. —/f ezther X and Z are true, or X and Z are false, ΤΥ ts true, The aggregate of these partial interpretations will express the whole significance of the equation given. 15. We may here call attention again to the remark, that although the idea of time appears to be an essential element in the theory of the interpretation of Secondary Propositions, it may practically be neglected as soon as the laws of ex- pression and of interpretation are definitely established. The forms to which those laws give rise seem, indeed, to corre- spond with the forms of a perfect language. Let us imagine any known or existing languages freed from idioms and divested of superfluity, and let us express in that language any given proposition in a manner the most simple and literal, —the most in accordance with those principles of pure and universal thought upon which all languages are founded, of which all bear the manifestation, but from which all have more or less departed. The transition from such a language to the notation of analysis would consist of no more than the substitution of one set of signs for another, without essential Pe ee ee al i ta bas Sant” OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 185 change eitherof form or character. For the elements, whether things or propositions, among which relation is expressed, we should substitute letters ; for the disjunctive conjunction we should write +; for the connecting copula or sign of relation, we should write =. This analogy I need not pursue. Its reality and completeness will be made more apparent from the study of those forms of expression which will present themselves in subsequent applications of the present theory, viewed in more immediate comparison with that imperfect yet noble instrument of thought-—the English language. 16. Upon the general analogy between the theory of Pri- mary and that of Secondary Propositions, I am desirous of adding a few remarks before dismissing the subject of the present chapter. We might undoubtedly have established the theory of Pri- mary Propositions upon the simple notion of space,in the same [175] way as that of Secondary Propositions has been estab- lished upon the notion of time. Perhaps, had this been done, the analogy which we are contemplating would have been in somewhat closer accordance with the view of those who regard space and time as merely ‘‘ forms of the human under- standing,” conditions of knowledge imposed by the very constitution of the mind upon all that is submitted to its apprehension. But this view, while on the one hand it is incapable of demonstration, on the other hand ties us down to the recognition of ‘‘ place,” τὸ ποῦ, as an essential cate- gory of existence. The question, indeed, whether it is so or not, lies, I apprehend, beyond the reach of our faculties ; but it may be, and I conceive has been, established, that the formal processes of reasoning in primary propositions do not require, as an essential condition, the manifestation in space of the things about which we reason ; that they would remain applicable, with equal strictness of demonstration, to forms of existence, if such there be, which lie beyond the realm of sensible extension. It is a fact, perhaps, in some degree analogous to this, that we are able in many known examples in geometry and dynamics, to exhibit the formal 186 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT analysis of problems founded upon some intellectual con- ception of space different from that which is presented to us by the senses, or which can be realized by the imagination. * I conceive, therefore, that the idea of space is not [176] essential to the development of a theory of primary proposi- tions, but am disposed, though desiring to speak with dif- fidence upon a question of such extreme difficulty, to think that the idea of time is essential to the establishment of a theory of secondary propositions. There seem to be grounds for thinking, that without any change in those faculties which are concerned in reasoning, the manifestation of space to the human mind might have been different from what it is, but not (at least the same) grounds for supposing that the mani- festation of time could have been otherwise than we perceive — it to be. Dismissing, however, these speculations as possibly not altogether free from presumption, let it be affirmed that the real ground upon which the symbol 1 represents in primary propositions the universe of things, and not the space they occupy, is, that the sign of identity = connecting the mem- bers of the corresponding equations, implies that the things which they represent are identical, not simply that they are found in the same portion of space. Let it in like manner be affirmed, that the reason why the symbol 1 in secondary propositions represents, not the universe of events, but the eternity in whose successive moments and periods they are evolved, is, that the same sign of identity connecting the logical members of the corresponding equations implies, not * Space is presented to us in perception, as possessing the three dimensions of length, breadth, and depth. But in a large class of problems relating to the properties of curved surfaces, the rotations of solid bodies around axes, the vibra- tions of elastic media, &c., this limitation appears in the analytical investigation to be of an arbitrary character, and if attention were paid to the processes of solution alone, no reason could be discovered why space should not exist in four or in any greater number of dimensions. ‘The intellectual procedure in the im- aginary world thus suggested can be apprehended by the clearest light of analogy. The existence of space in three dimensions, and the views thereupon of the religious and philosophical mind of antiquity, are thus set forth by Aristotle: — Μέγεθος δὲ τὸ μὲν ἐφ ἕν, γραμμή, τὸ δ᾽ ἐπὶ δύο ἐπίπεδον, τὸ δ᾽ ἐπὶ τρία σῶμα: Καὶ παρὰ ταῦτα οὐκ ἔστιν ἄλλο μέγεθος, διὰ τὸ τρία πάντα εἵναι καὶ τὸ τρὶς πάντῃ. Κάθαπερ γάρ φασι καὶ οἱ Πυθαγόρειοι, τὸ πᾶν καὶ τὰ πάντα τοῖς τρισὶν ὥρισται. Τελευτὴ γὰρ καὶ μέσον καὶ ἀρχὴ τὸν ἀριθμὸν ἔχει τὸν τοῦ παντός" ταῦτα δὲ τὸν τῆς τριάδος. Διὸ παρὰ τῆς φύσεως εἰληφότες ὥσπερ νόμους ἐκείνης, καὶ πρὸς τὰς ἀγιστείας χρώμεθα τῶν θεῶν τῷ ἀριθμῷ τούτῷ.--- 206 Cela, τ. i Ee ee Pe TES Ee νας, ΟΝ OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 187 that the events which those members represent are identical, but that the times of their occurrence are the same. These reasons appear to me to be decisive of the immediate question of interpretation. Ina former treatise on this subject (Mathe- matical Analysis of Logic, p. 49), following the theory of Wallis respecting the Reduction of Hypothetical Proposi- tions, 1 was led to interpret the symbol 1 in secondary pro- positions as the universe of ‘‘cases” or ‘‘conjunctures of circumstances”; but this view involves the necessity of a definition of what is meant by a ‘‘case,” or ‘‘ conjuncture of circumstances” ; and it is certain, that whatever is involved in the term beyond the notion of time is alien to the objects, and restrictive of the processes, of formal Logic. [177] CHAPTER XII OF THE METHODS AND PROCESSES TO BE ADOPTED IN THE TREATMENT OF SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 1. IT has appeared from previous researches (XI. 7) that the laws of combination of the literal symbols of Logic are the same, whether those symbols are employed in the ex- pression of primary or in that of secondary propositions, the sole existing difference between the two cases being a differ- ence of interpretation. It has also been established (V. 6), that whenever distinct systems of thought and interpreta- tion are connected with the same system of formal laws, z.e., of laws relating to the combination and use of symbols, the attendant processes, intermediate between the expression of the primary conditions of a problem and the interpretation of its symbolical solution, are the same in both. Hence, as between the systems of thought manifested in the two forms of primary and of secondary propositions, this community of formal law exists, the processes which have been estab- lished and illustrated in our discussion of the former class of propositions will, without any modification, be applicable to the latter. 2. Thus the laws of the two fundamental processes of elimination and development are the same in the system of secondary as in the system of primary propositions. Again, it has been seen (Chap. VI. Prop. II.) how, in primary pro- positions, the interpretation of any proposed equation devoid of fractional forms may be effected by developing it into a series of constituents, and equating to o every constituent whose coefficient does not vanish. To the equations of secondary propositions the same method is applicable, and the interpreted result to which it finally conducts us is, as 188 EMETHODS IN SECONDARY PROPOSITIONS 189 in the former case (VI. 6), a system of co-existent denials. - But while in the former case the force of those denials is ex- pended upon the existence of certain classes of things, in the latter it relates to the truth of certain combinations of the: ele-[178]mentary propositions involved in the terms of the given premises. And as in primary propositions it was seen that the system of denials admitted of conversion into various other forms of propositions (VI. 7), &c., such conversion will be found to be possible here also, the sole difference consist- ing not in the forms of the equations, but in the nature of their interpretation. 3. Moreover, as in primary propositions, we can find the expression of any element entering into a system of equations, in terms of the remaining elements (VI. 10), or of any selected number of the remaining elements, and interpret that ex- pression into a logical inference, the same object can be accomplished by the same means, difference of interpretation alone excepted, in the system of secondary propositions. The elimination of those elements which we desire to banish from the final solution, the reduction of the system toa single equation, the algebraic solution and the mode of its develop- ment into an interpretable form, differ in no respect from the corresponding steps in the discussion of primary propositions, To remove, however, any possible difficulty, it may be de- sirable to collect under a general Rule the different cases which present themselves inthe treatment of secondary propositions. RULE. — Express symbolically the gtven propositions BXI. 11). Eliminate separately from each equation in which it ts found the indefinite symbol v (VII. 5). Eliminate the remaining symbols which tt ts desired to banish from the final solution: always before elimination re- ducing to a single equation those equations in whtch the symbol or symbols to be eliminated are found (V\II. 7). Collect the resulting equations into a single equation V =o, Then proceed according to the particular form tn which tt ts desired to express the final relation, as— 190 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT ist. 77 in the form of a denial, or system of dentals, develop ) coefficients do not vanish. andly. [fin the form of a disjunctive proposition, equate to 1 the sum of those constituents whose coeffictents vanish. the function V, and equate to 0 all those constituents whose 3 4 grdly. If in the form of a conditional proposition having a sim-[179] ple element, as x or 1—4, for its antecedent, deter- mine the algebraic expression of that element, and develop — that expression. 4athly. 17 in the form of a conditional proposition having a compound expression, as XY, aty+(1—a*)\(1-y), &e., for tts antecedent, equate that expression to a new symbol t, and determine t as a developed function of the symbols which are to appear in the consequent, either by ordinary methods or by the spectal method (1X. 9). sthly. Juterpret the results by (ΧΙ. 13, 14). Tf it only be desired to ascertain whether a particular ele- mentary proposition x ts true or false, we must eliminate all the symbols but «x; then the equation x=1 will indtcate that the proposition ts true, x=0 that it ἐς false, o=0 that the pre- mises are insufficient to determine whether tt is true or false. 4. Ex. 1.—The following prediction is made the subject of a curious discussion in Cicero’s fragmentary treatise, De Fato :—‘‘Si quis (Fabius) natus est oriente Canicula, is in mari non morietur.” I shall apply to it the method of this chapter. Let represent the proposition, ‘‘ Fabius was born at the rising of the dogstar”; x the proposition, ‘‘ Fabius will die in the sea.” In saying that x represents the proposi- tion, ‘‘ Fabius, &c.,” it is only meant that x is a symbol so appropriated (XI. 7) to the above proposition, that the equa- tion += 1 declares, and the equation r=0 denies, the truth of that proposition. The equation we have to discuss will be γτεσίι -- PORTION OF : THE “GETHIGA ORDINE GEOMETRICO DEMONSTRATA” OF SPINOZA 1. THE general order which, in the investigations of the following Chapter, I design to pursue, is the following. I shall examine what are the actual premises involved in the demonstrations of some of the general propositions of the above treatises, whether those premises be expressed or implied. By the actual premises I mean whatever proposi- tions are assumed in the course of the argument, without being proved, and are employed as parts of the foundation upon which the final conclusion is built. The premises thus determined, I shall express in the language of symbols, and I shall then deduce from them by the methods developed in the previous chapters of this work, the most important in- ferences which they involve, in addition to the particular inferences actually drawn by the authors, I shall in some instances modify the premises by the omission of some fact or principle which is contained in them, or by the addition or substitution of some new proposition, and shall determine how by such change the ultimate conclusions are affected. In the pursuit of these objects it will not devolve upon me to inquire, except incidentally, how far the metaphysical principles laid down in these celebrated productions are worthy of confidence, but only to ascertain what conclusions may justly be drawn from given premises ; and in doing this, to exemplify the perfect liberty which we possess as concerns both the choice and the order of the elements of the final or concluding propositions, viz., as to determining 197 198 EAE LAWS OF 2A OC GH Tf. what elementary propositions are true or false, and what are true or false under given restrictions, or in given combinations. 2. The chief practical difficulty of this inquiry will con- sist, [186] not in the application of the method to the premises once determined, but in ascertaining what the premises are. In what are regarded as the most rigorous examples of reasoning applied to metaphysical questions, it will occasionally be found that different trains of thought are blended together ; that particular but essential parts of the demonstration are given parenthetically, or out of the main course of the argument ; that the meaning of a premiss may be in some degree ambiguous ; and, not unfrequently, that arguments, viewed by the strict laws of formal reason- ing, are incorrect or inconclusive. The difficulty of deter- mining and distinctly exhibiting the true premises of a demonstration may, in such cases, be very considerable. But it is a difficulty which must be overcome by all who would ascertain whether a particular conclusion is proved or not, whatever form they may be prepared or disposed to give to the ulterior process of reasoning. It is a difficulty, therefore, which is not peculiar to the method of this work, though it manifests itself more distinctly in connexion with this method than with any other. So intimate, indeed, is this connexion, that is impossible, employing the method of this treatise, to form even a conjecture as to the validity of a conclusion, without a distinct apprehension and exact statement of all the premises upon which it rests. In the more usual course of procedure, nothing is, however, more common than to examine some of the steps of a train of argument, and thence to form a vague general impression of the scope of the whole, without any such preliminary and thorough analysis of the premises which it involves. The necessity of a rigorous determination of the real premises of a demonstration ought not to be regarded as an evil; especially as, when that task is accomplished, every source of doubt or ambiguity is removed. In employing CLARKE AND SPINOZA 199 the method of this treatise, the order in which premises are arranged, the mode of connexion which they exhibit, with every similar circumstance, may be esteemed a matter of indifference, and the process of inference is conducted with a precision which might almost be termed mechanical. 3. The Demonstration of the Being and Attributes of God consists of a series of propositions or theorems, each [187] of them proved by means of premises resolvable, for the most part, into two distinct classes, viz., facts of observation, such as the existence of a material world, the phenomenon of motion, &c., and hypothetical principles, the authority and universality of which are supposed to be recognised a priort. It is, of course, upon the truth of the latter, assuming the correctness of the reasoning, that the validity of the demonstration really depends. But what- ever may be thought of its claims in this respect, it is un- questionable that, as an intellectual performance, its merits are very high. Though the trains of argument of which it consists are not in general very clearly arranged, they are almost always specimens of correct Logic, and they exhibit a subtlety of apprehension and a force of reasoning which have seldom been equalled, never perhaps surpassed. We see in them the consummation of those intellectual efforts which were awakened in the realm of metaphysical inquiry, at a period when the dominion of hypothetical principles was less questioned than it now is, and when the rigorous demonstrations of the newly risen school of mathematical physics seemed to have furnished a model for their direction. They appear to me for this reason (not to mention the dignity of the subject of which they treat) to be deserving of high consideration ; and I do not deem it a vain or super- fluous task to expend upon some of them a careful analysis. 4. The Ethics of Benedict Spinoza is a treatise, the object of which is to prove the identity of God and the universe, and to establish, upon this doctrine, a system of morals and of philosophy. The analysis of its main argument is ex- tremely difficult, owing not to the complexity of the separate 200 THE LAWS. OF 1 BOUGHT propositions which it involves, but to the use of vague defini- tions, and of axioms which, through a like defect of clearness, it is perplexing to determine whether we ought to accept or to reject. While the reasoning of Dr. Samuel Clarke is in part verbal, that of Spinoza is so in a much greater degree ; and perhaps this is the reason why, to some minds, it has appeared to possess a formal cogency, to which in reality it possesses no just claim. These points will, however, be con- sidered in the proper place. [188] CLARKE’S DEMONSTRATION PROPOSITION I 5. ‘* Something has existed from eternity.” The proof is as follows :— ‘‘ For since something now is, ’tis manifest that something always was. Otherwise the things that now are must have risen out of nothing, absolutely and without cause. Which is a plain contradiction in terms. For to say a thing is pro- duced, and yet that there is no cause at all of that production, is to say that something is effected when it is effected by nothing, that is, at the same time when it is not effected at all. Whatever exists has a cause of its existence, either in the necessity of its own nature, and thus it must have been of itself eternal: or in the will of some other being, and then that other being must, at least in the order of nature and causality, have existed before it.” Let us now proceed to analyze the above demonstration. Its first sentence is resolvable into the following propositions : Ist. Something is. 2nd. If something is, either something always was, or the things that now are must have risen out of nothing, The next portion of the demonstration consists of a proof that the second of the above alternatives, viz., ‘‘ The things that now are have risen out of nothing,” is impossible, and it may formally be resolved as follows: 3rd. If the things that now are have risen out of nothing, CLARKE AND SPINOZA 201 something has been effected, and at the same time that some- thing has been effected by nothing. 4th. If that something has been effected by nothing, it has not been effected at all. The second portion of this argument appears to be a mere assumption of the point to be proved, or an attempt to make that point clearer by a different verbal statement. The third and last portion of the demonstration contains a distinct proof of the truth of either the original proposition to be proved, viz., ‘‘Something always was,” or the point proved in the second part of the demonstration, viz., the untenable nature [189] of the hypothesis, that ‘‘ the things that now are have risen out of nothing.” It is resolvable as follows :— 5th. If something is, either it exists by the necessity of its own nature, or it exists by the will of another being. 6th. If it exists by the necessity of its own nature, some- thing always was. 7th. If it exists by the will of another being, then the proposition, that the things which exist have arisen out of nothing, is false. The last proposition is not expressed in the same form in the text of Dr. Clarke ; but his expressed conclusion of the prior existence of another Being is clearly meant as equivalent to a denial of the proposition that the things which now are have arisen out of nothing. It appears, therefore, that the demonstration consists of two distinct trains of argument: one of those trains compris- ing what I have designated as the firs¢ and second parts of the demonstration ; the other comprising the firs¢ and ¢hzrd parts, Let us consider the latter train. The premises are :— Ist. Something is. 2nd. If something is, either something always was, or the things that now are have risen out of nothing. 3rd. If something is, either it exists in the necessity of its own nature, or it exists by the will of another being. 202 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT, 4th. lf it exists in the necessity of its own nature, some- — thing always was. 5th. If it exists by the will of another being, then the | hypothesis, that the things which now are have risen out of — nothing, is false. We must now express symbolically the above proposition. τοι a= Something is. y =Something always was. g= The things which now are, have risen from nothing. p=lIt exists in the necessity of its own nature (2.4. the something spoken of above). g=It exists by the will of another Being. [190] It must be understood, that by the expression, Let x= ‘‘Something is,” is meant no more than that # is the repre- sentative symbol of that proposition (XI. 7), the equations x=1, x=0, respectively declaring its truth and its falsehood. The equations of the premises are :— Ist; “x= 1 ; 2nd. x=v{y(1 -—2)+2(1-y)} ; 3rd. x=o{p(1-¢g)+9(1-p)}; 4th. p=y; sth. g=v(1-2); and on eliminating the several indefinite symbols v, we have c= 407; (1) a{yz+(1—y)(1 - 2)} =0; (2) x{pg+(1 -p)(1-9)}=0; (3) P(r -y)=0; (4) gz=0. (5) 6. First, I shall examine whether any conclusions are de- ducible from the above, concerning the truth or falsity of the single propositions represented by the symbols y, 2, 2, g, viz., of the propositions, ‘‘ Something always was” ; ‘‘ The things which now are have risen from nothing” ; ‘‘ The something which is exists by the necessity of its own nature”; ‘‘ The something which is exists by the will of another being.” ee ee a CLARKE AND SPINOZA 203 For this purpose we must separately eliminate all the symbols but y, all these but z, &c. The resulting equation will determine whether any such separate relations exist. To eliminate x from (1), (2), and (3), it is only necessary to substitute in (2) and (3) the value of x derived from (1). We find as the results, Pot (HO ἡ), Ὁ (6) pat (1 -p)(t- 9) Ὁ: (7) To eliminate 2 we have from (4) and (7), by addition, p(t —y) + q+ (1 -P)t- 9) =03 (8) whence we find, (1 -y)(1-9) .0. (9) [191] To eliminate g from (5) and (9), we have gz+(1—-y)(1-g)=0; whence we find φ(ι —y) =o. (10) There now remain but the two equations (6) and (10), which, on addition, give yeti-y=o, Eliminating from this equation z, we have I-y=o0, or, y=I. (11) Eliminating from the same equation y, we have Z=0., {12 The interpretation of (11) is Something always was. The interpretation of (12) is The things which are have not risen from nothing. Next resuming the system (6), (7), with the two equations (4), (5), let us determine the two equations involving 2 and 0 respectively. To eliminate y we have from (4) and (6), P(r —y) tye + (ι -)α ~ 2) =(0)5 whence, (p+1—z)z=0, οἵ, 22-:-ο. (13) 204 THE LAWS OCF THOUGHT To eliminate z from (5) and (13), we have g2t+ pz=0; whence we get, Ο-ΞΞο. There remains then but the equation (7), from which eliminating g, we have O=0 for the final equation, in 2. Hence there ts no concluston derivable from the premtses affirming the simple truth or falsehood of the proposition, ‘The something which ts exists tn the necessity of tts own nature.” And as, on eliminating 2, there is the same result, o=0, for the ultimate equation in g, it also follows, that there ts no conclusion deductible from the premises as to the simple truth or falsehood of the proposttion, ‘‘ The something which ts exists by the will of another Being.” [192] Of relations connecting more than one of the pro- positions represented by the elementary symbols, it is need- less to consider any but that which is denoted by the equation (7) connecting 2 and g, inasmuch as the propositions repre- sented by the remaining symbols are absolutely true or false independently of any connexion of the kind here spoken of. The interpretation of (7), placed under the form Alt -g)+9(1-A)=1, is, The something whtch ts, etther exists in the necesstty of its own nature, or by the will of another being. I have exhibited the details of the above analysis with a, perhaps, needless fulness and prolixity, because in the ex- amples which will follow, | propose rather to indicate the steps by which results are obtained, than to incur the danger of a wearisome frequency of repetition The conclusions which have resulted from the above application of the method are easily verified by ordinary reasoning. The reader will have no difficulty in applying the method to the other train of premises involved in Dr. Clarke’s first Proposition, and deducing from them the two first of the conclusions to which the above analysis has led. CLARKE AND SPINOZA 205 PROPOSITION II 7. Some one unchangeable and independent Being has existed from eternity. The premises from which the above proposition is proved are the following : Ist. Something has always existed. 2nd. If something has always existed, either there has existed some one unchangeable and independent being, or the whole of existing things has been comprehended in a succession of changeable and dependent beings. 3rd. If the universe has consisted of a succession of change- able and dependent beings, either that series has had a cause from without, or it has had a cause from within. 4th. It has not had a cause from without (because it in- cludes, by hypothesis, all things that exist). [193] 5th. It has not had a cause from within (because no part is necessary, and if no part is necessary, the whole cannot be necessary). Omitting, merely for brevity, the subsidiary proofs con- tained in the parentheses of the fourth and fifth premiss, we may represent the premises as follows : eet «= Something has always existed. y = There has existed some one unchangeable and independent being. = There has existed a succession of changeable and dependent beings. p = That series has had a cause from without. g = That series has had a cause from within. Then we have the following system of equations, viz. : 1St,> X45 and, x«=v{y(1—2) + 2(1 -¥)} 5 3rd. Ζεῦ p(1-g)+(1-P)9}; 4th. ~=0; sth. g=o; 206 THER DAWS Of THOUGHT which, on the separate elimination of the indefinite symbols ' Vv, gives I—-x=0; (1) x{ yz+(1 —y)(1 - 2} =0; (2) 2{pgt+(1-p)(t-g)} Ξο; (3) 2Ξο; (4) g=0; (5) The elimination from the above system of x, 2, g, and y, conducts to the equation go. And the elimination of x, 23, g, and z, conducts in a similar manner to the equation γε τ. Of which equations the respective interpretations are: ist. The whole of existing things has not been compre- hended in a succession of changeable and dependent beings. 2nd. There has existed some one unchangeable and inde- pendent being. [194] The latter of these is the proposition which Dr. Clarke proves. As, by the above analysis, all the pro- positions represented by the literal symbols 4, y, 2, 2, g, are determined as absolutely true or false, it is needless to en- quire into the existence of any further relations connecting those propositions together. Another proof is given of Prop. II., which for brevity I pass over. It may be observed, that the ‘‘ impossibility of in- finite succession,” the proof of which forms a part of Clarke’s argument, has commonly been assumed as a fundamental principle of metaphysics, and extended to other questions than that of causation. Aristotle applies it to establish the necessity of first principles of demonstration ; * the necessity of an end (the good), in human actions, &c. | There is, perhaps, no principle more frequently referred to in his writings. By the schoolmen it was similarly applied to prove the impossibility of an infinite subordination of genera and * Metaphystes, 111. 4; Anal. Post. 1. 19, et seq. + Nite. Ethics, Book I. cap. ii. CLARKE AND SPINOZA 207 species, and hence the necessary existence of universals. Apparently the impossibility of our forming a definite and complete conception of an infinite series, z.e. of comprehend- ing it as a whole, has been confounded with a logical incon- sistency, or contradiction in the idea itself. 8. The analysis of the following argument depends upon the theory of Primary Propositions, PROPOSITION III That unchangeable and independent Being must be self- existent. The premises are :— I. Every being must either have come into existence out of nothing, or it must have been produced by some external cause, or it must be self-existent. 2. No being has come into existence out of nothing. 3. The unchangeable and independent Being has not been produced by an external cause. For the symbolical expression of the above, let us assume, [195] += Beings which have arisen out of nothing. y= Beings which have be produced by an external cause, z= Beings which are self-existent. w= The unchangeable and independent Being. Then we have x(t —y)(1 -- 2) + y(t — Δ) -- 2) +2(1 -- x(t -- ))Ξ τ, (1) X=0, . (2) w=v(I ~ 4), (3) from the last of which eliminating v, wy =0. (4) Whenever, as above, the value of a symbol is given as Oor 1, it is best eliminated by simple substitution. Thus the elimi- nation of 4 gives Ἅγ.τ 2 1 901 νὺ 1; (5) or, γε ( -)α - 2) ο. (6) 208 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Now adding (4) and (6), and eliminating γ, we get w(I — 5) =0, W = UZ} the interpretation of which is, —The unchangeable and inde- pendent being is necessarily self-existing. Of (5), in its actual form, the interpretation is,—Hvery ὦ being has either been produced by an external cause, or it ts | self-existent. 9g. In Dr. Samuel Clarke’s observations on the above pro- position occurs a remarkable argument, designed to prove that the material world is not the self-existent being above ~ spoken of. The passage to which I refer is the following : ‘Tf matter be supposed to exist necessarily, then in that necessary existence there is either included the power of gravitation, or not. If not, then in a world merely material, and in which no intelligent being presides, there never could have been any motion ; because motion, as has been already shown, and is now granted in the question, is not necessary of itself. But if the [196] power of gravitation be included in the pretended necessary existence of matter: then, it following necessarily that there must be a vacuum (as the incomparable Sir Isaac Newton has abundantly demonstrated that there must, if gravitation be an universal quality or affection of matter), it follows likewise, that matter is not a necessary being. For if a vacuum actually be, then it is plainly more than possible for matter not to be.” —(pp. 25, 26). It will, upon attentive examination, be found that the actual premises involved in the above demonstration are the following : ist. If matter is a necessary being, either the property of gravitation is necessarily present, or it is necessarily absent. 2nd. If gravitation is necessarily absent, and the world is not subject to any presiding Intelligence, motion does not exist. 3rd. If the property of gravitation is necessarily present, the existence of a vacuum is necessary. Ἐς ΡΥ ΡΝ «σὺν ΝΟΣ, CLARKE AND: SPINOZA 209 4th. If the existence of a vacuum is necessary, matter is not a necessary being. 5th. If matter is a necessary being, the world is not sub- ject to a presiding Intelligence. 6th. Motion exists. Of the above premises the first four are expressed in the demonstration ; the fifth is implied in the connexion of its first and second sentences; and the sixth expresses a fact, which the author does not appear to have thought it necessary to state, but which is obviously a part of the ground of his reasoning. Let us represent the elementary propositions in the following manner : Let x= Matter is a necessary being. y =Gravitation is necessarily present. ¢= Gravitation is necessarily absent. z= The world is merely material, and not subject to any presiding Intelligence. τὺ = Motion exists. v= A vacuum is necessary. Then the system of premises will be represented by the following equations, in which g is employed as the symbol of time indefinite : [197] a =g{y(1 -- ἢ + (1 -9)Z}- tz =9(1 — w). y= QD. v=g(I—%X). coe w =I. From which, if we eliminate the symbols g, we have the following system, viz.° x{ytt+ (1 —y)(1t -2)} =o. (1) tzw =0. (2) Wi —v)=0. (3) Ux = 0. | (4) χᾷι — 2) =0. (5) I-w=o. (6) 14 210 EE LAWS OF THOCG RE Now if from these equations we eliminate w, v, z, y, and ¢, we obtain the equation a, which expresses the proposition, Matter 7s not a necessary being. This is Dr. Clarke's conclusion. If we endeavour to eliminate any other set of five symbols (except the set v, z, y, t, and %, which would give w=1), we obtain a result of the form o=o. It hence appears that there are no other conclusions expressive of the absolute truth or falsehood of any of the elementary propositions designated by single symbols. Of conclusions expressed by equations involving two symbols, there exists but the following, viz.:—J/ the world is merely material, and not subject to a presiding Intelligence, gravitation is not necessarily absent, ‘This conclusion is ex- pressed by the equation το, whence Ζ-φίι -- ἢ. If in the above analysis we suppress the concluding premiss, expressing the fact of the existence of motion, and leave the hypothetical principles which are embodied in the remaining premises untouched, some remarkable conclusions follow. To these I shall direct attention in the following chapter. 10. Of the remainder of Dr. Clarke’s argument I shall briefly state the substance and connexion, dwelling only on certain por-[198]tions of it which are of a more complex character than the others, and afford better illustrations of the method of this work. In Prop. IV. it is shown that the substance or essence of the self-existent being is incomprehensible. The tenor of the reasoning employed is, that we are ignorant of the essen- tial nature of all other things,—much more, then, of the essence of the self-existent being. In Prop. V. it is contended that ‘‘though the substance or essence of the self-existent being is itself absolutely incompre- hensible to us, yet many of the essential attributes of his nature are strictly demonstrable, as well as his existence.” In Prop. VI. it is argued that ‘‘ the self-existent being ΨΥ πὸ δὲ τος ee ee δι. ον ee — 7 CLARKE AND SPINOZA 2ὉῚ1 must of necessity be infinite and omnipresent ” ; and it is con- tended that his infinity must be ‘‘an infinity of fulness as well as of immensity.” The ground upon which the demon- stration proceeds is, that an absolute necessity of existence must be independent of time, place, and circumstance, free from limitation, and therefore excluding all imperfection, And hence it is inferred that the self-existent being must be ‘¢a most simple, unchangeable, incorruptible being, without parts, figure, motion, or any other such properties as we find in matter.” The premises actually employed may be exhibited as follows : 1. If a finite being is self-existent, it is a contradiction to suppose it not to exist. 2. A finite being may, without contradiction, be absent from one place. 3. That which may without contradiction be absent from one place may without contradiction be absent from all places. 4. That which may without contradiction be absent from all places may without contradiction be supposed not to exist. Let us assume x= Finite beings. y= Things self-existent. g= Things which it is a contradiction to suppose not to exist, w= Things which may be absent without contradiction from one place. t=Things which without contradiction may be absent from every place. [199] We have on expressing the above, and eliminating the indefinite symbols, χγᾷ(ι —z)=0. (1) x(I — 20) ΞΞ ο. (2) w(t -- ἢ =o. (3) fz =0. (4) Eliminating in succession ¢, w, and z, we get 212 THE LAWS Of THOUGHT i ay -- Ο, ο “νι x) ; the interpretation of which is,— Whatever ts self-existent ts — infinite. In Prop. VII. it is argued that the self-existent being must — of necessity be One. The order of the proof is, that the self- existent being is ‘‘necessarily existent,” that ‘‘ necessity absolute in itself is simple and uniform, and without any © possible difference or variety,” that all ‘‘ variety or difference of existence” implies dependence ; and hence that ‘‘ what- ever exists necessarily is the one simple essence of the self- existent being.” The conclusion is also made to flow from the following pre- mises :— 1. If there are two or more necessary and independent beings, either of them may be supposed to exist alone. 2. If either may be supposed to exist alone, it is not a con- tradiction to suppose the other not to exist. 3. If it is nota contradiction to suppose this, there are not two necessary and independent beings. Let us represent the elementary propositions as follows :— “= there exist two necessary independent beings. y =either may be supposed to exist alone. #= it is not a contradiction to suppose the other not toexist. We have then, on proceeding as before, x(1 -y)=0. (1) (I —Z)=0. (2) 2X = 0. (3) [200] Eliminating y and z, we have xXx=0, Whence, There do not exist two necessary and independent beings. 11. ΤῸ the premises upon which the two previous proposi- tions rest, it is well known that Bishop Butler, who at the time: eg : CLARKE ΑἸΥΣΒΡΙΝΟΖΑ 213 of the publication of the Demonstration, was a student in a nonconformist academy, made objection in some celebrated letters, which, together with Dr. Clarke’s replies to them, are usually appended to editions of the work. The real question at issue is the validity of the principle, that ‘‘ whatsoever is absolutely necessary at all is absolutely necessary in every _ part of space, and in every point of duration,’—a principle assumed in Dr. Clarke’s reasoning, and explicitly stated in his reply to Butler’s first letter. In his second communica- tion Butler says: ‘‘ I do not conceive that the idea of ubiquity is contained in the idea of self-existence, or directly follows from it, any otherwise than as whatever exists must exist somewhere.” hat is to say, necessary existence implies ex- istence in some part of space, but notin every part. It does not appear that Dr. Clarke was ever able to dispose effectually of this objection. The whole of the correspondence is ex- tremely curious and interesting. The objections of Butler are precisely those which would occur to an acute mind impressed with the conviction, that upon the sifting of first principles, rather than upon any mechanical dexterity of reasoning, the successful investigation of truth mainly de- pends. Andthe replies of Dr. Clarke, although they cannot be admitted as satisfactory, evince, in a remarkable degree, that peculiar intellectual power which is manifest in the work from which the discussion arose. 12. In Prop. VIII. it is argued that the self-existent and original cause of all things must be an Intelligent Being. The main argument adduced in support of this proposition is, that as the cause is more excellent than the effect, the self- existent being, as the cause and original of all things, must contain in itself the perfections of all things ; and that Intelli- gence is one of the perfections manifested in a part of the creation. It is further argued that this perfection is not a modification of [201] figure, divisibility, or any of the known properties of matter ; for these are not perfections, but Zmz¢a- tions. To this is added the ὦ posterzort argument from the manifestation of design in the frame of the universe. 214 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT There is appended, however, a distinct argument for the existence of an intelligent self-existent being, founded upon the phenomenal existence of motion in the universe. I shall briefly exhibit this proof, and shall apply to it the method of the present treatise. | The argument, omitting unimportant explanations, is as_ follows :— ‘“’Tis evident there is some such a thing as motion in the world ; which either began at some time or other, or was eternal. Ifit began in time, then the question is granted that the first cause is an intelligent being. ... On the con- trary, if motion was eternal, either it was eternally caused by — some eternal intelligent being, or it must of itself be necessary — and self-existent, or else, without any necessity in its own nature, and without any external necessary cause, it must_ have existed from eternity by an endless successive communi- © cation. If motion was eternally caused by some eternal in- telligent being, this also is granting the question as to the - present dispute. If it was of itself necessary and self-existent, then it follows that it must be a contradiction in terms to sup- | pose any matter to be at rest. And yet, at the same time, because the determination of this self-existent motion must be every way at once, the effect of it would be nothing else but a perpetual rest. . . . But if it be said that motion, with- out any necessity in its own nature, and without any external necessary cause, has existed from eternity merely by an end- less successive communication, as Spinoza inconsistently enough seems to assert, this I have before shown (in the | proof of the second general proposition of this discourse) to_ be a plain contradiction. It remains, therefore, that motion - must of necessity be originally caused by something that is intelligent.” | The premises of the above argument may be thus disposed : I. If motion began in time, the first cause is an intelligent being. | [202] 2. If motion has existed from eternity, either it has’ been eternally caused by some eternal intelligent being, or it i. CLARKE AND SPINOZA 215 is self-existent, or it must have existed by endless successive communication. 3. 1f motion has been eternally caused by an eternal in- telligent being, the first cause is an intelligent being. 4. If it is self-existent, matter is at rest and not at rest. 5. That motion has existed by endless successive communi- cation, and that at the same time it is not self-existent, and has not been eternally caused by some eternal intelligent being, is false. To express these propositions, let us assume— x= Motion began in time (and therefore) 1 —x= Motion has existed from eternity. y =The first cause is an intelligent being. p =Motion has been eternally caused by some eternal in- telligent being. g = Motion is self-existent. y= Motion has existed by endless successive communica- tion. S=— Matter τῷ αἴ rest. The equations of the premises then are— x= Uy. ι - ατεϑίζᾷ - 4)(1 -- 7) Ἐφίι - 2). -- 7) +7(1 ~ A) -4)}: p=vyy. g=US(I -- 5) ΞΞ ο. (τ 11 2) ΞῸ Since, by the fourth equation, g =0, we obtain, on substitut- ing for g its value in the remaining equations, the system x= UY, 1-x=o{p(1—7)+7(1-P)}, p=y, πα 3). "0. from which eliminating the indefinite symbols v, we have the final reduced system, x(I — J) =O, (1) (x —x){pr+(1-p)(t -7)} =o, (2) P(r -y) =0- (3) r(1—p)=0. (4) [203] We shall first seek the value of y, the symbol involved 216 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT in Dr. Clarke’s conclusion. First, eliminating x from (1) ᾿ and (2), we have x (1 -y) {pr + (1 -p)(1 -7)} =0. (5). Next, to eliminate 7 from (4) and (5), we have (1 — p) + (1 —y) {or + (1 - p)(1 -7)} ἡ oP i ChE Ὁ ὁ. whence UP) ac: (6) Lastly, eliminating p from (3) and (6), we have I-y=0, EID γ»,1 which expresses the required conclusion, The first cause ts an — intelligent being. Let us now examine what other conclusions are deducible from the premises. If we substitute the value just found for y in the equations (1), (2), (3), (4), they are reduced to the following pair of equations, viz., Cea LPT = A) γα ep) =O: (7) Eliminating from these equations x, we have 7(1-—p)=0, whence r=zp, which expresses the conclusion, 27 motion has existed by end- less successive communication, tt has been eternally caused by an eternal intelligent being. Again eliminating, from the given pair, 7, we have (1 —x)(1-p)=0, or, I-—XxX=U), which expresses the conclusion, /f motion has existed from eternity, it has been eternally caused by some eternal intellc- gent being. Lastly, from the same original pair eliminating 2, we get (1-x)r=0, which, solved in the form I-x=U1-7), CLARKE AND SPINOZA 217 [204] gives the conclusion, /f motion has existed from eternity, tt has not extsted by an endless successive com- munication. Solved under the form Fan) the above equation leads to the equivalent conclusion, /f motion exists by an endless successive communication, it began in time. 13. Now it will appear to the reader that the first and last of the above four conclusions are inconsistent with each other. The two consequences drawn from the hypothesis that motion exists by an endless successive communication, viz., Ist, that it has been eternally caused by an eternal intelligent being ; 2ndly, that it began in time, —are plainly at variance. Never- theless, they are both rigorous deductions from the original premises. The opposition between them is not of a dogzcad, but of what is technically termed a materzal, character. This opposition might, however, have been formally stated in the premises. We might have added to them a formal proposi- tion, asserting that ‘‘ whatever is eternally caused by an eter- nal intelligent being, does not begin in time.” Had this been done, no such opposition as now appears in our conclusions could have presented itself. Formal logic can only take ac- count of relations which are formally expressed (VI. 16) ; and it may thus, in particular instances, become necessary to express, in a formal manner, some connexion among the premises which, without actual statement, is involved in the very meaning of the language employed. To illustrate what has been said, let us add to the equations (2) and (4) the equation px=o, which expresses the condition above adverted to. We have (τ x){pr+ (1 τ Ὁ} +71 2) + px=0. (8) Eliminating 2 from this, we find simply r=0, 218 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT which expresses the proposition, A/otzon does not extst by an endless successive communication. If now we substitute for γ its value in (8), we have (t-—x)(1-p)+px=0, Or, I1-x=f; [205] whence we have the interpretation, /f motion has existed from eternity, tt has been eternally caused by an eternal © intelligent being ; together with the converse of that pro-— position. ; In Prop. 1X. it is argued, that ‘‘the self-existent and original — cause of all things is not a necessary agent, but a being en- — dued with liberty and choice.” The proof is based mainly — upon his possession of intelligence, and upon the existence — of final causes, implying design and choice. To the objection — that the supreme cause operates by necessity for the produc- Ἷ tion of what is best, it is replied, that this is a necessity of fitness and wisdom, and not of nature. : 14. In Prop. Χ. it is argued, that ‘‘ the self-existent being, the supreme cause of all things, must of necessity have infinite — power.” The ground of the demonstration is, that as ‘‘all — the powers of all things are derived from him, nothing can ~ make any difficulty or resistance to the execution of his will.” Ὁ It is defined that the infinite power of the self-existent being — does not extend to the ‘‘ making of a thing which implies a _ contradiction,” or the doing of that ‘‘ which would imply — imperfection (whether natural or moral) in the being to whom such power is ascribed,” but that it does extend to the creation of matter, and of an immaterial, cogitative substance, endued with a power of beginning motion, and with a liberty of will or choice. Upon this doctrine of liberty it is con- tended that we are able to give a satisfactory answer to ‘‘ that ancient and great question, πόθεν τὸ κακὸν, what is the cause and original of evil?” The argument on this head I shall briefly exhibit. ‘* All that we call evil is either an evil of imperfection, as the want of certain faculties or excellencies which other creatures have ; or natural evil, as pain, death, and the like ; or moral . CLARKE AND SPINOZA 219 evil, as all kinds of vice. The first of these is not properly an evil; for every power, faculty, or perfection, which any creature enjoys, being the free gift of God, . . it is plain the want of any certain faculty or perfection in any kind of creatures, which never belonged to their natures is no more an evil to them, than their never having been created or brought into being at all could properly have been called an evil. The second kind of evil, which we call natural evil, is either a necessary consequence of the [206] former, as death to acreature on whose nature immortality wasnever conferred; and then it is no more properly an evil than the former. Or else it is counterpoised on the whole with as great or greater good, as the afflictions and sufferings of good men, and then also it is not properly an evil; or else, lastly, it is a punish- ment, and then it is a necessary consequence of the third and last kind of evil, viz., moralevil. And this arises wholly from the abuse of liberty which God gave to His creatures for other purposes, and which it was reasonable and fit to give them for the perfection and order of the whole creation. Only they, contrary to God’s intention and command, have abused what was necessary to the perfection of the whole, to the corruption and depravation of themselves. And thus all sorts of evils have entered into the world without any diminution to the infinite goodness of the Creator and Governor thereof.”—p. I12. The main premises of the above argument may be thus stated : ist. All reputed evil is either evil of imperfection, or natural evil, or moral evil. 2nd. Evil of imperfection is not absolute evil. 3rd. Natural evil is either a consequence of evil of imper- fection, or it is compensated with greater good, or it isa consequence of moral evil. 4th. That which is either a consequence of evil of imper- fection, or is compensated with greater good, is not absolute evil. 5th. All absolute evils are included in reputed evils. 220 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT To express these premises let us assume— w =reputed evil. ax=evil of imperfection. y =natural evil. g=moral evil. p =consequence of evil of imperfection. g =compensated with greater good. r=consequence of moral evil. t=absolute evil. Then, regarding the premises as Primary Propositions, οὗ which [207] all the predicates are particular, and the οοη- junctions eéther, or, as absolutely disjunctive, we have the following equations : w=o{a(t—y)(t— 9) τ) -- α)ὰ -- 2) +2(1— x(x -))) σία — ὃ. y=v{ p(t —g)(1—r) + 94 —p)(t —7) +71 “01 ὩΣ P(t -- φ) +91 -p)=0(1 - 2). ἢ t= VW. | From which, if we separately eliminate the symbol v, we have ~ τοί τ - χίι -y)(1 -- 5) -γίι -- x)(1 — 2) -2(1—x)(r-y)}=0, (1) | xt=0, (2) — Vite Gr) υἱὲ 2) 17) = A Pt 7), Gp {2(1-- 9) + 9(1 -- fp) }t=0, (4) t(1 — τ) =o. (5) Let it be required, first, to find what conclusion the premises warrant us in forming respecting absolute evils, as concerns their dependence upon moral evils, and the consequences of moral evils. For this purpose we must determine ¢in terms of zand~y. The symbols w, +, y, 2, g must therefore be eliminated. The process is easy, as any set of the equations is reducible to a single equation by addition. Eliminating w from (1) and (5), we have ἦτ —a(1-y)(t—2) -y(1 —a)(1-2) -2(2-a\(1-y)}=0. (6) The elimination of 2 from (3) and (4) gives Jar + ygt+ yi —r)(t — 9) οἱ 3 (7) CLARKE AND SPINOZA 221 The elimination of g from this gives y(t -- γ)Ξ ο. (8) The elimination of + between (2) and (6) gives tye + (1 —y)(1 -- 2)} =0. (9) The elimination of y from (8) and (9) gives t(1 -- 2). —r)=0. This is the only relation existing between the elements Ζ, <, and 7. [208] We hence get “απ - τ) Ἐπ κι τς ir) ee τ Our) a 0 ο Ὁ =-g+-(1-2)r; eS τὶ 5) ᾿ the interpretation of which is, Adsolute evil is etther moral evil, or 11 1s, of not moral evil, a consequence of moral evil. Any of the results obtained in the process of the above solution furnishes us with interpretations. Thus from (8) we might deduce ere et ie ey whence, Adsolute evils are either natural evils, which are the consequences of moral evils, or they are not natural evils at all. A variety of other conclusions may be deduced from the given equations in reply to questions which may be arbitrarily proposed. Of such I shall give a few examples, without ex- hibiting the intermediate processes of solution. Quest. 1.—Can any relation be deduced from the premises connecting the following elements, viz. : absolute evils, con- sequences of evils of imperfection, evils compensated with greater good ? Ans.—WVo relation exists. 1{ we eliminate all the symbols Hut 2, 2, g, the result is o=0. Quest. 2.—Is any relation implied between absolute _ evils, evils of imperfection, and consequences of evils of im- perfection ? 722 THE LAWS OF ΤΠΜΟΘΘΗ͂Σ Ans.—The final relation between 4, ¢, and 2 is xt + pt=o; whence oat — p)(1 -- x). Therefore, Absolute evils are neither evils of imperfection, nor : consequences of evils of imperfection. 2 [209] Quest. 3.—Required the relation of natural evils to evils of imperfection and evils compensated with greater good. We find PY = 0, “τ 3 ἢ Therefore, Natural evils are either consequences of evils of tm- perfection which are not compensated with greater good, or they are not consequences of evils of tmperfection at all. Quest. 4.—In what relation do those natural evils which are not moral evils stand to absolute evils and the conse- quences of moral evils ? If (1 —z)=s, we find, after elimination, ts(1-—r)=0;3 A Ο oO Ο ἘΠ το τ Π - ἢ). Therefore, Natural evils, which are not moral evils, are etther absolute evils, which are the consequences af moral evils, or they are not absolute evils at all. The following conclusions have been deduced in a similar manner. The subject of each conclusion will show of what particular things a description was required, and the predicate will show what elements it was designed to involve :— Absolute evils, which are not consequences of moral evils, are moral and not natural evils. Absolute evils which are not moral evils are natural evils, which are the consequences of moral evils. Natural evils which are not consequences of moral evils are not absolute evils, CLARKE AND SPINOZA 223 Lastly, let us seek a description of evils which are not ab- solute, expressed in terms of natural and moral evils. We obtain as the final equation, I —tayst+—y(t τ) 42(1 —y)s+(1-y)(t -- 2). The direct interpretation of this equation is a necessary truth, but the reverse interpretation is remarkable. Hvzls which are both [210] natural and moral, and evils which are neither natural nor moral, are not absolute evils. This conclusion, though it may not express a truth, is cer- tainly involved in the given premises, as formally stated. 15. Let us take from the same argument a somewhat fuller system of premises, and let us in those premises suppose that the particles, ezther, or, are not absolutely disjunctive, so that in the meaning of the expression, ‘‘either evil of imperfection, or natural evil, or moral evil,” we include whatever possesses one or more of these qualities. Let the premises be— 1. All evil (w) is either evil of imperfection (x), or natural evil (y), or moral evil (2). 2. Evil of imperfection (1) is not absolute evil (2). 3. Natural evil (y) is either a consequence of evil of imper- fection (2), or it is compensated with greater good (4), or it is a consequence of moral evil (7). ~ 4. Whatever is a consequence of evil of imperfection (2) is not absolute evil (2). 5. Whatever is compensated with greater good (Φ) is not absolute evil (2). 6. Moral evil (z) is a consequence of the abuse of liberty (2). 7, That which is a consequence of moral evil (7) is a conse- quence of the abuse of liberty (2). 8. Absolute evils are included in reputed evils. The premises expressed in the usual way give, after the eli- mination of the indefinite symbols v, the following equations: w(x -- x)(1 —9)(t — 2) =0, (1) Leo. (2) 224 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT γα -2)α -g)(1-7) =0, (3) pt=9, (4) φί -- Ο, (5) 2(I -- 2) =o, (6) r(1 —%)=0, (7) {ι —w)=o. (8) Each of these equations satisfies the condition V(1 — V)=o0. [211] The following results are easily deduced— Natural evil ts either absolute evil, which ts a consequence of moral evil, or it ts not absolute evil at all. All evils are either absolute evils, which are consequences of the abuse of liberty, or they are not absolute evils. Natural evils are either evils of imperfection, which are not absolute evils, or they are not evils of tmperfection at all. Absolute evils are either natural evils, which are conse- guences of the abuse of liberty, or they are not natural evils, and at the same time not evils of imperfection. Consequences of the abuse of liberty include all natural evils which are absolute evils, and are not evils of tmperfection, with an indefinite remainder of natural evils which are not absolute, and of evils which are not natural. 16. These examples will suffice for illustration. The reader can easily supply others if they are needed. We proceed now to examine the most essential portions of the demonstration of Spinoza. DEFINITIONS 1. By a cause of ttself (causa suz), 1 understand that of which the essence involves existence, or that of which the nature cannot be conceived except as existing. 2. That thing is said to be finite or bounded in its own kind (22 suo genere finita) which may be bounded by another thing of the same kind; e.g. Body is said to be finite, be- cause we can always conceive of another body greater than a givenone. Sothought is bounded by other thought. But body is not bounded by thought, nor thought by body. CLARKE AND SPINOZA 228 3. By substance, [ understand that which is in itself (zx se), and is conceived by itself (per se conctpitur), t.e., that whose conception does not require to be formed from the conception of another thing. 4. By attribute, I understand that which the intellect per- ceives in substance, as constituting its very essence. 5. By mode, I understand the affections of substance, or that which is in another thing, by which thing also it is conceived. 6. By God, I understand the Being absolutely infinite, that [212] is the substance consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses an eternal and infinite essence, Explanation.—I say absolutely infinite, not infinite in its own kind. For to whatever is only infinite in its own kind we may deny the possession of (some) infinite attributes. But when a thing is absolutely infinite, whatsoever expresses essence and involves no negation belongs to its essence. 7. That thing is termed free, which exists by the sole necessity of its own nature, and is determined to action by itself alone ; mecessary, or rather constrained, which is deter- mined by another thing to existence and action, ina certain and determinate manner. 8. By eternity, | understand existence itself, in so far as -it is conceived necessarily to follow from the sole definition of the eternal thing. Explanation.—For such existence, as an eternal truth, is conceived as the essence of the thing, and therefore cannot be explained by mere duration or time, though the latter should be conceived as without beginning and without end. AXIOMS 1. All things which exist are either in themselves (zx se) or in another thing. 2. That which cannot be conceived by another thing ought to be conceived by itself. 3. From a given determinate cause the effect necessarily 15 226 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT follows, and, contrariwise, if no determinate cause be granted, it is impossible that an effect should follow. cl : 4. The knowledge of the effect depends upon, and in-— volves, the knowledge of the cause. 5. Things which have nothing in common cannot be under- | stood by means of each other ; or the conception of the one— does not involve the conception of the other. 6. A true idea ought to agree with its own object. (/dea vera debet cum suo tdeato conventre. ) 7, Whatever can be conceived as non-existing does not involve existence in its essence. [213] Other definitions are implied, and other axioms are virtually assumed, in some of the demonstrations. Thus, in Prop. I., ‘‘Substance is prior in nature to its affections,” the proof of which consists in a mere reference to Defs. 3° and 5, there seems to be an assumption of the following | axiom, viz., ‘‘ That by which a thing is conceived is prior | in nature to the thing conceived.” Again, in the demon- stration of Prop. V. the converse of this axiom is assumed to be true. Many other examples of the same kind occur. | It is impossible, therefore, by the mere processes of Logic, to deduce the whole of the conclusions of the first book of the Ethics from the axioms and definitions which are prefixed to it, and which are given above. In the brief analysis which will follow, I shall endeavour to present in their proper order what appear to me to be the real premises, whether formally | stated or implied, and shall show in what manner they i in- volve the conclusions to which Spinoza was led. ; 17. I conceive, then, that in the course of his demonstra- tion, Spinoza effects several parallel divisions of the univers€ of possible existence, as, Ist. Into things which are in themselves, x, and things! which are in some other thing, x’; whence, as these classes of things together make up the universe, we have | noe (Ax. 1) or, =I-—X’, 2nd. Into things ΠΕΣ are conceived by themselves, » lai Ae 8 oes CLARKE AND SPINOZA 227 and things which are conceived through some other thing, y ; whence y=1-y. (Ax. 2) 3rd. Into substance, z, and modes, 2’; whence z=1-2. (Def. 3, 5) 4th. Into things free, 4 and things necessary, /’; whence f=t-f'. (Def. 7) 5th. Into things which are causes and self-existent, 6, and things caused by some other thing, e’ ; whence ἐξ τ πὶ. (Def. 1, Ax. 7) [214] And his reasoning proceeds upon the expressed or assumed principle that these divisions are not only parallel, but equivalent. Thus in Def. 3, Substance is made equivalent with that which is conceived by itself ; whence Z=Y, Again, Ax. 4, as it is actually applied by Spinoza, es- tablishes the identity of cause with that by which a thing is conceived ; whence yrHe. Again, in Def. 7, things free are identified with things self-existent ; whence ; ΞΞ é, Lastly, in Def. 5, mode is made identical with that which is in another thing ; whence 2’=2’, and therefore, iit All these results may be collected together into the follow- ing series of equations, viz. : eay=goafmemt-x =1-y=1~-f'=1-7 =1-¢, And any two members of this series connected together by the sign of equality express a conclusion, whether drawn by Spinoza or not, which is a legitimate consequence of his system. Thus the equation Z=1-€, β expresses the sixth Proposition of his system, viz., One 228 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT substance cannot be produced by another. Similarly the equation Z=e, expresses his seventh Proposition, viz., ‘‘It pertains to the nature of substance to exist.” This a of deduction it is en 4 q P unnecessary to pursue. Spinoza applies it chiefly to the de- : duction according to his views of the properties of the Divine Nature, having first endeavoured to prove that the only sub- stance is God. In the steps of this process, there appear to me to exist some fallacies, dependent chiefly upon the am- biguous use of words, to which it will be necessary here to direct attention. [215] 18. In Prop. Ν᾿. itis endeavoured to show, that ‘‘ There cannot exist two or more substances of the same nature or attribute.” The proof is virtually as follows: If — there are more substances than one, they are distinguished either by attributes or modes ; if by attributes, then there is only one substance of the same attribute ; if by modes, then, laying aside these as non-essential, there remains no real © ground of distinction. Hence there exists but one substance of the same attribute. The assumptions here involved are in- consistent with those which are found in other parts of the — treatise. Thus substance, Def. 4, is apprehended by the intellect through the means of attribute. By Def. 6 it may have many attributes. One substance may, therefore, con- ceivably be distinguished from another by a difference in some of its attributes, while others remain the same. In Prop. VIII. it is attempted to show that, All substance is necessarily infinite. The proof is as follows. There ex- Ὁ ists but one substance, of one attribute, Prop. V. ; and it per- tains to its nature to exist, Prop. VII. It will, therefore, be of its nature to exist either as finite or infinite. But not as finite, for, by Def. 2 it would require to be bounded by another substance of the same nature, which also ought to exist zecessarily, Prop. VII. Therefore, there would be two substances of the same attribute, which is absurd, τῶν Ve Substance, therefore, is infinite, CLARKE AND SPINOZA 229 In this demonstration the word ‘‘ finite” is confounded with the expression, ‘‘ Finite in its own kind,” Def. 2. It is thus assumed that nothing can be finite, unless it is bounded by another thing of the same kind. This is not consistent with the ordinary meaning of the term. Spinoza’s use of the term finite tends to make space the only form of substance, and all existing things but affections of space, and this, I think, is really one of the ultimate foundations of his system. The first scholium applied to the above Proposition is re- markable. I give it in the original words: ‘‘Quum finitum esse revera sit ex parte negatio, et infinitum absoluta affir- _ matio existentiz alicujus nature, sequitur ergo ex sola Prop. VII. omnem substantiam debere esse infinitam.” Now this is in reality an assertion of the principle affirmed by Clarke, and controverted by [216] Butler (XIII. 11), that necessary existence implies existence in every part of space. Probably this principle will be found to lie at the basis of every attempt to demonstrate, a priorz, the existence of an Infinite Being. From the general properties of substance above stated, and the definition of God as the substance consisting of infinite attributes, the peculiar doctrines of Spinoza relating to the Divine Nature necessarily follow. As substance is self-ex- istent, free, causal in its very nature, the thing in which other things are, and by which they are conceived ; the same pro- perties are also asserted of the Deity. He is self-existent, Prop. XI. ; indivisible, Prop. XIII. ; the only substance, Prop. XIV. ; the Being in which all things are, and by which all pmings are conceived, Prop. XV. ; free, Prop. XVII. ; the immanent cause of all things, Prop. XVIII. The proof that God is the only substance is drawn from Def. 6, which is interpreted into a declaration that ‘‘God is the Being ab- solutely infinite, of whom no attribute which expresses the essence of substance can be denied.” Every conceivable attribute being thus assigned by definition to Him, and it being determined in Prop. V. that there cannot exist two substances of the same attribute, it follows that God is the only substance. 230 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Though the E¢hics of Spinoza, like a large portion οὔ. his other writings, is presented in the geometrical form, it — does not afford a good praxis for the symbolical method οὔ this work. Of course every train of reasoning admits, when ~ its ultimate premises are truly determined, of being treated by that method ; but in the present instance, such treatment scarcely differs, except in the use of letters for words, from the processes employed in the original demonstrations. Reasoning which consists so largely of a play upon terms defined as equivalent, is not often met with ; and it is rather on account of the interest attaching to the subject, than of the merits of the demonstrations, highly as by some they are esteemed, that I have devoted a few pages here to their exposition. 19. It is not possible, I think, to rise from the perusal of the arguments of Clarke and Spinoza without a deep con- viction of the futility of all endeavours to establish, entirely a priort, the existence [217] of an Infinite Being, His attri- butes, and His relation to the universe. The fundamental principle of all such speculations, viz., that whatever we can clearly conceive, must exist, fails to accomplish its end, even when its truth is admitted. For how shall the finite com- prehend the infinite? Yet must the possibility of such con- ception be granted, and in something more than the sense of a mere withdrawal of the limits of phenomenal existence, before any solid ground can be established for the knowledge, a priori, of things infinite and eternal. Spinoza’s affirma- tion of the reality of such knowledge is plain and explicit: ‘*Mens humana adequatum habet cognitionem externe et infinite essentie Dei” (Prop. XLVII., Part 2nd). Let this be compared with Prop. XXXIV., Part 2nd: ‘‘ Omnis idea que in nobis est absoluta sive adzquata et perfecta, vera est”; and with Axiom 6, Part Ist, ‘‘ Idea vera debet cum suo ideato convenire.” Moreover, this species of knowledge is made the essential constituent of all other knowledge : ‘“De natura rationis est res sub quadam eternitatis specie percipere”” (Prop. XLIV., Cor. II., Part 2nd). Were it said, CLARKE AND SPINOZA 231 that there is a tendency inthe human mind to rise in con- templation from the particular towards the universal, from the finite towards the infinite, from the transient towards the eternal; and that this tendency suggests to us, with _ high probability, the existence of more than sense perceives or understanding comprehends ; the statement might be ac- cepted as true for at least a large number of minds. There is, however, a class of speculations, the character of which must be explained in part by reference to other causes, — impatience of probable or limited knowledge, so often all that we can really attain to; a desire for absolute certainty where intimations sufficient to mark out before us the path of duty, but not to satisfy the demands of the speculative intellect, have alone been granted to us; perhaps, too, dis- satisfaction with the present scene of things. With the undue predominance of these motives, the more sober pro- cedure of analogy and probable induction falls into neglect. Yet the latter is, beyond all question, the course most adapted to our present condition. To infer the existence of an intelligent cause from the teeming evidences of sur- _ rounding design, to rise to the conception of a moral Governor ~of the world, from the study of [218] the constitution and the moral provisions of our own nature ;—these, though but the feeble steps of an understanding limited in its faculties and its materials of knowledge, are of more avail than the ambitious attempt to arrive at a certainty unattainable on the ground of natural religion. And as these were the most ancient, so are they still the most solid foundations, Revela- tion being set apart, of the belief that the course of this world is not abandoned to chance and inexorable fate. [219] CHAPTER XIV EXAMPLE OF THE ANALYSIS OF A SYSTEM OF EQUATIONS BY THE METHOD OF REDUCTION TO A SINGLE EQUI- VALENT EQUATION V=0, WHEREIN V SATISFIES THE CONDITION V(1—V)=0 1. LeET us take the remarkable system of premises employed in the previous Chapter, to prove that ‘‘ Matter is not a necessary being”; and suppressing the 6th premiss, viz., Motion exists,—examine some of the consequences which flow from the remaining premises. This is in reality to accept as true Dr. Clarke’s hypothetical principles ; but to suppose ourselves ignorant of the fact of the existence of motion. Instances may occur in which such a selection of a portion of the premises of an argument may lead to interest- ing consequences, though it is with other views that the present example has been resumed. The premises actually employed will be— 1 If matter is a necessary being, either the property of gravitation is necessarily present, or it is necessarily absent. 2. If gravitation is necessarily absent, and the world is not subject to any presiding intelligence, motion does not exist, 3. If gravitation is necessarily present, a vacuum is necessary. 4. If a vacuum is necessary, matter is not a necessary being. 5. If matter is a necessary being, the world is not subject to a presiding intelligence. If, as before, we represent the elementary propositions by the following notation, viz. : 232 Ἰ EXAMPLE OF ANALYSIS 233 += Matter is a necessary being, y=Gravitation is necessarily present, w = Motion exists, t= Gravitation is necessarily absent, z= The world is merely material, and not subject to a presiding intelligence, v= A vacuum is necessary, [220] we shall on expression of the premises and elimina- tion of the indefinite class symbols (Φ), obtain the following system of equations: xyt + xyf=o, lz7 = 0, YU=0, UX =O, xZ=0, in which for brevity 7 stands for 1—y, ¢ for 1—Z, and so on; whence, also 1—f=¢4, 1—y=y, &c. As the first members of these equations involve only positive terms, we can form a single equation by adding Meer tocether (Vill. Prop. Ils); vize: xyt + xy + γὸ τ Ux +x5 + ἔστ =o, and it remains to reduce the first member so as to cause it to satisfy the condition V(1 — V)=0. For this purpose we will first obtain its development with reference to the symbols # and y. The result is— (¢+d+0+F+cew)xy+(F+u+ 2+ tew)xy + (d+ fsw)xy + tzwxy =o. And our object will be accomplished by reducing the four coefficients of the development to equivalent forms, them- selves satisfying the condition required. Now the first coefficient is, since v-+v=I, 1+74+2+ few, which reduces to unity (IX. Prop. I.). The second coefficient is f+u+zst+lew ; 234 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT and its reduced form (X. 3) is Ζ- ἐσ τ 02 + tozw. The third coefficient, 7-+¢zw, reduces by the same method | to d+¢gwv ; and the last coefficient ¢zw needs no reduction. Hence the development becomes [221] xy t+ (F+ τὺ Ὁ 102 + lisw) xy + (Ὁ + ἐσευῦ)ὰν + L2wxy =o ; (1) and this is the form of reduction sought. 2. Now according to the principle asserted in Prop. III. Chap. X., the whole relation connecting any particular set — of the symbols in the above equation may be deduced by developing that equation with reference to the particular symbols in question, and retaining in the result only those — constituents whose coefficients are unity. Thus, if 2 and y are the symbols chosen, we are immediately conducted to the equation XY =O, whence we have pA — 2); Θ with the interpretation, // gravitation is necessarily present, matter 15 not a necessary being. Let us next seek the relation between and w. Develop- ing (1) with respect to those symbols, we get ( + ty + toy + tozy + tosy)xw + (ν + % + toy + C057) x + (ay + tsvy + tay) xw + DyXW =. The coefficient of rw, and it alone, reduces to unity. For 2027 + tozy = toy, and tvy+ toy =ty, and ty+ty=y, and lastly, y+y=1. This is always the mode in which such reductions take place. Hence we get XxW = 0, ο aa — x), of which the interpretation is, 17 motion extsts, matter ts not a necessary being. | EAAM PEER OH ANALYSTS 510 If, in like manner, we develop (1) with respect to # and 2, we get the equation XZ = x= ΘΟ ΘΟ 0 with the interpretation, /f matter ts a necessary being, the world ts merely material, and without a presiding intelligence. [222] This, indeed, is only the fifth premiss reproduced, but it shows that there is no other relation connecting the two elements which it involves. If we seek the whole relation connecting the elements 7, w, and y, we find, on developing (1) with reference to those symbols, and proceeding as before, XY + xWY =O. Suppose it required to determine hence the consequences of _ the hypothesis, ‘‘ Motion does not exist,” relatively to the questions of the necessity of matter, and the necessary pre- sence of gravitation. We find a I — W = Ah +5, With, αν — 0: The direct interpretation of the first equation is, 17} motzon does not exist, either matter is a necessary being, and gravt- tation ts not necessarily present, or matter ts not a necessary being. The reverse interpretation is, /f matter ts a necessary being, and gravitation not necessary, motion does not exist. In exactly the same mode, if we sought the full relation between 2, 2, and w, we should find xX2W+XZ=0. From this we may deduce Εἰ καθ Z=xw+—x, with xw=o. ο 236 THE CAW ΟΣ Δ ΙΕ fF Therefore, 77 the world ts merely matertal, and not subject to any presiding intelligence, either matter ts a necessary being, and motion does not exist, or matter ts not a necessary being. Also, reversely, If matter ἐς a necessary being, and there 7s no such thing as motion, the world ts merely material. 3. We might, of course, extend the same method to the de-[223]termination of the consequences of any complex hypothesis #, such as, ‘‘ The world is merely material, and without any presiding intelligence (z), but motion exists ” (w), with reference to any other elements of doubt or specula- tion involved in the original premises, such as, ‘‘ Matter is a necessary being” (%), ‘‘ Gravitation is a necessary quality of matter” (y).' We should, for this purpose, connect with the general equation (1) a new equation, 2; reduce the systems thus formed to a single equation V =o, in which V satisfies the condition V(1 — V)=o0, and proceed as above to determine the relation between w, x, and y, and finally « as a developed function of x and y. But it is very much better to adopt the methods of Chapters VIII. and IX. I shall here simply indicate a few results, with the leading steps of their deduction, and leave their verification to the reader’s choice. In the problem last mentioned we find, as the relation connecting 4, ἡ, w, and 2, XW + XWY + XWYZ =O. And if we write «=2y, and then eliminate the symbols + and y by the general problem, Chap. IX., we find XU + XU =O; whence I Roe uU=—-XV +OxXy4+—-X ; [9] O wherefore Cas “5. XW LY —= 0, ο Hence, [f the world ts merelv material and without a presida- EXAMPLE OF ANALYSIS 237 ing intelligence, and at the same time motion exists, matter ἦς not a necessary being. Now it has before been shown that z/ motion exists, matter ἧς not a necessary being, so that the above conclusion tells us even less than we had before ascertained to be (infer- _ entially) true. Nevertheless, that conclusion is the proper and complete answer to the question which was proposed, which was to determine simply the consequences of a certain complex hypothesis. [224] 4. It would thus be easy, even from the limited system of premises before us, to deduce a great variety of additional inferences, involving, in the conditions which are given, any proposed combinations of the elementary pro- positions. If the condition is one which is inconsistent with the premises, the fact will be indicated by the form of the solution. The value which the method will assign to the combination of symbols expressive of the proposed con- dition will be o. If, on the other hand, the fulfilment of the condition in question imposes no restriction upon the - propositions among which relation is sought, so that every combination of those propositions is equally possible, —the ~fact will also be indicated by the form of the solution. Ex- amples of each of these cases are subjoined. If in the ordinary way we seek the consequences which would flow from the condition that matter ts a necessary being, and at the same time that sotzon exists, as affecting the Propositions, The world ts merely matertal, and with- out a presiding intelligence, and Gravitation is necessarily present, we shall obtain the equation XI = 0, which indicates that the condition proposed is inconsistent with the premises, and therefore cannot be fulfilled. If we seek the consequences which would flow from the condition that Matter ἐς not a necessary being, and at the same time that Motion does exist, with reference to the same elements as above, viz., the absence of a presiding 238 THE LAWS OF THOU GH rT. intelligence, and the necessity of gravitation,—we obtain the following result, (1 — xt = 2 ys + —9( 1 — a) +2(1 —y) e+ 2(1 - 3) -- 2), which might literally be interpreted as follows : 47 matter ts not a necessary being, and motion exists, then either the world ts merely material and without a presiding intelligence, and gravitation ts necessary, or one of these two results follows without the other, or they both fail of being true. Wherefore of the four possible combinations, of which. some one is true of necessity, and of which of necessity one only can be true, it is [225] affirmed that any one may be true. Such a result is a truism—a mere necessary truth. Still it contains the only answer which can be given to the question proposed. I do not deem it necessary to vindicate against the charge of laborious trifling these applications. It may be requisite to enter with some fulness into details useless in themselves, in order to establish confidence in general principles and methods. When this end shall have been accomplished in the subject of the present inquiry, let all that has contri- buted to its attainment, but has afterwards been found super- — fluous, be forgotten. [226] CHAPTER XV THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC AND ITS MODERN EXTENSIONS, EXAMINED BY THE METHOD OF THIS TREATISE I. THE logical system of Aristotle, modified in its details, but unchanged in its essential features, occupies so important a place in academical education, that some account of its nature, and some brief discussion of the leading problems which it presents, seem to be called for in the present work. It is, I trust, in no narrow or harshly critical spirit that I approach this task. My object, indeed, is not to institute any direct comparison between the time-honoured system of the schools and that of the present treatise ; but, setting truth above all other considerations, to endeavour to exhibit the real nature of the ancient doctrine, and to remove one or two prevailing misapprehensions respecting its extent —and sufficiency. That which may be regarded as essential in the spirit and procedure of the Aristotelian, and of all cognate systems of Logic, is the attempted classification of the allowable forms of inference, and the distinct reference of those forms, col- lectively or individually, to some general principle of an axiomatic nature, such as the ‘‘ dictum of Aristotle”: What- soever is affirmed or denied of the genus may in the same sense be affirmed or denied of any species included under that genus. Concerning such general principles it may, I think, be observed, that they either state directly, but in an abstract form, the argument which they are supposed to elucidate, and, so stating that argument, affirm its validity ; or involve in their expression technical terms which, after definition, conduct us again to the same point, viz., the abstract statement of the supposed allowable forms of infer- 239 240 TLE EA SO a OC Gre ence. The idea of classification is thus a pervading element in those systems. Furthermore, they exhibit Logic as resolvable into two great branches, the one of which is occupied with the treatment of categorical, the other with that of hypothetical or [227] conditional propositions. The distinction is nearly identical with that of primary and secondary propositions in the present work. The discussion of the theory of categorical propositions is, in all the ordinary treatises of Logic, much more full and elaborate than that of hypothetical propositions, and is occupied partly with ancient scholastic distinctions, partly with the canons of de- ductive inference. To the latter application only is it neces- sary to direct attention here. : 2. Categorical propositions are classed under the four following heads, viz :— TYPE rst. Universal affirmative Propositions: All Y’s are X’s. 2nd. Universal negative ᾿ No Y’s are X’s. 3rd. Particular affirmative = SOMeC 2s atecy s. 4th. Particular negative Fr Some Y’s are not X’s. To these forms, four others have recently been added, so as to constitute in the whole eight forms (see the next article) susceptible, however, of reduction to six, and subject to relations which have been discussed with great fulness and ability by Professor De Morgan, in his Formal Logic. A scheme somewhat different from the above has been given to the world by Sir W. Hamilton, and is made the basis of a method of syllogistic inference, which is spoken of with very high respect by authorities on the subject of Logic. * The processes of Formal Logic, in relation to the above system of propositions, are described as of two kinds, viz., ‘“Conversion” and ‘‘Syllogism.” By Conversion is meant the expression of any proposition of the above kind in an equivalent form, but with a reserved order of terms. By Syllogism is meant the deduction from two such propositions having ἃ common term, whether subject or predicate, of some * Thomson’s Outlines of the Laws of Thought, p. 177. OF THE ARISTOTELIAN ΣΟ. 241 third proposition inferentially involved in the two, and form- ing the ‘‘ conclusion.” It is maintained by most writers on _ Logic, that those processes, and according to some, the single process of Syllogism, furnish the universal types of reason- ing, and that it is the business of the mind, in any train of demonstration, to conform itself, whether [228] consciously or unconsciously, to the particular models of the processes which have been classified in the writings of logicians. 3. The course which I design to pursue is to show how these processes of Syllogism and Conversion may be con- ducted in the most general manner upon the principles of the present treatise, and, viewing them thus in relation to a system of Logic, the foundations of which, it is conceived, have been laid in the ultimate laws of thought, to seek to determine their true place and essential character. The expressions of the eight fundamental types of proposi- tion in the language of symbols are as follows : Pom YS are ἃς, Y =Ux. 2c NO δὲ ατὸ Xs, y=U(1—X). 3. Some Y’s are X’s, 2), ON. 4. Some Y’s are not-X’s, vy =v(1 -- x). A 5. All not- Y’s are X’s, I—y=Ux. (1) 6. No not-Y’s are X’s, I-y=v(1-x). 7. Some not- Y’s are X’s, v(I —y) = vx. 8. Some not-Y’s are not-X’s, v(1 —y)=v(1—2). In referring to these forms, it will be convenient to apply, in a sense shortly to be explained, the epithets of logical quantity, ‘‘universal” and ‘‘ particular,” and of quality, ‘‘ affirmative ” and ‘‘ negative,” to the terms of propositions, and not to the propositions themselves. We shall thus con- sider the term ‘‘ All Y’s,” as universal-affirmative ; the term M.Y’s,” or ‘‘Some Y’s,” as particular-affirmative ; the term “ΑἹ! not- Y’s,” as universal-negative ; the term ‘‘ Some not- Y's,” as particular-negative. The expression ‘‘ No Y's,” is not properly a term of a proposition, for the true meaning of the proposition, ‘‘ No ΚΡ are _X’s,” is “" All Y’s are not-X’s.” The subject of that proposition is, therefore, universal- 16 242 Lie LAWS Of 7 OCUCT 7. affirmative, the predicate particular-negative. That there is a real distinction between the conceptions of ‘‘men” and τ ΠΟΥ men” is manifest. — [his distinction ts all: that | con- template when applying as above the designations of affirma- tive and negative, without, however, insisting upon the etymological propriety of the application to the terms of pro- positions. The designations positive and privative would have been more ap-[229]propriate, but the former term is already employed in a fixed sense in other parts of this work. 4. From the symbolical forms above given the laws of conversion immediately follow. Thus from the equation πε representing the proposition, ‘‘ All Y’s are X’s,” we deduce, on eliminating v, γα - x) =0, which gives by solution with reference to 1 -- 2, 1-x=<(1-y); oO the interpretation of which is, All not-X’s are not- Y’s. ΤΠ is anexample of what is called ‘‘ negative conver- sion.” In like manner, the equation sme v(1 τ representing the proposition, ‘‘No Y’s are X’s” gives () saa =) the interpretation of which is, ‘‘No X’s are Y's.” This is an example of what is termed simple conversion ; though it is in reality of the same kind as the conversion exhibited in the previousexample. All the examples of conversion which have been noticed by logicians are either of the above kind, or of that which consists in the mere transposition of the terms of a proposition, without altering their quality, as when we change vy =vx, representing, Some Y’s are X’s, into vx = vy, representing, Some X’s are Y’s ; OF THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC 243 or they involve a combination of those processes with some auxiliary process of limitation, as when from the equation y=vx, representing, All Y’s are X’s, we deduce on multiplication by Ὁ, vy = vx, representing, Some Y’s are X’s, and hence vx=vy, representing, Some X’s are Y’s. [230] In this example, the process of limitation precedes that of transposition. From these instances it is seen that conversion is a parti- cular application of a much more general process in Logic, of which many examples have been given in this work. That process has for its object the determination of any element in any proposition, however complex, as a logical function of the remaining elements. Instead of confining our attention to the subject and predicate, regarded as simple terms, we can take any element or any combination of elements entering into either of them ; make that element, or that combination, the ‘‘ subject” of a new proposition ; and determine what its predicate shall be, in accordance with the data afforded to us. It may be remarked, that even the simple forms of propositions enumerated above afford some ground for the application of such a method, beyond what the received laws of conversion appear to recognise. Thus the equation y =vx, representing, All Y’s are X’s, gives us, in addition to the proposition before deducted, the three following :— πὶ (1 — x) =0. There are no Y’s that are not-X’s. 2nd. τις. Things that are not-Y’s include all ἥ things that are not-X’s, and an indefinite remainder of things that are X’s. 3rd. x=y+ mG - )). Things that are X’s include all things Ἢ that are Y’s, and an indefinite re- mainder of things that are not-Y’s. 244 THE LAWS. OF THOUGHT These conclusions, it is true, merely place the given proposi- | tion in other and equivalent forms,—but. such and no more is the office of the received mode of ‘‘ negative conversion.” — Furthermore, these processes of conversion are not elemen- — tary, but they are combinations of processes more simple — than they, more immediately dependent upon the ultimate laws and axioms which govern the use of the symbolical ἢ instrument of [231] reasoning. This remark is equally ap- plicable to the case of Syllogism, which we proceed next to ~ consider. 5. The nature of syllogism is best seen in the particular instance. Suppose that we have the propositions, Alt Χ σέατο /-s, All Xs are.Z's. From these we may deduce the conclusion, All X’s are 2’s. This is a syllogistic inference. The terms Y and Z are@ called the extremes, and Y is called the middle term. The function of the syllogism generally may now be defined. Given two propositions of the kind whose species are tabu- lated in (1), and involving one middle or common term Y, — which is connected in one of the propositions with an extreme &X, in the other with an extreme Z ; required the relation connecting the extremes Y and Z. The term Y may appear in its affirmative form, as, All Y’s, Some Y’s; or in its negative form, as, All not-Y’s, Some not-Y’s; in either | proposition, without regard to the particular form which it assumes in the other. Nothing is easier than in particular instances to resolve the Syllogism by the method of this treatise. [ts resolution is, indeed, a particular application of the process for the re-— duction of systems of propositions. Taking the examples above given, we have, x= YY, VHS; whence by substitution, Δ 27,5. OF THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC 245 which is interpreted into All Χχὺς are: 735. Or, proceeding rigorously in accordance with the method developed in (VIII. 7), we deduce x(t-y)=0, γ(ι -- 2): ο. Adding these equations, and eliminating y, we have χει —2)=o; eee 0 Ὁ All WR are σι Ὁ And in the same way may any other case be treated. 6. Quitting, however, the consideration of special ex- amples, let us examine the general forms to which all syl- logism may be reduced, PROPOSITION I[ To deduce the general rules of Syllogism _By the general rules of Syllogism, I here mean the rules applicable to premises admitting of every variety both of quantity and of quality in their subjects and predicates, ex- cept the combination of two universal terms in the same pro- position. The admissible forms of propositions are therefore those of which a tabular view is given in (1). Let X and Y be the elements or things entering into the first premiss, Z and Y those involved in the second. Two cases, fundamentally different in character, will then present themselves. The terms involving Y will either be of lke or of unlike quality, those terms being regarded as of like quality when they both speak of ‘‘ Y’s,” or both of ‘‘ Not- Y’s,” as of unlike quality when one of them speaks of ‘‘ Y’s,” and the other of ‘‘Not-Y’s.” Any pair of premises, in which the former condition is satisfied, may be represented by the equations Ox — 0, (1) Ws=W'y ; (2) 246 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT for we can employ the symbol y to represent either ‘‘ All Y’s,” or “ΑἹ! not- Y’s,” since the interpretation of the symbol is purely conventional. If we employ y in the sense of «ΑἹ not- Y’s,” then 1—y will represent ‘‘ All Y's,” and no other change will be introduced. An equal freedom is per- ᾿ 2 : a Ἂν ME bea ΝΣ, af: 3 ἣν mitted with respect to the symbols x and 2, so that the : equations (1) and (2) may, by properly assigning the inter- — pretations of 4, 7, and z, be made to represent all varieties in the combination of premises dependent upon the guality ᾿ of the respective terms. Again, by assuming proper inter- : pretations to the symbols Ὁ, σ΄, w, w’, in those equations, all varieties with reference to guanizty may also be [233] — represented. Thus, if we take v=1, and represent by σ΄ a class indefinite, the equation (1) will represent a universal — proposition according to the ordinary sense of that term, ζ.6., a proposition with universal subject and particular pre- elite Rate arn iy dicate. We may, in fact, give to subject and predicate in ἢ either premiss whatever guantztzes (using this term in the scholastic sense) we please, except that by hypothesis, they i must not both be universal. The system (1), (2), repre- sents, therefore, with perfect generality, the possible com- binations of premises which have like middle terms. 7. That our analysis may be as general as the equations to which it is applied, let us, by the method of this work, eliminate y from (1) and (2), and seek the expressions for x, Ι -- 2, and vx, in terms of g and of the symbols τ, ν΄, τὺ, w’. The above will include all the possible forms of the subject — of the conclusion. The form v(1 -- 1) is excluded, inasmuch — as we cannot from the interpretation vr=Some X’s, given in the premises, interpret v(1—%) as Some not-X’s. . The symbol v, when used in the sense of ‘‘ some,” applies to that term only with which it is connected in the premises. The results of the analysis are as follows : x =[vv'we"' + τίου —w)(1 -- w’) + ww'(1 -- v)(1 -- ΟἽ) Ἐ( -ο)ᾷ -- }}]6 Ὁ Ξ(ονζα - ΟἽ + 1-0} (1 - 2), αν OF THE ARISTOFELIAN: LOGIC 247 1-x«=[v(1-v'){ww'+(1-w)(1-w’)} +0(1 -w)w’ + ={o0(1 —w)(1 —w’)+ww'(1 —v)(1 -v') + (1 -v)(1 —w)} ]2 +[o(1 — woo" + 2{00'(1 -w')+1-v}](1-3), (II.) vx = {vv ww + =v (1 - w)(1- w!)}a+ (1 —w')(1 -- 2). (III.) Each of these expressions involves in its second member two terms, of one of which z is a factor, of the other 1 —z. But syllogistic inference does not, asa matter of form, admit of contrary classes in its conclusion, as of Z’s and not-Z’s together. [234] We must, therefore, in order to determine the rules of that species of inference, ascertain under what conditions the second members of any of our equations are reducible to a single term. The simplest form is (III.), and it is reducible to a single term if w’=1. The equation then becomes Vx = UU'WE, (3) the first member is identical with the extreme in the first premiss ; the second is of the same quantity and quality as “the extreme in the second premiss. For since w’=1, the second member of (2), involving the middle term y, is uni- versal; therefore, by the hypothesis, the first member is particular, and therefore, the second member of (3), involv- ing the same symbol w in its coefficient, is particular also. Hence we deduce the following law. CONDITION OF INFERENCE.—One middle term, at least, universal. RULE OF INFERENCE.—FE quate the extremes. From an analysis of the equations (I.) and (II.), it will further appear, that the above is the only condition of syl- logistic inference when the middle terms are of like quality. Thus the second member of (I.) reduces to a single term, if w’=1 and v=1; and the second member of (II.) reduces to a single term, if w’=1, v=1, w=1. Ineach of these cases, 248 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT it is necessary that w’=1, the solely sufficient condition — before assigned. Consider, secondly, the case in which the middle terms . are of unlike quality. The premises may then be represented © under the forms Ὁ Ξ vy, (4) : we=w'(1—Yy); (5) and if, as before, we eliminate y, and determine the ex- | pressions of 4, 1—%, and vz, we get x =[vu'(1 —w)w' + = {z020'(1 —v)+(1-v)(1-v)(1 -w) +u (1 —-w)(1 —w’)}|z + [vow +={(1 - γα -- σ) τ σα -- «ὐ}] -- 2. (IV) [235] ,- x [ww'v +0(1 —v)(1 -- w) + = {zoe (1 - ) +(1-v)(1 -- σγ -- τ) +0 (1 -w)(1 —w’)} 2 +[o(1 -ογ)ετίσα -w')+(1-v)(1-v)} (1-2). (V.) ! vx = {vv' (τ — w)w’ + ~ov' (1 —w)(1 —w’)}z + {vv'w' + sou! (1 —w')}(1-2). (VI.) Now the second member of (VI.) reduces to a single term relatively to z, if w=1, giving x= (υστυ' + 200'(t -- τυΎ}(ι -- 2); the second member of which is opposite, both in quantity and quality, to the corresponding extreme, wz, in the second premiss. For since w=1, wz is universal. But the factor vv’ indicates that the term to which it is attached is particular, since by hypothesis v and v’ are not both equaltos. Hence we deduce the following law of inference in the case of like middle terms: FIRST CONDITION OF INFERENCE. —Az least one universal extreme. RULE OF INFERENCE.—Change the quantity and quality of that extreme, and equate the result to the other extreme. OF THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC 240 Moreover, the second member of (V.) reduces to a single ferm if v'=1, w =1; it then gives heer {v2 + τα - v)w}s. Now since v’=1, w’=1, the middle terms of the premises are both universal, therefore the extremes uv, wz, are par- ticular. But in the conclusion the extreme involving + is opposite, both in quantity and quality, to the extreme vz in the first premiss, while the extreme involving z agrees both in quantity and quality with the corresponding extreme wz in the second premiss. Hence the following general law: [236] SECOND CONDITION OF INFERENCE.— Two univer- sal middle terms. RULE OF INFERENCE.—Change the quantity and quality of etther extreme, and equate the result to the other extreme unchanged. There are in the case of unlike middle terms no other conditions or rules of syllogistic inference than the above. Thus the equation (1V.), though reducible to the form of a syllogistic conclusion, when w=1 and v=1, does not “thereby establish a new condition of inference; since, by what has preceded, the single condition v=1, or w=1, would suffice. 8. The following examples will sufficiently illustrate the general rules of syllogism above given : I. All Y’s are X’s. AllZ’s are: V's: This belongs to Case 1. All Y’s is the universal middle term. The extremes equated give as the conclusion All Z’s are X’s; the universal term, All Z’s, becoming the subject ; the par- ticular term (some) X’s, the predicate. 2. All Χ s are. V/s. No Z’s are Y’s. 250 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT The proper expression of these premises is AliX’s are) ‘s; All Z’s are ποι: Y’s. They belong to Case 2, and satisfy the first condition of ἡ inference. The middle term, Y’s, in the first premiss, is ἢ particular-affrmative ; that in the second premiss, not- Y’s, particular-negative. If we take all Z’s as the universal ex- treme, and change its quantity and quality according to the rule, we obtain the term Some not-Z’s, and this equated with the other extreme, All X’s, gives, All X’s are not-2’s, z.e., No X’s are Z’s. If we commence with the other universal extreme, and pro- ceed similarly, we obtain the equivalent result, No Z’s are X’s. [237] Be All Y's are Xs: All not- Y’s are Z’s. Here also the middle terms are unlike in quality. The pre- mises therefore belong to Case 2, and there being two uni- versal middle terms, the second condition of inference is satisfied. If by the rule we change the quantity and quality of the first extreme, (some) X’s, we obtain All not-X’s, which, equated with the other extreme, gives All not-X’s are Z’s. The reverse order of procedure would give the equivalent result, All not-Z’s are X’s. The conclusions of the two last examples would not be re- cognised as valid in the scholastic system of Logic, which virtually requires that the subject of a proposition should be affirmative. They are, however, perfectly legitimate in them- selves, and the rules by which they are determined form un- doubtedly the most general canons of syllogistic inference. The process of investigation by which they are deduced will probably appear to be of needless complexity ; and it is cer- tain that they might have been obtained with greater facility, OF THE ARISTOTELIAN LOGIC ΖΕῚ « and without the aid of any symbolical instrument whatever. It was, however, my object to conduct the investigation in the most general manner, and by an analysis thoroughly exhaustive. With this end in view, the brevity or prolixity of the method employed is a matter of indifference. Indeed the analysis is not properly that of the syllogism, but of a much more general combination of propositions ; for we are permitted to assign to the symbols Ὁ, σ΄, w, w’, any class- interpretations that we please. To illustrate this remark, I will apply the solution (I.) to the following imaginary case : Suppose that a number of pieces of cloth striped with different colours were submitted to inspection, and that the two following observations were made upon them : Ist. That every piece striped with white and green was also striped with black and yellow, and vce versa. 2nd. That every piece striped with red and orange was also striped with blue and yellow, and vice versa. [238] Suppose it then required to determine how the pieces marked with green stood affected with reference to the colours white, black, red, orange, and blue. Here (1) we assume 7— white, τ orecn. Φι black, 7 — yellow, w=red, =orange, w’=blue, the expression of our premises will be IX =U, Ws=W'y, agreeing with the system (1) (2). The equation (I.) then leads to the following conclusion : Pieces striped with green are either striped with orange, white, black, red, and blue, together, all pieces possessing which character are included in those striped with green ; or they are striped with orange, white, and black, but not with red or blue; or they are striped with orange, red, and blue, _ but not with white or black ; or they are striped with orange, but not with white or red; or they are striped with white and black, but not with blue or orange; or they are striped neither with white nor orange. Considering the nature of this conclusion, neither the 252 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT symbolical expression (I.) by which it is conveyed, nor the analysis by which that expression is deduced, can be con- sidered as needlessly complex. | 9. The form in which the doctrine of syllogism has been presented in this chapter affords ground for an important observation. We have seen that in each of its two great divisions the entire discussion is reducible, so far, at least, as concerns the determination of rules and methods, to the analysis of a pair of equations, viz., of the system (1), (2), when the premises have like middle terms, and of the system (4), (5), when the middle terms are unlike. Moreover, that analysis has been actually conducted by a method founded upon certain general laws deduced immediately from the con- stitution of language, Chap. II., confirmed by the study of the operations of the human mind, Chap. IILI., and proved to be applicable to the analysis of all systems of equations whatever, by which propositions, or combination of proposi- tions, can be represented, Chap. VIII. Here, then, we have the means of definitely resolving the question, whether syllogism is indeed the fundamental type of reasoning, — whether [239] the study of its laws is co-extensive with the study of deductive logic. For if it be so, some indication of the fact must be given in the systems of equations upon the analysis of which we have been engaged. It cannot be conceived that syllogism should be the one essential process of reasoning, and yet the manifestation of that process present nothing indicative of this high quality of pre-eminence. No sign, however, appears that the discussion of all systems of equations expressing propositions is involved in that of the particular system examined in this chapter. And yet writers on Logic have been all but unanimous in their assertion, not merely of the supremacy, but of the universal sufficiency of syllogistic inference in deductive reasoning. The language of Archbishop Whately, always clear and definite, and on the subject of Logic entitled to peculiar attention, is very ex- press on this point. ‘‘ For Logic,” he says, ‘‘ which is, as it were, the Grammar of Reasoning, does not bring forward OR PHP ARTS OTELIAN LOGIC 253 the regular Syllogism as a dzstinct mode of argumentation, de- signed to be substituted for any other mode ; but as the form to which al/ correct reasoning may be ultimately reduced.” * And Mr. Mill, in a chapter of his System of Logic, entitled, ‘“‘Of Ratiocination or Syllogism,” having enumerated the ordinary forms of syllogism, observes, ‘‘ All valid ratiocina- tion, all reasoning by which from general propositions pre- viously admitted, other propositions, equally or less general, are inferred, may be exhibited in some of the above forms.” And again : ‘‘ Weare therefore at liberty, in conformity with the general opinion of logicians, to consider the two ele- mentary forms of the first figure as the universal types of all correct ratiocination.” In accordance with these views it has been contended that the science of Logic enjoys an immunity from these conditions of imperfection and of progress to which all other sciences are subject ;+ and its origin from the - travail of one mighty mind of old has, by a somewhat daring metaphor, been compared to the mythological birth of Pallas. As Syllogism isa species of elimination, the question before us manifestly resolves itself into the two following ones :— ist. Whether all elimination is reducible to Syllogism ; _ 2ndly. Whe-[240]ther deductive reasoning can with propriety be regarded as consisting only of elimination. I believe, upon careful examination, the true answer to the former question to be, that it is always theoretically possible so to resolve and combine propositions that elimination may sub- sequently be effected by the syllogistic canons, but that the process of reduction would in many instances be constrained and unnatural, and would involve operations which are not syllogistic. To the second question I reply, that reasoning cannot, except by an arbitrary restriction of its meaning, be confined to the process of elimination. No definition can suffice which makes it less than the aggregate of the methods which are founded upon the laws of thought, as exercised upon propositions ; and among those methods, the process * Elements of Logic, p. 13, ninth edition. + Introduction to Kant’s δορά. 254 THE LAWS OF THOCGH of elimination, eminently important as it is, occupies only a — place. Much of the error, as I cannot but regard it, which pre- vails respecting the nature of the Syllogism and the extent of its office, seems to be founded in a disposition to regard all those truths in Logic as przmary which possess the character of simplicity and intuitive certainty, without inquiring into the relation which they sustain to other truths in the Science, or to general methods in the Art, of Reasoning. Arristotle’s dictum de omni et nullo is a self-evident principle, but it is not found among those #étzmate laws of the reasoning faculty to which all other laws, however plain and self-evident, admit of being traced, and from which they may in strictest order of scientific evolution be deduced. For though of every science the fundamental truths are usually the most simple of apprehension, yet is not that simplicity the criterion by which their title to be regarded as fundamental must be judged. This must be sought for in the nature and extent of the structure which they are capable of supporting. Tak- ing this view, Leibnitz appears to me to have judged cor- rectly when he assigned to the ‘‘ principle of contradiction ” a fundamental place in Logic :* for we have seen the conse- quences of that law of thought of which it is the axiomatic expression (III. 15). But enough has been said upon the nature of deductive inference and upon its constitutive ele- ments. The subject of [241] induction may probably re- ceive some attention in another part of this work. 10. It has been remarked in this chapter that the ordinary treatment of hypothetical, is much more defective than that of categorical, propositions. What is commonly termed the hypothetical syllogism appears, indeed, to be no syllogism at all. Let the argument— A 5 τ ἀπ ἋΣ But 4 is B, Therefore C is D, * Nouveaux Essais sur lentendement humain, Liv. IV. cap. 2; Théodicée, Pt. I. sec. 44. OF THE ARIS TOLPELIAN LOCTC 255 be put in the form— If the proposition X is true, Υ is true, But X is true, Therefore Y is true ; wherein by XY is meant the proposition A is B, and by Y, the proposition Cis D. It is then seen that the premises contain only two terms or elements, while a syllogism essen- tially involves three. The following would be a genuine hypothetical syllogism : If X is true, Y is true; Τὺ Υ is true, 21s tues If X is true, Z is true. After the discussion of secondary propositions in a former part of this work, it is evident that the forms of hypothetical syllogism must present, in every respect, an exact counter- part to those of categorical syllogism. Particular Proposi- tions, such as, ‘‘ Sometimes if XY is true, Y is true,” may be introduced, and the conditions and rules of inference de- duced in this chapter for categorical syllogisms may, with- out abatement, be interpreted to meet the corresponding cases in hypotheticals. 11. To what final conclusions are we then led respecting the nature and extent of the scholastic logic? I think to the following : that it is not a science, but a collection of scientific truths, too incomplete to form a system of themselves, and not sufficiently fundamental to serve as the foundation upon which a perfect system may rest. It does not, however, follow, that because the logic of the schools has been in- vested with attributes to which it [242] has no just claim, it is therefore undeserving of regard. A system which has been associated with the very growth of language, which has left its stamp upon the greatest questions and the most famous demonstrations of philosophy, cannot be altogether unworthy of attention. Memory, too, and usage, it must be admitted, have much to do with the intellectual processes ; and there are certain of the canons of the ancient logic which 256 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT have become almost inwoven in the very texture of thought in cultured minds. But whether the mnemonic forrns, in which the particular rules of conversion and syllogism have been exhibited, possess any real utility,—whether the very ~ skill which they are supposed to impart might not, with greater advantage to the mental powers, be acquired by the unassisted efforts of a mind left to its own resources, —are questions which it might still be not unprofitable to examine. As concerns the particular results deduced in this Chapter, it is to be observed, that they are solely designed to aid the inquiry concerning the nature of the ordinary or scholastic logic, and its relation to a more perfect theory of deductive reasoning. ΠΡ ΓΉΡΕΦΗ ὍΝ: [243] CREAT TEREX OF THE THEORY OF PROBABILITIES I. BEFORE the expiration of another year just two centuries will have rolled away since Pascal solved the first known question in the theory of Probabilities, and laid, in its solu- tion, the foundations of a science possessing no common share of the attraction which belongs to the more abstract of mathematical speculations. The problem which the Chevalier de Méré, a reputed gamester, proposed to the recluse of Port Royal (not yet withdrawn from the interests of science * by the more distracting contemplation of the ‘‘sreatness and the misery of man”), was the first of a long series of problems, destined to call into existence new methods in mathematical analysis, and to render valuable service in the practical concerns of life. - Nor does the interest of the subject centre merely in its mathematical connexion, or its associations of utility. The attention is repaid which is devoted to the theory of Probabilities as an independent object of speculation,—to the fundamental modes in which it has been conceived, —to the great second- ary principles which, as in the contemporaneous science of Mechanics, have gradually been annexed to it,—and, lastly, to the estimate of the measure of perfection which has been actually attained. I speak here of that perfection which consists in unity of conception and harmony of processes. Some of these points it is designed very briefly to consider in the present Chapter. * See in particular a letter addressed by Pascal to Fermat, who had solicited his attention to a mathematical problem (/o7¢ Royal, par M. de Sainte Beuve) ; also various passages in the collection of Fragments published by M. Prosper Faugere. 257 | 17, 258 THE PAWS OF ΤΉ ΟΕ 2, A distinguished writer * has thus stated the funda-_ mental definitions of the science : [244] ‘‘The probability of an event is the reason we — have to believe that it has taken place, or that it will take ᾿ lace; ‘ : ‘©The measure of the probability of an event is the ratio of the number of cases favourable to that event, to the total — number of cases favourable or contrary, and all equally — possible ” (equally like to happen). From these definitions it follows that the word prodadzlity, — in its mathematical acceptation, has reference to the state — of our knowledge of the circumstances under which an event — may happen or fail. With the degree of information which ~ we possess concerning the circumstances of an event, the : reason we have to think that it will occur, or, to use a single — term, our expectation of it, will vary. Probability is ex-- pectation founded upon partial knowledge. A perfect ac- quaintance with αὐ πα circumstances affecting the occurrence of an event would change expectation into certainty, and _ leave neither room nor demand for a theory of probabilities. 3. Though our expectation of an event grows stronger — with the increase of the ratio of the number of the known cases favourable to its occurrence to the whole number of equally possible cases, favourable or unfavourable, it would — be unphilosophical to affirm that the strength of that ex- pectation, viewed as an emotion of the mind, is capable οἵ. being referred to any numerical standard. The man off sanguine temperament builds high hopes where the timid despair, and the irresolute are lost in doubt. As subjects of scientific inquiry, there is some analogy between opinion and sensation. ‘The thermometer and the carefully prepared photographic plate indicate, not the intensity of the sensa- tions of heat and light, but certain physical circumstances which accompany the production of those sensations. So also the theory of probabilities contemplates the numerical measure of the circumstances upon which expectation is * Poisson, Recherches sur la Probabilité des Jugemens. Care oe OF THE THEORY OF PROBABILITIES Στ founded ; and this object embraces the whole range of its legitimate applications. The rules which we employ in life- _ assurance, and in the other statistical applications of the theory of probabilities, are altogether independent of the mental phenomena of expectation. They are founded upon the assumption that the future will bear a resem- [245]blance to the past; that under the same circum- stances the same event will tend to recur with a definite numerical frequency ; not upon any attempt to submit to calculation the strength of human hopes and fears. Now experience actually testifies that events of a given species do, under given circumstances, tend to recur with definite frequency, whether their true causes be known to us or unknown. Of course this tendency is, in general, only manifested when the area of observation is sufficiently large. The judicial records of a great nation, its registries of births and deaths, in relation to age and sex, &c., present a re- markable uniformity from year to year. Ina given language, or family of languages, the same sounds, and successions of sounds, and, if it be a written language, the same characters and successions of characters recur with determinate fre- quency. The key to the rude Ogham inscriptions, found in various parts of Ireland, and in which no distinction of words could at first be traced, was, by a strict application of this principle, recovered.* The same method, it is understood, has been applied Ὁ to the deciphering of the cuneiform records recently disentombed from the ruins of Nineveh by the enterprise of Mr. Layard. 4. Let us endeavour from the above statements and definitions to form a conception of the legitimate object of the theory of Probabilities. Probability, it has been said, consists in the expectation founded upon a particular kind of knowledge, viz., the * The discovery is due to the Rev. Charles Graves, Professor of Mathematics in the University of Dublin. —Vide Proceedings of the Royal [rish Academy, Feb. 14, 1848. Professor Graves informs me that he has verified the principle by con- structing sequence tables for all the European languages, + By the learned Orientalist, Dr. Edward Hincks. 260 THE LAWS CF ἀντ knowledge of the relative frequency of occurrence of events. Hence the probabilities of events, or of combinations of events, whether deduced from a knowledge of the particular constitution of things under which they happen, or derived from the long-continued observation of past series of their occurrences and failures, constitute, in all cases, our data. The probability of some [246] connected event, or com- | bination of events, constitutes the corresponding gu@eszttum, or object sought. Now in the most general, yet strict meaning of the term ‘‘ event,” every combination of events constitutes also an event. The simultaneous occurrence of two or more events, or the cccurrence of an event under given conditions, or in any conceivable connexion with other events, is still an event. Using the term in this liberty of application, the object of the theory of probabilities might be thus defined. Given the probabilities of any events, of whatever kind, to find the probability of some other event connected with them. 5. Events may be distinguished as simple or compound, the latter term being applied to such events as consist in a combination of simple events (I. 13). In this manner we might define it as the practical end of the theory under con- sideration to determine the probability of some event, simple or compound, from the given probabilities of other events, simple or compound, with which, by the terms of its defini- tion, it stands connected. Thus if it is known from the constitution of a die that there is a probability, measured by the fraction Η͂ that the result of any particular throw will be an ace, and if it is required to determine the probability that there shall occur one ace, and only one, in two successive throws, we may state the problem in the order of its data and its guesitum, as follows : First DATUM.—Probability of the event that the first throw will give an ace ==. OF 2HE- THEORY OF PROBABILITIES: 261 SECOND DATUM.—Probability of the event that the second throw will give an ace =5. QuASITUM.—Probability of the event that either the first throw will give an ace, and the second not an ace; or the 7 first will not give an ace, and the second will give one. Here the two data are the probabilities of simple events defined as the first throw giving an ace, and the second throw giving an ace. The quesitum is the probability of a compound event,—a certain disjunctive combination of the simple events [247] involved or implied in the data. Pro- bably it will generally happen, when the numerical con- ditions of a problem are capable of being deduced, as above, from the constitution of things under which they exist, that the data will be the probabilities of szmple events and the quzsitum the probability of a compound event dependent upon the said simple events. Such is the case with a class of problems which has occupied perhaps an undue share of the attention of those who have studied the theory of probabilities, viz., games of chance and skill, in the former of which some physical circumstance, as the constitution of a die, determines the probability of each possible step of the game, its issue being some definite combination of those meps; while in the latter, the relative. dexterity of the players, supposed to be known ὦ priort, equally determines the same element. But where, as in statistical problems, the elements of our knowledge are drawn, not from the study of the constitution of things, but from the registered ob- servations of Nature or of human society, there is no reason why the data which such observations afford should be the probabilities of simple events. On the contrary, the occur- rence of events or conditions in marked combinations (indi- cative of some secret connexion of a causal character) ‘suggests to us the propriety of making such concurrences profitable for future instruction by a numerical record of their frequency. Now the data which observations of this kind afford are the probabilities of compound events. The 262 LHE LAWS OF THOUGHT solution, by some general method, of problems in which such data are involved, is thus not only essential to the perfect development of the theory of probabilities, but also a perhaps necessary condition of its application to a large and practi- cally important class of inquiries. 6. Before we proceed to estimate to what extent known methods may be applied to the solution of problerns such as the above, it will be advantageous to notice, that there is another form under which all questions in the theory of probabilities may be viewed ; and this form consists in sub- stituting for evexts the propositions which assert that those events have occurred, or will occur; and viewing the ele- ment of numerical probability as having reference to the truth of those propositions, not to the oc-[248 ]currence of the events concerning which they make assertion. Thus, instead of considering the numerical fraction 2. as expressing the pro- bability of the occurrence of an event £, let it be viewed as representing the probability of the truth of the proposition “ΧΟ, which asserts that the event A will occur. Similarly, instead of any probability, g, being considered as referring to some compound event, such as the concurrence of the events # and F, let it represent the probability of the truth of the proposition which asserts that # and F will jointly occur ; and in like manner, let the transformation be made from disjunctive and hypothetical combinations of events to disjunctive and conditional propositions. Though the new application thus assigned to probability is a necessary con- comitant of the old one, its adoption will be attended with a practical advantage drawn from the circumstance that we have already discussed the theory of propositions, have defined their principal varieties, and established methods for determining, in every case, the amount and character of their mutual dependence. Upon this, or upon some equiva- lent basis, any general theory of probabilities must rest. 1 do not say that other considerations may not in certain cases of applied theory be requisite. The data may prove insufficient for definite solution, and this defect it may be Ee ne Re: are a ΨΥ ΤΠ ΄'- μι a se ἘΝ ee ee es eee ket See OF THE Thon y OF PROBABILITIES. «262 thought necessary to supply by hypothesis. Or, where the statement of large numbers is involved, difficulties may arise after the solution, from this source, for which special methods of treatment are required. But in every instance, some form of the general problem as above stated (Art. 4) is involved, and in the discussion of that problem the proper and peculiar work of the theory consists. I desire it to be observed, that to this object the investigations of the following chapters are mainly devoted. It is not intended to enter, except incidentally, upon questions involving supplementary hypo- theses, because it is of primary importance, even with re- ference to such questions (I. 17), that a general method, founded upon a solid and sufficient basis of theory, be first established. 7. The following is a summary, chiefly taken from Laplace, of the principles which have been applied to the solution of questions of probability. They are consequences of its fundamental defini-[249]tions already stated, and may be regarded as indicating the degree in which it has been found possible to render those definitions available. PRINCIPLE Ist. If p be the probability of the occurrence of any event, 1 —/ will be the probability of its non-occurrence. 2nd. The probability of the concurrence of two inde- pendent events is the product of the probabilities of those events. 3rd. The probability of the concurrence of two depen- dent events is equal to the product of the probability of one of them by the probability that if that event occur, the other will happen also, 4th. The probability that if an event, 55, take place, an event, /, will also take place, is equal to the probability of the concurrence of the events / and F, divided by the pro- -bability of the occurrence of 2. 5th. The probability of the occurrence of one or the other of two events which cannot concur is equal to the sum of their separate probabilities. 6th. If an observed event can only result from some one 264. THE LAWS OF THOUGHT of different causes which are a przort equally probable, the probability of any one of the causes is a fraction whose | numerator is the probability of the event, on the hypothesis of the existence of that cause, and whose denominator is the — sum of the similar probabilities relative to all the causes, 7th. The probability of a future event is the sum of the — products formed by multiplying the probability of each cause — by the probability that if that cause exists, the said future — event will take place. 8. Respecting the extent and the relative sufficiency οὐ these principles, the following observations may be made. ist. It is always possible, by the due combination of these principles, to express the probability of a compound event, dependent in any manner upon independent simple events whose distinct probabilities are given. A very large pro- portion of the problems which have been actually solved are of this kind, and the difficulty attending their solution has not arisen from the insufficiency of the indications furnished by the theory of probabilities, but from the need of an analysis which should render [250] those indications avail- able when functions of large numbers, or series consisting of many and complicated terms, are thereby introduced. It may, therefore, be fully conceded, that all problems having for their data the probabilities of independent simple events fall within the scope of received methods. 2ndly. Certain of the principles above enumerated, and especially the sixth and seventh, do not presuppose that all the data are the probabilities of simple events. In their peculiar application to questions of causation, they do, how- ever, assume, that the causes of which they take account are mutually exclusive, so that no combination of them in the production of an effect is possible. If, as before explained, we transfer the numerical probabilities from the events with which they are connected to the propositions by which those events are expressed, the most general problem to which the aforesaid principles are applicable may be stated in the following order of data and guesita. * ht Se OF THE THEORY OF PROBABILITIES 265 DATA ist. The probabilities of the z conditional propositions : If the cause A, exist, the event & will follow; 9 As ” i ” 3) ihe 2) » 2) 2nd. The condition that the antecedents of those pro- positions are mutually conflicting, REQUIREMENTS The probability of the truth of the proposition which de- clares the occurrence of the event / ; also, when that pro- position is known to be true, the probabilities of truth of the several propositions which affirm the respective occurrences of the causes A,, A,. . A,. Here it is seen, that the data are the probabilities of a series of compound events, expressed by condttional pro- positions. But the system is obviously a very limited and particular one. For the antecedents of the propositions are subject to the condition of being mutually exclusive, and Ehere is but one consequent, the event 2, in the whole system. It does not follow, from our [251] ability to dis- cuss such a system as the above, that we are able to resolve problems whose data are the probabilities of azy system of conditional propositions ; far less that we can resolve pro- blems whose data are the probabilities of any system of pro- positions whatever. And, viewing the subject in its material rather than its formal aspect, it is evident, that the hypothesis of exclusive causation is one which is not often realized in the actual world, the phenomena of which seem to be, usually, the products of complex causes, the amount and character of whose co-operation is unknown. Such is, without doubt, the case in nearly all departments of natural or social inquiry in which the doctrine of probabilities holds out any new promise of useful applications. g. To the above principles we may add another, which 266 THE TAWS Of FHOUGTT. has been stated in the following terms by the Savilian Pro- fessor of Astronomy in the University of Oxford.* ‘Principle 8. If there be any number of mutually ex- clusive hypotheses, /,, ἅς, 43, . . of which the probabilities relative to a particular state of information are 2., 24» 23» - - and if new information be given which changes the proba- bilities of some of them, suppose of %,,,, and all that follow, without having otherwise any reference to the rest ; then the probabilities of these latter have the same ratios to one another, after the new information, that they had before, that is, Pit hot P's + +t BP m=Pi i Poi Pg + - +t Pm where the accented letters denote the values after the new information has been acquired.” This principle is apparently of a more fundamental char- acter than the most of those before enumerated, and perhaps it might, as has been suggested by Professor Donkin, be regarded as axiomatic. It seems indeed to be founded in the very definition of the measure of probability, as ‘‘the ratio of the number of cases favourable to an event to the total number of cases favourable or contrary, and all equally possible.” For, adopting this definition, it is evident that in whatever proportion the number of equally [252] possible cases is diminished, while the number of favourable cases remains unaltered, in exactly the same proportion will the probabilities of any events to which these cases have reference be increased. And as the new hypothesis, viz., the diminu- tion of the number of possible cases without affecting the number of them which are favourable to the events in question, increases the probabilities of those events in a constant ratio, the relative measures of those probabilities remain unaltered. If the principle we are considering be then, as it appears to be, inseparably involved in the very definition of probability, it can scarcely, of ztself, conduct us further than the attentive study of the definition would alone do, in the solution of * **On certain Questions relating to the Theory of Probabilities” ; by W. F. Donkin, M.A., F.R.S., &c. Philosophical Magazine, May, 1851. OF (he THEORY OF PROBABILITIES "δ᾽ problems. From these considerations it appears to be doubt- ful whether, without some aid of a different kind from any that has yet offered itself to our notice, any considerable advance, either in the theory of probabilities as a branch of speculative knowledge, or in the practical solution of its pro- blems can be hoped for. And the establishment, soledy upon the basis of any such collection of principles as the above, of a method universally applicable to the solution of problems, without regard either to the number or to the nature of the propositions involved in the expression of their data, seems to be impossible. For the attainment of such an object other elements are needed, the consideration of which will occupy the next Chapter. ΠΤ aaa [253] CHAPTER ov il DEMONSTRATION OF A GENERAL METHOD FOR THE SOLUTION _ OF PROBLEMS IN THE THEORY OF PROBABILITIES | 1, IT has been defined (XVI. 2), that ‘‘ the measure of the probability of an event is the ratio of the number of cases — favourable to that event, to the total number of cases favour- | able or unfavourable, and all equally possible.” In the ~ following investigations the term probability will be used in — the above sense of ‘‘ measure of probability.” : From the above definition we may deduce the following — conclusions. . I. When it is certain that an event will occur, the proba-_ bility of that event, in the above mathematical sense, is 1. _ For the cases which are favourable to the event, and the cases" which are possible, are in this instance the same. | Hence, also, if be the probability that an event 4 will happen, 1—f will be the probability that the said event will not happen. To deduce this result directly from the defini- tion, let # be the number of cases favourable to the event | +, nthe number of cases possible, then 2 — is the number of cases unfavourable to the event 2. Hence, by definition, κι = probability that x will happen. see probability that x will not happen. But 71 --- mM m on a ee: 2. II. The probability of the concurrence of any two events is the product of the probability of either of those events by the probability that if that event occur, the other will occur also. 268 GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 269 Let m be the number of cases favourable to the happen- ing of the first event, and 7 the number of equally possible cases unfavourable to it; then the probability of the first Of the m cases favour- : 772 event is, by defini-[254 ]tion, y [254] oer able to the first event, let 7 cases be favourable to the con- junction of the first and second events, then, by definition, 3 is the probability that if the first event happen, the second also will happen. Multiplying these fractions together, we have Cee Tce m+n m m+n- ; rs But the resulting fraction τεῖος has for its numerator the number of cases favourable to the conjunction of events, and for its denominator, the number 772-22 of possible cases. Therefore, it represents the probability of the joint occurrence of the two events. Hence, if f be the probability of any event 4, and g the probability that if # occur y will occur, the probability of the conjunction xy will be pg. Pile Phe probability thateit ancevent occur; the-event will occur, is a fraction whose numerator is the probability of their joint occurrence, and denominator the probability of the occurrence of the event %. This is an immediate consequence of Principle II. IV. The probability of the occurrence of some one of a series of exclusive events is equal to the sum of their separate probabilities. For let z be the number of possible cases ; #, the number of those cases favourable to the first event ; mm, the number of cases favourable to the second, &c. Then the separate My, ἜΡΟΝ 771 ' probabilities of the events are ΣᾺ: ae &c. Again, as the events are exclusive, none of the cases favourable to one of them is favourable to another ; and, therefore, the number of cases favourable to some one of the series will be #z,+ mm, . . , 270 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT 4 ‘ and the probability of some one of the series happenings will be M,+Ms-:* But this is the sum of the previous : 7 : fractions, 72, “2, &c. Whence the principle is manifest. [255] 2. DEFINITION.—Two events are said to be indedil ὃ pendent when the probability of the happening of either of © them is unaffected by our expectation of the occurrence οὐ failure of the other. | From this definition, combined with Principle II., we have — the following conclusion : V. The probability of the concurrence of two independent events is equal to the product of the separate probabilities of — those events. A For if p be the probability of an event 7, g that of an event © y regarded as quite independent of %, then is g also the pro- : bability that if x occur y will occur. Hence, by Principle II., — p@ is the probability of the concurrence of 4 and y. Under the same circumstances, the probability that a will occur and y not occur will be p(1—g). For 2 is the proba- : bility that x will occur, and 1—g the probability that y will not occur. In like manner (1—p)(1—g¢) will be the proba- bility that both the events fail of occurring. 3. There exists yet another principle, different in kind from the above, but necessary to the subsequent investigations of this Chapter, before proceeding to the explicit statement of which I desire to make one or two preliminary observations, I would, in the first place, remark that the distinction be- tween simple and compound events is not one founded in the ~ nature of events themselves, but upon the mode or connexion in which they are presented to the mind. How many © separate particulars, for instance, are implied in the terms ‘© To be in health,” “Το prosper,” &c., each of which might still be regarded as expressing a ‘‘simple event”? The prescriptive usages of language, which have assigned to par- ticular combination of events single and definite appellations, and have left unnumbered other combinations to be expressed — GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 271 by corresponding combinations of distinct terms or phrases, is essentially arbitrary. When, then, we designate as simple events those which are expressed by a single verb, or by what grammarians term a single sentence, we do not thereby imply any real simplicity in the events themselves, but use the term solely with reference to grammatical expression. [256] 4. Now if this distinction of events, as simple or compound, is not founded in their real nature, but rests upon the accidents of language, it cannot affect the question of their mutual dependence or independence. If my knowledge of two simple events is confined to this particular fact, viz., that the probability of the occurrence of one of them is f, and that of the other g ; then I regard the events as independent, and thereupon affirm that the probability of their joint occurrence is fg. But the ground of this affirmation is not that the events are simple ones, but that the data afford no infor- mation whatever concerning any connexion or dependence between them. When the probabilities of events are given, but all information respecting their dependence withheld, the mind regards them as independent. And this mode of thought is equally correct whether the events, judged accord- _ing to actual expression, are simple or compound, z.eé., whether each of them is expressed by a single verb or by a combination of verbs. 5. Let it, however, be supposed that, together with the probabilities of certain events, we possess some definite in- formation respecting their possible combinations, For ex- ample, let it be known that certain combinations are excluded from happening, and therefore that the remaining combina- tions alone are possible. Then still is. the same general principle applicable. The mode in which we avail ourselves of this information in the calculation of the probability of any ‘conceivable issue of events depends not upon the nature of the events whose probabilities and whose limits of possible connexion are given. It matters not whether they are simple or compound. It is indifferent from what source, or by what methods, the knowledge of their probabilities and of their 272 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT — connecting relations has been derived. We must regard the events as independent of any connexion beside that of which we have information, deeming itt of no consequence whether such information has been explicitly conveyed tous in the data, — or thence deduced by logical inference. And this leads us to the statement of the general principle in question, viz.: VI. The events whose probabilities are given are to be regarded as independent of any connexion but such as is either expressed, or necessarily implied, in the data ; and the mode in [257] which our knowledge of that connexion is to be employed is independent of the nature of the source from which such knowledge has been derived. The practical importance of the above principle consists in the circumstance, that whatever may be the nature of the events whose probabilities are given,—whatever the nature of the event whose probability is sought, we are always able, by an application of the Calculus of Logic, to determine the expression of the latter event as a definite combination of the former events, and definitely to assign the whole of the implied relations connecting the former events with each other. In other words, we can determine what that com- bination of the given events is whose probability is required, and what combinations of them are alone possible. It follows then from the above principle, that we can reason upon those events as if they were simple events, whose conditions of possible combination had been directly given by experience, and of which the probability of some definite combination is sought. The possibility of a general method in probabilities depends upon this reduction. 6. As the investigations upon which we are about to enter are based upon the employment of the Calculus of Logic, it is necessary to explain certain terms and modes of expression which are derived from this application. By the event +, 1 mean that event of which the proposi- tion which affirms the occurrence is symbolically expressed by the equation Ft ‘ ἕ 4 Z re & 4 es GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 273 By the event (4, y, 2, ..), I mean that event of which _ the occurrence is expressed by the equation Dy Vee) τ Such an event may be termed a compound event, in relation to the simple events x, 7, 2, which its conception involves. Thus, if + represent the event ‘‘It rains,” y the event ‘‘ It thunders,” the separate occurrences of those events being expressed by the logical equations x=T, yY=!I, then will #(1—y)+y(1 —%) represent the event or state of [258] things denoted by the Proposition, ‘‘It either rains or thunders, but not both”; the expression of that state of things being x(1—y)+y(1 —x)=1. If for brevity we represent the function (4%, », 2, . .), used in the above acceptation by V, it is evident (VI. 13) that the law of duality Vir- V)=o will be identically satisfied. The simple events 4, y, 5. will be said to be ‘‘ conditioned ” when they are not free to occur in every possible combina- tion ; in other words, when some compound event depending upon them is precluded from occurring. Thus the events denoted by the propositions, ‘‘ It rains,” ‘‘ It thunders,” are ‘“conditioned” if the event denoted by the proposition, “ΤῸ thunders, but does not rain,” is excluded from happen- ing, so that the range of possible is less than the range of con- ceivable combination. Simple unconditioned events are by definition independent. Any compound event is similarly said to be conditioned if it is assumed that it can only occur under a certain con- dition, that is, in combination with some other event consti- tuting, by its presence, that condition. 7. We shall proceed in the natural order of thought, from simple and unconditioned, to compound and conditioned events. 18 274 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT PROPOSITION I ist. If p, φ, v are the respective probabilities of any uncon- ditioned simple events x,y, 2, the probability of any compound event V will be [V], this function [V] being formed ὄν changing, in the function V, the symbols x, y, 2 tntop, Φ, γ, ὅς. : andly. Under the same circumstances, the probability that — if the event V occur, any other event V' will also occur, will : be ae wherein [7 17] denotes the result obtained by multt- plying together the logical functions V and V’, and changing © in the vesult x, y, 8, &c. tnto p, gq, r, Ge. Let us confine our attention in the first place to the pos- ἢ [259 ]sible combinations of the two simple events, x and y, of | which the respective probabilities are and g. The primary : combinations of those events (V. 11), and their corresponding probabilities, are as follows : EVENTS PROBABILITIES XY, Concurrence of x andy, =f. x(1 -- γ), Occurrence of x without y, Ζ(1 -- 9). (ι -- x)y, Occurrence of y without x, (1 -- 2). (1 —x)(1 ~y), Conjoint failure of « and y, (1 —p)(1 - 4). We see that in these cases the probability of the compound event represented by a constituent is the same function of 2 and g as the logical expression of that event is of rand y; and it is obvious that this remark applies, whatever may be — the number of the simple events whose probabilities are given, and whose joint existence or fatlure is involved in the — compound event of which we seek the probability. Consider, in the second place, any dzsjunctzve combination of the above constituents. The compound event, expressed in ordinary language as the occurrence of ‘‘ either the event « without the event y, or the event y without the event +,” is symbolically expressed in the form x(1 —y)+9(1 —*), and | its probability, determined by Principles IV. and V., is PU-—g)+¢(1—-p). The latter of these expressions is the same function of and qg as the former is of x and y. And it is obvious that this is also a particular illustration of a GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 275 “ _ general rule. The events which are expressed by any two or more constituents are mutually exclusive. The only possible combination of them is a dzsyunctive one, expressed in ordinary language by the conjunction ov, in the language of symbolical logic by the sign +. Now the probability of the occurrence of some one out of a set of mutually exclusive events is the sum of their separate probabilities, and is ex- pressed by connecting the expression for those separate pro- babilities by the sign +. Thus the law above exemplified is seen to be general. The probability of any unconditioned event V will be found by changing in V the symbols x, y, me. . into 2, 9, 7... 8. Again, by Principle III., the probability that if the event V occur, the event V’ will occur with it, is expressed by a frac-[260]tion whose numerator is the probability of the joint occurrence of V and V’, and denominator the pro- bability of the occurrence of V. Now the expression of that event, or state of things, which is constituted by the joint occurrence of the events V and V’, will be formed by multiplying together the expressions V and Γ᾽ according to the rules of the Calculus of Logic ; since whatever constituents are found in both V and ”’ will appear in the product, and no others. Again, by what has just been shown, the probability of the event represented by that product will be determined by changing therein x, y, z into Pp, 7, *,.. Hence the numerator sought will be what [VV] by definition represents. And the denominator will be [V], wherefore PAZ, [7] 9g. For example, if the probabilities of the simple events ΠῚ», 2 are 2, g, r respectively, and it is required to find the probability that if either x or y occur, then either y or 2 will occur, we have for the logical expressions of the antecedent and consequent— Probability that if V occur, V’ will occur with it = Ist. Either x or y occurs, x(1 —y) +(1 — x). 2nd. Either y or z occurs, γ(1 — 2) + Ζᾷ -- y)- 276 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT If now we multiply these two expressions together according to the rules of the Calculus of Logic, we shall have for the expression of the concurrence of antecedent and consequent, x2(1 —y) ἘΚ — x)(1 -- 2). Changing in this result x, y, z into 2, g, 7, and similarly transforming the expression of the antecedent, we find for the probability sought the value prir—9) +91 - pit - 7) | διτ 2) tote) The special function of the calculus, in a case like the above, is to supply the office of the reason in determining what are the conjunctures involved at once in the consequent and the antecedent. But the advantage of this application is almost entirely [261] prospective, and will be made manifest in a subsequent proposition. PROPOSITION II 10. /¢t 7s known that the probabilities of certain simple events, X y, 2,..arep, gq, r,.. respectively when a certain condition V ts satisfied; V being in expression a function of 4,9, %,.. Regutred the absolute probabilities of the events %, y, &,.., that ts, the probabilities of thetr respective occur- rence independently of the condition V. Let 7’, 7’, 7, &c., be the probabilities. required, z.e. the probabilities of the events, x, y, z, . ., regarded not only as simple, but as independent events. Then by Prop. I. the probabilities that these events will occur when the condition V, represented by the logical equation V = 1, is satisfied, are [ΠΕ]. [ΠῚ we, VAR eee in which [¢V] denotes the result obtained by multiplying V by 2, according to the rules of the Calculus of Logic, and changing in the result x, y, z, into p’, g’, 7, &c. But the above conditioned probabilities are by hypothesis equal to p,q, 7%, .. respectively. Hence we have, GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES ‘277 [x7] [»7] [2] ἐπ 2 -- Ζ, =r, &c i eee I from which system of equations equal in number to the - quantities 2, g, 7,.., the values of those quantities may be determined. Now +V consists simply of those constituents in V of which xis a factor. Let this sum be represented by V,,, and in like manner let yV be represented by V,, &c. Our equa- tions then assume the form el ΕΠ where [17,] denotes the results obtained by changing in V, the symbols %, y, 2, &c., into ~’, g’, 7, &c. To render the meaning of the general problem and the prin-[262]ciple of its solution more evident, let us take the following example. Suppose that in the drawing of balls from an urn attention had only been paid to those cases in which the balls drawn were either of a particular colour, ‘‘white,” or of a particular composition, ‘‘ marble,” or were marked by both these characters, no record having been kept of those cases in which a ball that was neither white nor of marble had been drawn. Let it then have been found, that whenever the supposed condition was satisfied, there was a probability 2 that a white ball would be drawn, and a pro- bability g that a marble ball would be drawn: and from these data alone let it be required to find the probability that in the next drawing, without reference at all to the condition above mentioned, a white ball will be drawn ; also the probability that a marble ball will be drawn. Here if x represent the drawing of a white ball, y that of a marble ball, the condition V will be represented by the logical function xy χᾷ -—y)+ (1 —x)y. Hence we have Vi=xyta(r—y)=a, Vi=ayt(1-x)y=y; whence [V.j=2, [Y,)=93 278 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT and the final equations of the problem are , i 9 ἘΠῚ pg t+p-g7)t7(t-P) eae +P(t-9)+9-f) * from which we find Pe) ων Eman) i Ca 2 αν 7 7 It is seen that 2’ and g’ are respectively proportional to 2 and g, as by Professor Donkin’s principle they ought to be. The solution of this class of problems might indeed, by a . direct application of that principle, be obtained. To meet a possible objection, I here remark, that the above reasoning does not require that the drawings of a white and a marble ball should be independent, in virtue of — the physical constitution of the balls. The assumption of ἢ their independence is indeed involved in the solution, but it does not rest upon any [263] prior assumption as to the nature of the balls, and their relations, or freedom from ἢ relations, of form, colour, structure, &c. It is founded upon our total ignorance of all these things. Probability always has reference to the state of our actual knowledge, and its numerical value varies with varying information. PROPOSITION III 11. 70 determine in any question of probabilities the logical connexton of the quesitum with the data; that 75, to assign the event whose probability ἐς sought, as a logical function of the event whose probabilities are given. Let S, 7, &c., represent any compound events whose — probabilities are given, S and 7 being in expression known functions of the symbols z, J, 2, &c., representing simple ὦ events. Similarly let W represent any event whose proba- © bility is sought, W being also a known function of ὌΠ Pe: F We As. δ W must satisfy the fundamental law of duality, we are permitted to replace them by single logical symbols, s, ¢,..w. Assume then s= 5S, t=7, w=W. fot fein χρυ gs Be aD lia A ΜΟῚ ΟΡ es ci, Sy Sas GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 275 These, by the definition of S, 7,.. W, will bea series οἵ logical equations connecting the symbols s, ¢, .. w, with the symbols 4, y, 2 By the methods of the Calculus of Logic we can eliminate -from the above system any of the symbols 4, y, 2, . ., re- presenting events whose probabilities are not given, and de- termine w as a developed function of 5, ¢, &c., and of such of the symbols Ἐς», 2, &c., if any such there be, as corre- spond to events whose probabilities are given. The result will be of the form ww dt oh ΟΣ ο οΟ where A, δ, C, and D comprise among them all the possible constituents which can be formed from the symbols s, ¢, &c., z.e. from all the symbols representing events whose proba- bilities are given. The above will evidently be the complete expression of the relation sought. For it fully determines the event W, repre-[264]sented by the single symbol w, as a function or combination of the events similarly denoted by the symbols s, ¢, &c., and it assigns by the laws of the Calculus of Logic the condition 3) Ξ as connecting the events s, ¢, &c., among themselves. We may, therefore, by Principle VI., regard s, ¢, &c., as semple events, of which the combination w, and the condition with which it is associated D, are definitely determined. Uniformity in the logical processes of reduction being de- sirable, I shall here state the order which will generally be pursued, 12. By (VIII. 8), the primitive equations are reducible to the forms s(1 - S)+ S(1-5)=0; eels 1. aed {τ| ee W)+ ee ee under which they can be added together without impairing 280 THE SAWS OF THOUGHT their significance. We can then eliminate the symbols 4, y, 2, either separately or together. If the latter course is chosen, ~ it is necessary, after adding together the equations of the — system, to develop the result with reference to all the - symbols to be eliminated, and equate to o the product of all the coefficients of the constituents (VI1. 9). As w is the symbol whose expression is sought, we may ~ also, by Prop. III. Chap. IX., express the result of elimina- tion in the form Ew+ E'(1 -w)=o. E and E’ being successively determined by making in the general system (1), w=1 and w=o, and eliminating the symbols 4, y, z,.. Thus the single equations from which — E and £’ are to be respectively determined become si -—S)+ S(1-s)+41-7)+7U-4..+1-We=o0; “( -- 5) Ὁ δά -- 5). Δα -- Ζ2: ΖΕ -δ- We=o. Ἷ From these it only remains to eliminate x, y, z, &c., and to | determine w by subsequent development. [265] In the process of elimination we may, if needful, avail ourselves of the simplifications of Props. I. and II. Cha eX, 13. Should the data, beside informing us of the proba- bilities of events, further assign among them any explicit connexion, such connexion must be logically expressed, and the equation or equations thus formed be introduced into the general system. PROPOSITION IV 14. Given the probabilities of any system of events; to determine by a general method the consequent or derived pro- bability of any other event. As in the last Proposition, let S, 7, &c., be the events whose probabilities are given, W the event whose proba- bility is sought, these being known functions of x, Ve Se. Let us represent the data as follows: Probability of S=2; (1) Probability of 7=g; ᾿ GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 281 and so on, 2, g, &c., being known numerical values. If then we represent the compound event S by s, 7 by ¢, and W by w, we find by the last proposition, w=A+oB4+°C4-4D; (2) Ο Oo A, B, C, and D being functions of s, ¢, &c. Moreover the data (1) are transformed into TOD. 5— 7, Proba7z—a, Se: (3) Now the equation (2) is resolvable into the system w=A+gC ; D=0, (4) g being an indefinite class symbol (VI. 12). But since by the properties of constituents (V. Prop. III.), we have A+B+C+D=1, the second equation of the above system may be expressed in the form A+B+C=1. [266] If we represent the function d+B+C by V, the system (4) becomes | w=A+9qC; (5) V=1. (6) Let us for a moment consider this result. Since V is the sum of a series of constituents of s, ¢, &c., it represents the compound event in which the simple events involved are those denoted by s, ¢, &c. Hence (6) shows that the events de- noted by s, z, &c., and whose probabilities are p, g, &c., have such probabilities not as zudependent events, but as events subject to a certain condition V. Equation (5) ex- presses w as a similarly conditioned combination of the same events. Now by Principle VI. the mode in which this knowledge of the connexion of events has been obtained does not influ- ence the mode in which, when obtained, it is to be employed. We must reason upon it as if experience had presented to us the events s, ¢, &c., as simple events, free to enter into every 282 THE PAWS OF [HOUGHT combination, but possessing, when actually subject to the : condition V, the probabilities ~, g, &c., respectively. { Let then 7’, 7’, . ., be the corresponding probabilities of — such events, when the restriction V is removed. Then by ἢ Prop. II. of the present chapter, these quantities will be ἢ determined by the system of equations, yn ane cer. (7) : and by Prop. I. the probability of the event w under the 4 same condition V will be Prob. zw = ee ; (8) 7 wherein V, denotes the sum of those constituents in V of which s is a factor, and [V,] what that sum becomes when ἢ Ge. ake chanced into 7" 7... respectively. | ne am constant ¢ represents the probability of the indefinite event 7; it is, therefore, arbitrary, and admits of any value from ~ oto, 7 Now it will be observed, that the values of #’, g’, &c., are determined from (7) only in order that they may be sub- stituted in (8), so as to render Prob. w a function of known quantities, 2, g, [267] ὅς. It is obvious, therefore, that instead of the letters 2’, g’, &c., we might employ any others as Ss, ἢ &c., in the same quantitative acceptations. This particular step would simply involve a change of meaning of the symbols s, ¢, &c.—their ceasing to be logical, and ἴ becoming quantitative. The systems (7) and (8) would then become Ve V, Ὁ; ν᾽ “5 ἄτα. : (9) Prob. a (10) In employing these, it is only necessary to determine from (9) 5, ¢, &c., regarded as quantitative symbols, in terms of 2, 9, &c., and substitute the resulting values in (10). It is GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 283 evident, that s, ¢, &c., inasmuch as they represent proda- bilities, will be positive proper fractions. The system (9) may be more symmetrically expressed in the form Ane Ζ pip aa en ie rae (11) Or we may express both (9) and (10) together in the symme- trical system γι 2c A+cC ai pene. _7.- = — OA RES Fae - 9 7 : oa wherein w represents Prob. w. 15. It remains to interpret the constant c assumed to re- present the probability of the indefinite event g. Now the logical equation w=A+gC, interpreted in the reverse order, implies that if either the event A take place, or the event C in connexion with the event g, the event w will take place, and not otherwise. Hence g represents that condition under which, if the event C take place, the event w will take place. But the proba- bility of gis c. Hence, therefore, c= probability that if the event C take place the event w will take place. Wherefore by Principle II., ra Probability of concurrence of C and w Probability of € : [268] We may hence determine the nature of that new ex- perience from which the actual value of c may be obtained. For if we substitute in C for s, ¢, &c., their original expres- sions as functions of the simple events x, y, 2, &c., we shall form the expression of that event whose probability consti- tutes the denominator of the above value of c; and if we multiply that expression by the original expression of w, we shall form the expression of that event whose probability con- stitutes the numerator of c, and the ratio of the frequency of this event to that of the former one, determined by new observa- tions, will give the value of c. Let it be remarked here, that 284 THE LAWS OF THOCGHRT the constant cdoes not xecessarily make its appearance in the — solution of a problem. It is only when the data are insuffi- ᾿ cient to render determinate the probability sought, that this : arbitrary element presents itself, and in this case it is seen that the final logical equation (2) or (5) informs us how it is to be determined. : If that new experience by which c may be determined can- — not be obtained, we can still, by assigning to c its limiting ᾿ values o and 1, determine the limits of the probability of τὺ. These are Minor limit of Prob. zw -%. Superior limit oe i Between these limits, it is certain that the probability sought ᾿ must lie independently of all new experience which does not ‘ absolutely contradict the past. ; If the expression of the event C consists of many con- stituents, the logical value of w being of the form ἢ w= A+°C\+-C,+ &e., we can, instead of employing their aggregate as above, present : the final solution in the form Prob. w= A+qC; ow ce [269] Here c,=probability that if the event C, occur, the event w will occur, and so on for the others. Convenience must decide which form is to be preferred. 16. The above is the complete theoretical solution of the problem proposed. It may be added, that it is applicable - equally to the case in which any of the events mentioned in its original statement are conditioned. Thus, if one of the data is the probability 2, that if the event + occur the event y will occur ; the probability of the occurrence of x not being given, we must assume Prob, x=c (an arbitrary constant), then Prob. zy=cp, and these two conditions must be intro- SCENEKAL METHOD TN PROBABILITIES § 285 duced into the data, and employed according to the previous method. Again, if it is sought to determine the probability that if an event x occur an event y will occur, the solution will assume the form ELov. ἂν Prob. sought = >» 37 ee πος the numerator and denominator of which must be separately determined by the previous general method. 17. We are enabled by the results of these investigations to establish a general rule for the solution of questions in probabilities. GENERAL RULE CASE ].— When all the events are unconditioned. Form the symbolical expression of the events whose pro- babilities are given or sought. Equate such of those expressions as relate to compound events to a new series of symbols, s, ¢, &c., which symbols regard as representing the events, no longer as compound but simple, to whose expressions they have been equated. Eliminate from the equations thus formed all the logical symbols, except those which express events, 5, Z, &c., whose respective probabilities ~, 7, &c., are given, or the event w whose probability is sought, and determine w asa developed function of s, ¢, &c. in the form FEN elo see Oui BE Oo = 70 [270] Let 4+ B+C= TV, and let V, represent the aggre- gate of those constituents in V which contains s as a factor, V, of those which contain ¢ as a factor, and thus for all the symbols whose probabilities are given. Then, passing from Logic to Algebra, form the equations dD (1) A+cC 2 (2) 286 THE LAWS, OF TACCGCH from (1) determine s, ¢, &c. as functions of 2, g, &c., and ~ substitute their values in (2). The result will express the j solution required. Or form the symmetrical system of equations where wz represents the probability sought. If c appear in the solution, its interpretation will be Prob. Cw C= τς Prop 2 and this interpretation indicates the nature of the experience % which is necessary for its discovery. CASE I].— When some of the events are conditioned. If there be given the probability p that if the event Α΄ 3 occur, the event Y will occur, and if the probability of the antecedent XY be not given, resolve the proposition into the — two following, viz. : Probability of X =, Probability of Y Y= cp. If the gu@situm be the probability that if the event W occur, the event Ζ will occur, determine separately, by the previous case, the terms of the fraction Prob. WZ Prob. W ’ and the fraction itself will express the probability sought. [271] It is understood in this case that XY, Y, W, Z may be any compound events whatsoever. The expressions X Y — and WZ represent the products of the symbolical expressions of X and Y and of W and Z, formed according to the rules of the Calculus of Logic. The determination of the single constant ¢ may in certain © cases be resolved into, or replaced by, the determination of a series of arbitrary constants, Cy, Cg . . according to conveni- ence, as previously explained. ac te δι — ; (3) ; pean eek Me, | SN Rete RP Dames | | | 1 GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 287 18. It has been stated (I. 12) that there exist two distinct ‘definitions, or modes of conception, upon which the theory of probabilities may be made to depend, one of them being connected more immediately with Number, the other more directly with Logic. We have now considered the conse- quences which flow from the numerical definition, and have shown how it conducts us to a point in which the necessity of a connexion with Logic obviously suggests itself. We have seen to some extent what is the nature of that con- nexion ; and further, in what manner the peculiar processes of Logic, and the more familiar ones of quantitative Algebra, are involved in the same general method of solution, each of these so accomplishing its own object that the two processes may be regarded as supplementary to each other. It remains to institute the reverse order of investigation, and, setting out from a definition of probability in which the logical re- lation is more immediately involved, to show how the numerical definition would thence arise, and how the same general method, equally dependent upon both elements, would finally, but by a different order of procedure, be established. That between the symbolical expressions of the logical calculus and those of Algebra there exists a close analogy, is a fact to which attention has frequently been directed in the course of the present treatise. It might even be said that they possess a community of forms, and, to a very consider- able degree, a community of laws. With a single exception in the latter respect, their difference is only one of inter- pretation. Thus the same expression admits of a logical or of a quantitative interpretation, according to the particular meaning which we attach to the sym-[272]bols it involves. The expression xy represents, under the former condition, a concurrence of the events denoted by x and y; under the latter, the product of the numbers or quantities denoted by x and y. And thus every expression denoting an event, simple or compound, admits, under another system of inter- pretation, of a meaning purely quantitative. Here then 288 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT arises the question, whether there exists any principle of transition, in accordance with which the logical and the numerical interpretations of the same symbolical expression shall have an intelligible connexion. And to this question the following considerations afford an answer. 19. Let it be granted that there exists such a feeling as expectation, a feeling of which the object is the occurrence of events, and which admits of differing degrees of intensity. Let it also be granted that this feeling of expectation ac- companies our knowledge of the circumstances under which events are produced, and that it varies with the degree and kind of that knowledge. Then, without assuming, or tacitly implying, that the intensity of the feeling of expectation, viewed as a mental emotion, admits of precise numerical measurement, it is perfectly legitimate to inquire into the pos- sibility of a mode of numerical estimation which shall, at least, satisfy these following conditions, viz., that the numerical value which it assigns shall increase when the known circum- stances of an event are felt to justify a stronger expectation, shall diminish when they demand a weaker expectation, and shall remain constant when they obviously require an equal degree of expectation. Now these conditions at least will be satisfied, if we assume the fundamental principle of expectation to be this, viz., that the laws for the expression of expectation, viewed as a numerical element, shall be the same as the laws for the ex- pression of the expected event viewed as a logical element. Thus if φᾷ, 7, 5) represent any unconditional event com- pounded in any manner of the events 4, y, 5, let the same expression ¢(%, 7, ), according to the above principle, de- note the expectation oi that event: 7%, 7, 2 represciiting no longer the simple events involved, but the expectations of those events. [273] For, in the first place, it is evident that, under this hypothesis, the probability of the occurrence of some one of a set of mutually exclusive events will be equal to the sum of the separate probabilities of those events. Thus if the GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 289 alternation in question consist of 7 mutually exclusive events whose expressions are P(X, ¥, 2), PolX, », 2)» . . + » φ,(α, γ, 2), the expression of that alternation will be φ,(5,.», 2) + hol, Is 2)... + Φ,(α, γ, 2) = 75 the literal symbols x, y, z being logical, and relating to the simple events of which the three alternatives are com- pounded : and, by hypothesis, the expression of the proba- bility that some one of those alternatives will occur is P(x, ν, 2) + $,(x, J; 2) et + (αὶ ys 2), x,y, 8 here denoting the probabilities of the above simple events. Now this expression increases, ceteris paribus, with the increase of the number of the alternatives which are in- volved, and diminishes with the diminution of their number ; which is agreeable to the condition stated. Furthermore, if we set out from the above hypothetical definition of the measure of probability, we shall be con- ducted, either by necessary inference or by successive steps of suggestion, which might perhaps be termed mecessary, to the received numerical definition. We are at once led to recognise unity (1) as the proper numerical measure of cer- tainty. For it is certain that any event # or its contrary 1—2z will occur. The expression of this proposition is x+(1—-%x)=1, whence, by hypothesis, x+(1—-*), the measure of the pro- bability of the above proposition, becomes the measure of certainty. But the value of that expression is 1, whatever the particular value of x may be. Unity, or 1, is therefore, jon the hypothesis in question, the measure of certainty. Let there, in the next place, be 22 mutually exclusive, {but equally possible events, which we will represent by t,, t,,..¢,. [274] The proposition which affirms that some n one of these must occur will be expressed by the equation A+ .-+4= 1; 19 290 THe GAWS ΕΟ and, as when we pass in accordance with the reasoning of the last section to numerical probabilities, the same equation remains true in form, and as the probabilities ¢,, ¢,,.. 7, are equal, we have nt, = 1, oe! I I whence A=, and similarly Ca le Suppose it then required to determine the probability that some one event Of the partial series τ, = ¢,, will occur; we have tor the expression required cee oe ch eae fe . to m terms Hence, therefore, if there are 72 cases favourable to the oc- currence of a particular alternation of events out of 2 possible and equally probable cases, the probability of the occurrence Tie of that alternation will be expressed by the fraction oa Now the occurrence of any event which may happen in different equally possible ways is really equivalent to the occurrence of an alternation, z.e., of some one out of a set of alternatives. Hence the probability of the occurrence of any event may be expressed by a fraction whose numerator represents the number of cases favourable to its occurrence, and denominator the total number of equally possible cases. But this is the rigorous numerical definition of the measure of probability. That definition is therefore involved in the more peculiarly /ogzcal definition, the consequences of which; we have endeavoured to trace. 20. From the above investigations it clearly appears, Ist, that whether we set out from the ordinary numerical defini- tion of the measure of probability, or from the definition which assigns to the numerical measure of probability such a law of) value as shall establish a formal identity between the logical expressions [275] of events and the algebraic expressions of their values, we shall be led to the same system of practical GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 291 results. 2ndly, That either of these definitions pursued to its consequences, and considered in connexion with the rela- tions which it inseparably involves, conducts us, by inference or suggestion, to the other definition. To a scientific view of the theory of probabilities it is essential that both prin- ciples should be viewed together, in their mutual bearing and dependence. [276] CHAPTER XVIII ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS OF THE GENERAL METHOD IN PROBABILITIES 1. IT is designed here to illustrate, by elementary examples, — the general method demonstrated in the last Chapter. The | examples chosen will be chiefly such as, from their simplicity, ὦ permit a ready verification of the solutions obtained. But | some intimations will appear of a higher class of problems, ἢ hereafter to be more fully considered, the analysis of which | would be incomplete without the aid of a distinct method . determining the necessary conditions among their data, in ἢ order that they may represent a possible experience, and_ assigning the corresponding limits of the final solutions. The - fuller consideration of that method, and of its applications, Se is-reserved ἥν the next Chapter: 2. Ex. 1.—The probability that it thunders upon a given day is ~, the probability that it both thunders and hails is g, but of the connexion of the two phenomena of thunder and hail, nothing further is supposed to be known. Required — the probability that it hails on the proposed day. Let x represent the event—It thunders. Let y represent the event—It hails. Then xy will represent the event—It thunders and hails; — and the data of the problem are | Re oe τον ee a a ee eee oe Se eee ee ree Prob. τυ Ξ 9, Probesy — a: There being here but one compound event xy involved, ἢ assume, according to the rule, . sey =U, (1) Our data then become δ Prob. ἀξ Prob. x=: (2) 292 ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS 293 and it is required to find Prob. y. Now (1) gives (2771 , =O = uae + “u(t -- a) +0(1 ~ ux + (1 — γᾷ - αν. Hence (XVII. 17) we find Γ =uxt+(1-u“)x+(1-u)(1 -- x), VIS Uri wits, τ. and the equations of the General Rule, viz., tia : p > Prob. y=4 Ἐς, V become, on substitution, and observing that A=az, C= (1 -- 2}(1 --- 2), and that V reduces to r+ (1—u)(1—»*), Fo (3) Prop τ τς - 4)(1 -- x) x+(1—u)(1—x)’ (4) from which we readily deduce, by elimination of x and a, Prob. y=¢ +¢(1 -- 2). (5) In this result c represents the unknown probability that if the event (1—%)(1—%) happen, the event y will happen. Now (1 —4)(1—%)=(1—4y)(1 —4) =1—4, on actual multipli- cation. Hence c is the unknown probability that if it do not thunder, it will hail. The general solution (5) may therefore be interpreted as follows :—The probability that it hails is equal to the proba- bility that it thunders and hails, g, together with the proba- bility that it does not thunder, 1—f, multiplied by the probability c, that if it does not thunder it will hail. And - common reasoning verifies this result. If ¢ cannot be numerically determined, we find, on assign- ing to it the limiting values o and 1, the following limits of wrod. 7, Viz. : Inferior limit =¢. Superior limit=g+1-—-f. 294 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT [278] 3. Ex. 2.—The probability that one or both of two events happen is 23, that one or both of them fail is g. What is the probability that only one of these happens ? Let x and y represent the respective events, then the data are— Prob. «y+ «(1 -—y)+(1- x)y=, Prob. x(1 —y) + (1 -x)y+(1-x)(1 -- )) εξ φ; and we are to find Prob. «(1 -y) +y(1 - x). Here all the events concerned being compound, assume sy+x(i—-y)+(1-xyes, a(1-y)+(1-x)y+(1-x)(1-y)=4, χᾷ -—y)+(1 -—x)y=w. Then eliminating x andy, and determining w as a developed function of s and ¢, we find w = st + ὁρᾷ τοῦ + 0(1 -- δ) “(1 ~5)(1 -- ἢ. Hence A=st, C=0, V=st+s(1-—t)+(1—s)t=s+(1—s)é, V,=s, V,=¢; and the equations of the General Rule (XVII. 17) become Sore oe a 2 τ S)Z, I rer (1-5) (1) Brel ye ene S+(1—s)é whence we find, on eliminating s and Ζ, Prob. w=p+q-1. Hence 2 -Ἐφ — 1 is the measure of the probability sought. This result may be verified as follows :—Since p is the probability that one or both of the given events occur, 1 -- 2 will be the probability that they both fail ; and since g is the probability that one or both fail, 1g is the probability that they both happen. Hence 1—g+1~-g, or 2 —p—g, is the probability that they either both happen or both fail. But the only remaining alternative which is possible is that one alone of the events happens. Hence the probability of this occur- rence is --(2 --2 -- Φ), or +g —1, as above. Se PEEVE NTARY ILLUSTRATIONS 295 = [279] 4. Ex. 3.—The probability that a witness A speaks the truth is g, the probability that another witness B speaks the truth is g, and the probability that they disagree in a statement is y What is the probability that if they agree, their statement is true? Let x represent the hypothesis that A speaks truth ; y that B speaks truth; then the hypothesis that A and B disagree in their statement will be represented by +(1—y) +y(1—2#); the hypothesis that they agree in statement by ay+(1—#)(1—y), and the hypothesis that they agree in the truth by xy. Hence we have the following data: Prob. x=, Prob. y=g, Prob. x(1 -—y)+y(1 -x)=7, from which we are to determine Prob: ay Prob. xy+(1 —x)(t—y) But as Prob. χίι -- 7))-Ἐ 7 -- ξε σ, it is evident that Prob. ay +(1—4+)(1—y) will be 1-7; we have therefore to seek Prob. xy 7 - A Now the compound events concerned being in expression, x(1—y)+y(1 —*) and xy, let us assume χᾷι -- ») Ἐγᾷ -- “)Ξ 9 ᾿ (1) xy Ξ (ἢ Our data then are Prob. =f, Prob. y=g, Prob. 5. -Ξ- 7, and we are to find Prob. w. The system (1) gives, on reduction, {a(x —y) + (1 — x) }(1— δ) + 5{ay +(x -αλὰ -9)} + xy(1 -- Ww) +w(1 -- xy) =0; whence _ «(1 -y)(1 - 5) +y(1 —x)(1 -- 5) +sxy +5(1 — α)ᾷ —y) + x 2Χ} - ὦ «υ - =xys + ay(1— 5) τ ον ys + ταί τι Ὁ Ἐσ(ι -- ᾽ν» Ὲ τι τα) —y)s + τα — 2 ~ 5) 4+ 0(1—x)(1—y)(1 -- 5). (2) 296 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT [280] In the expression of this development, the coefficient * has been made to replace every equivalent form (X. 6). O Here we have Y= ay(1 ἡ χα —y)s+(1—axyys-+ (1 —a)(1 ~y\(r-5) 5 whence, passing from Logic to Algebra, xy(I -—S)+x(1 —y)s_ xy —s)+(1 = x)ys _ x(1 —v)s+(1-—x)ys 2 7 εἴ =ay(1 - 5) + a(t —y)s-+ τ x)yst (1 -a)(1 -y)(4-5). xy(1 5) F100. = 5) Fae ays EAMETS) from which we readily deduce Prob. w =P 59 whence we have Prob. xy ptg-7 Teor, § 2(1 7) (3) for the value sought. If in the same way we seek the probability that if A and & agree in their statement, that statement will be false, we must replace the second equation of the system (1) by the following, viz.: ee) a, the final logical equation will then be τυ ΣΙ oxy(I -- 5) + 0x(1 —y)s + ται —y)(1- 5s) +0(1 - ays + τα — x)y(1 — 8) 42(1 —x)(1 -- γ)ς +(1-x)(1-y)(1-5); (4) whence, proceeding as before, we finally deduce Probes 22 ae ee (5) 2 Wherefore we have [281] Prob. (1-x)(1-y) 2-p-g-r eae = (6) 1-- 2(1 -- 2) for the value here sought. ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS 297 These results are mutually consistent. For since it is certain that the joint statement of A and B must be either true or false, the second members of (3) and (5) ought by addition to make 1. Now we have identically, Prete 7 5 2(1 -- 2) 2 Fe - It is probable, from the simplicity of the results (5) and (6), that they might easily be deduced by the application of known principles ; but it is to be remarked that they do not fall directly within the scope of known methods. The num- ber of the data exceeds that of the simple events which they involve. M. Cournot, in his very able work, Exposition de la Théorte des Chances, has proposed, in such cases as the above, to select from the original premises different sets of data, each set equal in number to the simple events which they involve, to assume that those simple events are inde- pendent, determine separately from the respective sets of the data their probabilities, and comparing the different values thus found for the same elements, judge how far the assump- tion of independence is justified. This method can only approach to correctness when the said simple events prove, according to the above criterion, to be nearly or quite inde- pendent ; and in the questions of testimony and of judgment, in which such an hypothesis is adopted, it seems doubtful whether it is justified by actual experience of the ways of men. 5. Ex. 4.—From observations made during a period of general sickness, there was a probability 23. that any house taken at random in a particular district was visited by fever, a probability g that it was visited by cholera, and a pro- bability ~ that it escaped both diseases, and was not in a defective sanitary condition as regarded cleanliness and ventilation. What is the probability that any house taken at random was in a defective sanitary condition ἢ With reference to any house, let us appropriate the symbols 4, y, 2, as follows, viz.: 298 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT [282] The symbol to the visitation of fever. y a cholera. 2 to defective sanitary condition. The events whose probabilities are given are then denoted by ~ x, y, and (I1—x)(I1—y)(1—2), the event whose probability is — sought is z. Assume then, ; (1-2x)(1-y)(1 2) Ὁ, then our data are, o- Prob. x=/, Prob. y=g, Prob. w=rz, and we are to find Prob. z Now hd A Saat τ ΕἸ ΠΥ Ὁ} - ἔχγευ + Sxy( Ι -- 20) Ὁ χί I - ν)εῦ Ὁ 2e( I—y)(1 -- το) ο ο ο ο o— - Ξ +2(1-x)ywt τὰ - x)y(1 —w) + o(1 -- x)(1 —y)w ο +(1-2)(1 -- ν)α -- τὺ). (1) | The value of V deduced from the above is V=xv(i-w)tati-—y)(1 -—w) + (1 -- αὐνᾷι -- w) +(1-x)(1 -y)w+(1-x)(1 -y)(1 -w) = 1 -- τὸ τ τῦ(ι -x)(1 -- ν); and similarly reducing V,, V,, V., we get V.=x(1-w), V,=y(1-w), Ve=w(1-2)(1 -9); furnishing the algebraic equations τι π᾿ κι πὴ σι τι) —-w+w(1—-x)(1-y). (2) | 2 ἐ Α As respects those terms of the development characterized . by the coefficients - , I shall, instead of collecting them into ~ a single term, present them, for the sake of variety (XVII. 18), in the form . 2x(1 ~w)+2(1—a)y(1 τα); (3) the value of Prob. z will then be ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS 299 283] Bob. maa - x) -- ")(ι -- 20) tex(1-w) τ ἐ(ι —x)y(1 πο) I-w+w(1—x)(1-y) (4) From (2) and (4) we deduce Prob. 8 ee i ae) I by --Σ 2 as the expression of the probability required. If in this re- - sult we make c=0, and c’ =o, we find for an inferior limit of ee and if we make c=1, ¢=1, τ we obtain for its superior limit 1 -- 7. 6. It appears from inspection of this solution, that the premises chosen were exceedingly defective. The constants _¢ and ε΄ indicate this, and the corresponding terms (3) of _ the final logical equation show how the deficiency is to be supplied. Thus, since x(1 -w)=x{1 -(1-x)(1 -y)(1 -- 2)} = 2, (1—x)y(1 -w) =(1 -- xy {1 -(1 - x)(1 -- ))( -- 2)} ΞΞ (( --- σὴν, _we learn that ς is the probability that if any house was visited by fever its sanitary condition was defective, and that _¢ is the probability that if any house was visited by cholera without fever, its sanitary condition was defective. If the terms of the logical development affected by the its value : O : ; coefficient - had been collected together as in the direct statement of the general rule, the final solution would have assumed the following form : ich. τ 2. Γλι -7-)..(2.9- 22 ἘΠ Σ c here representing the probability that if a house was visited by either or both of the diseases mentioned, its sanitary con- dition was defective. This result is perfectly consistent with _the former one, and indeed the necessary equivalence of the different forms of solution presented in such cases may be formally established. ΕΓ The above solution may be verified in particular cases. _ Thus, taking the second form, if c=1 we find Prob, z=1—- 7, 300 THEO LAWS OL T 70 fT. acorrect result. For if the presence of either fever or cholera certainly [284] indicated a defective sanitary condition, the probability that any house would be in a defective sanitary state would be simply equal to the probability that it was not found in that category denoted by ΖΦ, the probability of which would, by the data, be 1-7. Perhaps the general verification of the above solution would be difficult. The constants 2, g, and χ inthe above solution are subject to the conditions x χει σφύζει. 7, Ex. 5.—Given the probabilities of the premises of a hypothetical syllogism, to find the probability of the conclusion. Let the syllogism in its naked form be as follows : Major premiss: If the proposition Y is true X is true. Minor premiss: If the proposition Z is true Vis true. Conclusion : If the proposition Z is true X is true. Suppose the probability of the major premiss to be 2, that of the minor premiss g. The data then are as follows, representing the proposition X by #, &c., and assuming c and c’ as arbitrary constants : Prob. y=c, Prob. xy=cp; Probe ec," γ᾽; ζῶ: from which we are to determine, Prob. xz Prob. xz _ Prob. z τ Let us assume, LY=U, YZ=V, XZ=W; then, proceeding according to the usual method to determine w as a developed function of y, z, 24, and v, the symbols corresponding to propositions whose probabilities are given, we find w= ξὺν + ομᾷι — 2)(1 -- v)y + 0(1 — 2)zvy + 5(1 = w)s(t (1-3) + (1 = N(x )α -- τὴν + 0(1—w)(1 -- 2)(t —v)(1 —y) + terms whose coefficients are ~ ο ee ΔΑ ELEMENTARY. ILLUSTRATIONS 301 [285] and passing from Logic to Algebra, a ad) LS eA Sd A a) AS) LS 2, 3 0a) _ usoy + (1 —u)zvy d ε τ _usoy + us — 2)(1 -- σὴν + (1 -- u)zvy + (1 —u)(1 -- 2)(1 =O s V. ; 4 isin ee _ usvy +a(t —u)2(1 —v)(1 -- γ) . τὺ -- : ; wherein V=uzvy+u(i -- 2)(1 -v)y + (1 -- μ)δὸν + (1 — u)2(1 -- σ)( — γ) + (1 οὐ τε 2)(x — oy + (1 (τ - 2)(1 τ v)(1 }} the solution of this system of equations gives Prob. w=¢pg +ac'(1 -- 4), aeaunes Prob. 99 pg +a(1~9) the value required. In this expression the arbitrary constant a is the probability that if the proposition Z is true and Y false, X is true. In other words, it is the probability, that if the minor premiss is false, the conclusion is true. This investigation might have been greatly simplified by ’ assuming the proposition Z to be true, and then seeking the probability of X. The data would have been simply Prob, 7— 7, ΕΠ αὺ Ξ 70. whence we should have found Prob. r=pg+a(1—q). Itis evident that under the circumstances this mode of procedure would have been allowable, but I have preferred to deduce the solution by the direct and unconditional application of the method. The result is one which ordinary reasoning verifies, and which it does not indeed require a calculus to obtain. General methods are apt to appear most cumbrous when applied to cases in which their aid is the least required. Let it be observed, that the above method is equally appli- cable to the categorical syllogism, and not to the syllogism only, [286] but to every form of deductive ratiocination. Given the probabilities separately attaching to the premises of any train of argument, it is always possible by the above 302 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT method to determine the consequent probability of the truth | of a conclusion legitimately drawn from such premises. It is not needful to remind the reader, that the truth and the correctness of a conclusion are different things. 8. One remarkable circumstance which presents itself in such applications deserves to be specially noticed. It is, that propositions which, when true, are equivalent, are ποῖ necessary equivalent when regarded only as probable. This principle will be illustrated in the following example. Ex. 6.—Given the probability 2 of the disjunctive proposi- tion ‘‘ Either the proposition Y is true, or both the proposi- tions XY and Y are false,” required the probability of the conditional proposition, ‘‘If the proposition Y is true, Y is trues. Let x and y be appropriated to the propositions XY and Y respectively. Then we have Prob. y+ (1 -x)(1 —y) =f, from which it is required to find the value of Prob. zy Prop. Ὁ Assume yt(i-x\(1-y)=4 (1) Eliminating y we get (1-2)(1-A)=0, whence ΘΑ, 12. Ο and proceeding in the usual way, Prob, x=1-f/+¢, (2) where c is the probability that if either Y is true, or Y and V falses 7 45 truce. Next to find Prob. xy. Assume xy =W. (3) Eliminating y from (1) and (3) we get 2(1—f)=0; [287] whence, proceeding as above, Prob. z=¢f, ELEMENTARY ILLUSTRATIONS 303 c having the same interpretation as before. Hence Prob: αν ὁ τπρῦ Prob.x 1-pt+cp’ for the probability of the truth of the conditional proposi- tion given. Now in the science of pure Logic, which, as such, is con- versant only with truth and with falsehood, the above dis- junctive and conditional propositions are equivalent. They are true and they are false together. It is seen, however, from the above investigation, that when the disjunctive proposition has a probability 23, the conditional proposition has a different and partly indefinite probability eae Aare I—pt+op Nevertheless these expressions are such, that when ezther of them becomes 1 or O, the other assumes the samevalue. The results are, therefore, perfectly consistent, and the logical transformation serves to verify the formula deduced from the theory of probabilities. The reader will easily prove by a similar analysis, that if the probability of the conditional proposition were given as p, that of the disjunctive proposition would be 1 --Φ- ᾧ, where c is the arbitrary probability of the truth of the pro- position X. 9. Ex. 7.—Required to determine the probability of an event x, having given either the first, or the first and second, or the first, second, and third of the following data, viz.: ist. The probability that the event x occurs, or that it alone of the three events, 2, y, 2, fails, 152. 2nd. The probability that the event y occurs, or that it alone of the three events, 7, y, 2, fails, is Φ. 3rd. The probability that the event 2 occurs, or that it alone of the three events 4, y, 2, fails, is 72. SOLUTION OF THE FIRST CASE Here we suppose that only the first of the above data is given. 304 THE LAWS CF THOUGI YT [288] We have then, Prob. {x +(1 —x)yz} =f, to find Ero, 4. weet x+(I-x)ys=s, then eliminating yz as a single symbol, we get A(t -5) = 0: oO Erence pee. eet ah τ δ Ae whence, proceeding according to the rule, we have Prob. x=¢, (1) where c is the probability that if x occurs, or alone fails, the former of the two alternatives is the one that will happen. The limits of the solution are evidently o and 2. This solution appears to give us no information beyond what unassisted good sense would have conveyed. It is, however, all that the single datum here assumed really warrants us in inferring. We shall in the next solution see how an addition to our data restricts within narrower limits the final solution. SOLUTION OF THE SECOND CASE Here we assume as our data the equations Prob. {x+(1 - x)yz} =f, Prob. {y+(1 -y)xz} Ξε φ. Let us write x+(1-x)ys=s, y+(i-y)xs=t; from the first of which we have, by (VIII. 7), {x+(1-x)yz}(1-s)+s{1-x—(1—x)vz}=0, or (x + £y2)5 + sx(1 —ys)=0; provided that for simplicity we write # for 1—%, 7 for 1—y, and so on. Now, writing for 1—yzx its value in constituents, we have (x + xy2)5 + sx(yZ +92 +72) =0, an equation consisting solely of positive terms. | | | | BREPNMENTAKRY [LEUSTRATIONS 305 [289] In like manner we have from the second equation, (y +yxz)t + ty(xF+*%2+X42)=0; and from the sum of these two equations we are to eliminate y and 2. If in that sum we makey=1, z=1, we get the result +2, If in the same sum we make y=1, z=0, we get the result xF+5x+0, If in the same sum we make γξξο, z=1, we get x5 + SK + 01 + EX. And if, lastly, in the same sum we make y =0, z=0, we find xS+sx+intix, or X5+sx+0. These four expressions are to be multiplied together. Now the first and third may be multiplied in the following manner : (5 Ἐ δίας + sX + xf + tx) = x5 + 4t+(5+7)(sx+¢*%) by (IX. Prop. 11.) = 05 + xb + St + sxt. (2) Again, the second and fourth give by (IX. Prop. I.) (x5 + sX + F)(x5 + 5x + ἢ) = KF + SH. (3) Lastly, (2) and (3) multiplied together give (x5 + sX)(x5 + sXE + xt + 1X5) = x5 + sx(sxt+ xf + x5) = x5 + sxt. Whence the final equation is (1 -s)x+s(1 -- δα - x) Ξε ο, which, solved with reference to %, gives s(1 -Σὃ wae —t)-(1-S) most +51 —t)+4+0(1 -- 5) Ἐ o(1 —s)(1-?), [2907 and, proceeding with this according to the rule, we have, finally, Prob. «= p(1 -- 97) + οὗ, (4) 20 306 THE LAWS Cf ΣΕ GH T. where c is the probability that if the event s¢ happen, 2 will happen. Now if we form the developed expression of s¢ by multiplying the expressions for s and ¢ together, we find— c= Prob. that if and y happen together, or x and z happen together, and y fail, or y and z happen together, and ~ fail, the event x will happen. The limits of Prob. x are evidently 2(1 -- Φ) and 2. This solution is more definite than the former one, inasmuch as it contains a term unaffected by an arbitrary constant. SOLUTION OF THE THIRD CASE Here the data are— Prob. {x+(1 -x)yz} =f, Prob. {y+(1 -y)xz}=49, Prob. {z+(1- z)xy} =r. Let us, as before, write ¢ for 1—%, &c., and assume X+XYZ=S, yrjus=t, Z+2xy=uU. On reduction by (VIII. 8) we obtain the equation (x + xyz)s + sx( V2 + 93 + 75) + (y+ yxz)t + ty( 2% + x3 + £7) + (2+ xy) + u3(xy + ἂν + XP) =0. (5) Now instead of directly eliminating y and z from the above equation, let us, in accordance with (IX. Prop. III.), assume the result of that elimination to be Ex+ FE (1—x)=0, then £ will be found by making in the given equation x=1, and eliminating y and z from the resulting equation, and Z’ will be found by making in the given equation +=0, and eliminating y and z from the result. First, then, making #%=1, we have [291] SH (V+ ps)e + pF + (2 +.2)a + ΜΚ} =0, and making in the first member of this equation successively ELEMENTARY [LEUSTRATIONS 307 Meet, 2-1; y=, 3=0; ὡς and multiplying together the results, we have the expression (S+Z+a)(S+Z+a)F+7+H)(5+¢42), which is equivalent to (S+Z+2)(5+¢+4). This is the expression for E. We shall retain it in its present form. It has already been shown by example (VIII. 3), that the actual reduction of such expressions by multiplication, though convenient, is not necessary. _ Again in (5), making +=0, we have V2E+ SVE +S +IHZ) +i + bp +2 +uzZ=0; from which, by the same process of elimination, we find for Ε΄ the expression (S+Z+a)(st+itu)st+t+a)(stt+u). The final result of the elimination of y and z from (5) is therefore (S+7+a)\(5+¢+u)x +(F+F%+2)(s4-7+u)(s+t+a)(st+t+u)(1-x)=0. Whence we have (§+7+a)/(st+f+u)(stt+a)(st+t+zu) ~ (F+F4+ay(s+itu)(s+i+a)(s+t+u) - σε ζει) τ)’ or, developing the second member, x =o stu Ἂν 1 shu He 1 sta + sti ce) 12) Oo 4 5tu + οδμ + O5ti + O50. (6) O Hence, passing from Logic to Algebra, stu + sti _ Stut+sta _stut Slu 1 = stu + sti + Stu + Sti + Sti. (7) [292] Pienee stit + cstu (8) stu + stit + Stu + Sti + Sti 3 : : : ὅλας Ζ To simplify this system of equations, change 2 into 5, : 308 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT into 2, &c., and after the change let ἃ stand for sta+s+¢+1. We then have Prob. x = cae Ὶ (9) with the relations Ἔρις ἘΣ ἐπεπς ee ATH ee (10) Ζ r From these equations we get stu+s=Ap, (11) stu+s=X-—t-u-t, \p=rX-u-f-1, u+t=X(1-p)-1. Similarly, “u+s=M1i-g)-1, and s+t=X1i-7)-1. From which equations we find ee Ce 0) τοῦ pe Me eB) ee ee ΣῪ - 2 2 ΡΣ δ ἐν as ὁ αὐ τὰ (12) | 2 i Now, by (10), stu=)p—s. Substitute in this equation the values of s, ¢, and « above determined, and we have ((1+p-g-r)A-1}{(1 +9g-p—r)r\-1}{(1+7-p-g)dr- 1} =4{(p+g+r-1)d4 1}, (13) an equation which determines Δ. The values of s, 2, and x, are then given by (12), and their substitution in (g) completes . the solution of the problem. [293] 10. Now a difficulty, the bringing of which pro- minently before the reader has been one object of this in- vestigation, here arises. How shall it be determined, which root of the above equation ought to be taken for the value of ΧΡ To this difficulty some reference was made in the opening of the present Chapter, and it was intimated that its fuller con- sideration was reserved for the next one; from which the following results are taken. - εἰ χω, ἐδ τόν ΚΣ ELEMENTARY [LLUSTRATIONS 309 _ In order that the data of the problem may be derived from a possible experience, the quantities 2, g, and ~ must be subject to the following conditions : ti Cae = Ο, I+g-p-rso, 11 7--.2 -- 923 ο. (14) Moreover, the value οἵ ἃ to be employed in the general solution must satisfy the following conditions : I 1+g-p-r’ N I ry ayer (15) Now these two sets of conditions suffice for the limitation of the general solution. It may be shown, that the central equation (13) furnishes but one value of ), which does satisfy these conditions, and that value cf ἃ is the one required. Let 1-Ὁ2 --τἶῷ --- be the least of the three coefficients of ἃ λ λ Vil Vil Vil given above, then will be the greatest of those I I+p—g-+7 values, above which we are to show that there exists but one value of }. Let us write (13) in the form π΄ Τὶ. τ|ἰτυς 2 ite 2. .-λ 1} —4{(ptqgtr—-1)A+1}=0; (16) and represent the first member by V/V. Assume Ve : , then V becomes which is negazzve. [294] Let X= o, then V is poszézve and infinite. Again, Bie Stace + similar positive terms, dn I I+p~-—q-r which expression is positive between thelimits A= nd \= ~, 310 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT If then we construct a curve whose abscissa shall be measured by Δ, and whose ordinates by V, that curve will, between the limits specified, pass from below to above the abscissa Δ, its convexity always being downwards. Hence it will but once intersect the abscissa ἃ within those limits ; and the equation (16) will, therefore, have but one root thereto corresponding. The solution is, therefore, expressed by (9), ἃ being that root of (13) which satisfies the conditions (15), and s, Ζ, and z being given by (12). The interpretation of c may be deduced in the usual way. It appears from the above, that the problem is, in all cases, more or less indeterminate. [295] CUAL Dine, OF STATISTICAL CONDITIONS 1. By the term statistical conditions, I mean those con- ditions which must connect the numerical data of a problem in order that those data may be consistent with each other, and therefore such as statistical observations might actually have furnished. The determination of such conditions con- stitutes an important problem, the solution of which, to an extent sufficient at least for the requirements of this work, I purpose to undertake in the present Chapter, regarding it partly as an independent object of speculation, but partly also as a necessary supplement to the theory of probabilities already in some degree exemplified. The nature of the con- nexion between the two subjects may be stated as follows : 2. There are innumerable instances, and one of the kind presented itself in the last Chapter, Ex. 7, in which the solu- tion of a question in the theory of probabilities is finally de- pendent upon the solution of an algebraic equation of an elevated degree. In such cases the selection of the proper root must be determined by certain conditions, partly relat- ing to the numerical values assigned in the data, partly to the due limitation of the element required. The discovery of such conditions may sometimes be effected by unaided reasoning. For instance, if there is a probability 2 of the occurrence of an event A, anda probability g of the con- currence of the said event A and another event δ, it is evident that we must have 2575. But for the gexera/ determination of such relations, a distinct method is required, and this we proceed to establish. 211 312 THE, LAWS OCF THOCGAT As derived from actual experience, the probability of any event is the result of a process of approximation. It is the limit of the ratio of the number of cases in which the event is observed to occur, to the whole number of equally possible — cases which [296] observation records,—a limit to which we approach the more nearly as the number of observations is increased. Now let the symbol 2, prefixed to the expression of any class, represent the number of individuals contained in that class. Thus, x representing men, and y white beings, let us assume n(x) =number of men. n( xy) = number of white men. m{x(1 —y)} =number of men who are not white; and so on. In accordance with this notation (1) will represent the number of individuals contained in the universe of discourse, and oe will represent the probability that any individual being, selected out of that universe of being denoted by x(1), is a man, If observation has not made us acquainted with the Zo¢ad values of n(x) and μι), then the probability : ΠΡ τς 62 in question is the limit to which aa approaches as the number of individual observations is increased. In like manner if, as will generally be supposed in this chapter, + represent an event of a particular kind observed, — n(x) will represent the number of occurrences of that event, m1) the number of observed events (equally probable) of all kinds, and met or its limit, the probability of the occurrence of the event z. Hence it is clear that any conclusions which may be deduced respecting the ratios of the quantities (rv), n(y), m1), &c. may be converted into conclusions respecting the probabilities of the events represented by x, y, &c. Thus, if we should find such a relation as the following, viz., n(x) + u( y) the class y. By Principle I. this number cannot exceed the number con- tained in the class x, nor can it exceed the number contained in the class y. Its major limit will then be the least of the two values (4) and x(y). By Principle II. a minor limit of the class xy will be given by the expression n(1) — major limit of #{x(1—y) +y(1 -- x) + (1 - x)(1 -}}} (1) since #(I—y)+y(1—¥%)+(1—#)(1—y) is the complement of the class xy, ὦ. 6. what it wants to make up the universe. Now #(1-y)+(1—#)(1-y)=1-—y. We have therefore for (1), a(t) -- major limit of z{1 —y +y(1 — x)} =n(1) — 2(1 —y) — major limit of z{ (1 -- x)}. (2) OF STATISTICAL CONDITIONS 315 The major limit of z{y(1—~*)} is the least of the two values my) and x(1—%). Let 2(y) be the least, then (2) becomes n(x) - n(x 3) ~ 219) =n(1) — (1) + 2(y) -- π΄) =0. Secondly, let z(1—~*%) be less than w(y), then major limit of z{y(1 —-x)}=x(1- 1, it may be shown that but one positive value of ἃ can be deduced from the central equation (10) which shall be less Ts as | I than each of the quantities —, —,..—. That value of X Pi 2. 2; is, therefore, the one required. To prove this, let us consider the equation (ι -- 2ιλ)( -- 22λ) .. (1 -- 2,λ) τ τ Ἔ λεο. When \=O the first member vanishes, and the equation is satisfied. Let us examine the variations of the first member between the limits \=o and an supposing 2, 1 the greatest of the values 7,, ~.,. . ,. [318] Representing the first member of the equation by V, we have a= Pile PA) ἃ P,A) - 2 {τ PAY a Pak) et, which, when \=o, assumes the form —p,—p,..—p,+1, and is negative in value. Again, we have ὩΣ De =p, pI -- p,A)(1 — 2,λ) + &e., consisting of a series of terms which, under the given re- strictions with reference to the value of A, are posttive. Lastly, when a we have 1 Goo 4 : Pi which is positive. From all this it appears, that if we construct a curve, the ordinates of which shall represent the value of V correspond- ing to the abscissa ἃ, that curve will pass through the origin, and will for small values of ) lie beneath the abscissa, Its OF STATISTICAL CONDITIONS 335 " convexity will, between the limits \ =o and A= ἢ be down- 1 wards, and at the extreme limit ἢ the curve will be above 1 the abscissa, its ordinate being positive. It follows from this description, that it will intersect the abscissa once, and only once, within the limits specified, viz., between the I values A=o, and A=—_. 1 The solution of the problem is, therefore, expressed by (11), the value of ἃ being that root of the equation (10), which lies within the limits o and—-, -,..—. Ar Pa Ve The constant ¢ is obviously the probability, that if the events %,, %,-.%,; all happen, or all fail, they will all happen. This determination of the value of ἃ suffices for all pro- blems in which the data are the same as in the one just con- sidered. It is, as from previous discussions we are prepared to expect, a determination independent of the form of the function ¢. [319] Let us, as another example, suppose φ-- οὐ w=x (I -- 4) . . (I-X_) .. $%,(1-%)) . . (τ -- α,.-)- This is equivalent to requiring the probability, that of the events 4, %,..%, one, and only one, will happen. The value of w will obviously be Ww =5,(1 ~ ἡ: {{πΞ τὴ. $5n(1 — 51). «(1 - Spi) += -(1-,). (LS), from which we should have Prob. (οἱ ὦ - (1-%n) τ τα) (τ αν ἢ] _ 5,(1 τὴ . - (te τ OE τ. Ok So ὺ τ : ire gee {ΠΥ Ο2ιλᾳ -- pod)» - ( - διλ) - - Ba Ek —prr) . . (1— ford) λα τ) A(t - oe ry eee) 1 --2.λ 1 -- pA : Ὰ 336 THE LAWS OF FHOUGCAT This solution serves well to illustrate the remarks made in the introductory Chapter (I. 16). The essential difficulties of the problem are founded in the nature of its data and not in that of its gu@stta. The central equation by which ἃ is determined, and the peculiar discussions connected there- with, are equally pertinent to every form which that problem can be made to assume, by varying the interpretation of the arbitrary elements in its original statement. [320] CHAPTER XX PROBLEMS RELATING TO THE CONNEXION OF CAUSES AND EFFECTS 1. SO to apprehend in all particular instances the relation of cause and effect, as to connect the two extremes in thought according to the order in which they are connected in nature (for the modus operandi is, and must be, unknown to us), is the final object of science. This treatise has shown, that there is special reference to such an object in the constitution of the intellectual faculties. There is a sphere of thought which comprehends things only as coexistent parts of a universe ; but there it also a sphere of thought (Chap. XI.) in which they are apprehended as links of an unbroken, and, to human appearance, an endless chain—as having their place in an order connecting them both with that which has gone before, and with that which shall follow after. In the contemplation of such a series, it is impossible not to feel the pre-eminence which is due, above all other relations, to the relation of cause and effect. Here I propose to consider, in their abstract form, some problems in which the above relation is involved. There exists among such problems, as might be anticipated from the nature of the relation with which they are concerned, a wide diversity. From the probabilities of causes assigned @ priort, or given by experience, and their respective prob- abilities of association with an effect contemplated, it may be required to determine the probability of that effect ; and this either, Ist, absolutely, or 2ndly, under given conditions. To such an object some of the earlier of the following pro- blems relate. On the other hand, it may be required to determine the probability of a particular cause, or of some 3532 22 338 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT particular connexion among a system of causes, from ob- served effects, and the known tendencies of the said causes, singly or in connexion, to the production of such effects. This class of questions will be considered in a subsequent portion of the [321] Chapter, and other forms of the general inquiry will also be noticed. I would remark, that although these examples are designed chiefly as illustrations of a method, no regard has been paid to the question of ease or convenience in the application of that method. On the con- trary, they have been devised, with whatever success, as types of the class of problems which might be expected to arise from the study of the relation of cause and effect in the more complex of its actual and visible manifestations. 2. PROBLEM I.—The probabilities of two causes A, and A, are c, and c, respectively. The probability that if the cause A, present itself, an event # will accompany it (whether as a consequence of the cause A, or not) is ~,, and the prob- ability that if the cause A, present itself, that event Ε will accompany it, whether as a consequence of it or not, is Pp. Moreover, the event & cannot appear in the absence of both the causes A, and A,.* Required the probability of the event 5 The solution of what this problem becomes in the case in which the causes A,, A, are mutually exclusive, is well known to be Prob. ΞΟ ΩΣ: * The mode in which such data as the above might be furnished by experience is easily conceivable. Opposite the window of the room in which I write is a field, liable to be overflowed from two causes, distinct, but capable of being com- bined, viz., floods from the upper sources of the River Lee, and tides from the ocean. Suppose that observations made on separate occasions have yielded the © following results : On 4 occasions the river was swollen by freshets, and on P of _ those occasions it was inundated, whether from this cause or not. On B occasions _ the river was swollen by the tide, and on Q of those occasions it was inundated, — whether from ‘this cause or not. Supposing, then, that the field cannot be in- ' undated in the absence of 40/4 the causes above mentioned, let it be required to — determine the total probability of its inundation. Here the elements, a, ὁ, 2, φ of the general problem represent the ratios ΟΡ cl ge: Ne Δ 8, or rather the values to which those ratios approach, as the value of Wis indefinitely increased. a ee PROBLEMS: ON CAUSES 339 and it expresses a particular case of a fundamental and very important principle in the received theory of probabilities. Here it is proposed to solve the problem free from the re- striction above stated. [322] Let us represent ‘he .causec Ay bya. The cause A, by y. The effect Z by z. Then we have the following numerical data : Prob. x =¢,, Prob. y=¢, Prob. xz=6),, Prob. yz Ξ ey Again, it is provided that if the causes A,, A, are both absent, the effect H does not occur ; whence we have the logical equation (1 -x)(1 —y) = (1 — 2). Or, eliminating v, 2(1-x)(1 -y)=0. (2) Now assume, CoS Ve (3) Then, reducing these equations (VIII. 7), and connecting the result with (2), x2(t -- δ) Ἐσᾷ — xz) +y2(1 -- ὃ ἘΠῚ - 2) +2(1-x)(1-y)=0. (4) From this equation, z must be determined as a developed logical function of x, y, 5, and ¢, and its probability thence deduced by means of the data, Prob. «=¢,, Prob. y—¢, Prob.s=aqp,, Prob. f=. (5) Now developing (4) with respect to 2, and putting # for 1—x, 7 for 1—y, and so on, we have (x5 + si ty? + + XV)z + (s+ 2)2=0, Ζ erat a an en ee es = τ απειηον ae xs — sx — yt - ty -— xy = stixy + * stxy + * sty + * sty ο ο ο τιν ἜΝ ΤΣ Ege - —stxy + Stxy 4 —stxy + -ῖχγ ο ο ο ie τ: le + Stay 4+ —Stxy + Stxy 4+ —Stxy ο ο fe) + ostxy + ostxy + ostxy + OStxy. (6) 340 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT [323] From this result we find (XVII. 17), V = stxy + sixy + Stxy + Stay + Stxy + Stxy + SUxy = stxy + sixy + Stxy + δῇ Whence, passing from Logic to Algebra, we have the follow- ing system of equations, # standing for the probability sought: | stay + sixy + ste _ stay + stay +5iy (ΑἹ ζ _ stay + stay _ stxy +stxy OP) CoP» _ stay + stay + Stxy _ stuy + sixy + 5tey + 5t Vv. (7) u I : from which we must eliminate s, 2 7, y, and V. Now if we have any series of equal fractions, as we know that la+mb+ nc a la +mb'+ne ν And thus from the above system of equations we may deduce © τὰν stay Shae γ- bap whoop, ee whence we have, on equating the product of the three first members to the cube of the last, ; SSL x Υ _ ps 8 / CE CeCe 8) Again, from the system (7) we have ΖΑ, sty ἣν stxy Ὁ whence proceeding as before Di) ΣΧ ΤῊ ὭΣ v3 (9) 4 (1 -G, +6) p, — Μ)(1 — 0 + 0g fy — U)(GP, + Copy — %) [324] Equating the values of 7, in (8) and (9), we have PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 341 (u -- α,2ι)ίω - efo)(1 - u) = {1-4(1-p,)-u}{1- C(I -- 39) -—u}(Qp, + C5 py — u), which may be more conveniently written in the form (ὦ — Cpi)(u -- & fy) ay {1 = κ(ι -- 21) ~~} {1 -- κα -- 29) -- u} . (10) Opi +f. -- Lh From this equation the value of wz may be found. It re- mains only to determine which of the roots must be taken for this purpose. 3. It has been shown (XIX. 12) that the quantity w, in order that it may represent the probability required in the above case, must exceed each of the quantities c,f,, ¢.f,, and fall short of each of the quantities 1 —c,(1 —f,), 1 τοι —p,), and ¢,f, +, ; the condition among the constants, more- over, being that the three last quantities must individually exceed each of the two former ones. Now I shall show that these conditions being satisfied, the final equation (10) has but one root which falls within the limits assigned. That root will therefore be the required value of z. Let us represent the lower limits ¢,p,, ¢.f,, by a, 6 re- spectively, and the upper limits 1 —c,(1—f,), I—c(1 —p,), and ¢,f,+&/.,, by 2’, 3’, δ᾽ respectively. Then the general equation may be expressed in the form (uw — a)(u — 6)(1 —u) —(a’ -- μ)(δ' -- μ)(έ -- u) =0, (11) or (1-a -- δ)μωξ -- [αὖ -- α'δ' - θ ι -- α' -- ὅγε }.6-Ὁ αὖ -- α΄ δ΄ ἐ΄ =o. Representing the first member of the above equation by V, we have 2 oan 2(1-a -- δ). (12) Now let us suppose a the highest of the lower limits of w, a’ the lowest of its higher limits, and trace the progress of the _ values of V between the limits =a and w=a’, When wz=a, we see from the form of the first member of (11) that V is negative, and when =a’ we see that V is positive. [325] Between those limits V varies continuously ery aye: . without becoming infinite, and Tt β always of the same sign. 342 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Hence if # represent the abscissa and V the ordinate of a plane curve, it is evident that the curve will pass from a point below the axis of # corresponding to «=a, to a point above the axis of # corresponding to =a’, the curve remaining continuous, and having its concavity or convexity always turned in the same direction. A little attention will show that, under these circumstances, it must cut the axis of a once, and only once. Hence between the limits s=a, u=a’, there exists one value of w, and only one, which satisfies the equation (11). It will further appear, if in thought the curve be traced, that the other value of z will be less than ὦ when the quantity 1—a’—0’ is positive and greater than any one of the quanti- ties a’, δ΄, ε΄ when Ι -- α΄ -- δ΄ is negative. It hence follows that in the solution of (11) the positive sign of the radical must be taken. We thus find αὖ -- α'δ' -- (τ -- α -- δ᾽ γέ + a a Say ve (13) where 0 - {αὖ -- α΄ δ΄ -- (τ -- α' -- ὅγΖ }3-Ξ 4(ι -- α' -0')(ab- «α΄ δ΄ 4). 24 A. s)he results ‘of this investigation may to some extent be verified. Thus, it is evident that the probability of the event / must in general exceed the probability of the con- currence of the event # and the cause A, or A,. Hence we must have, as the solution indicates, uU>C pi, 1ῶ 9. Again, it is clear that the probability of the effect E must in general be less than it would be if the causes A,, A, were mutually exclusive. Hence “
  • 1. This also appears from the application of the rule. 6. PROBLEM III.—The probabilities of two events 4 and B are a and 6 respectively, the probability that if the event A take place an event & will accompany it is 2, and the proba- bility that [328] if the event B take place, the same event Z PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 345 will accompany it is g. Required the probability that if the event A take place the event B will take place, or vice versa, the probability that if B take place, A will take place. ᾿ς Let us represent the event A by #, the event B by y, and the event & by z. Then the data are— Prob, x ὦ, Prob. y=d. Prob. x«z=af, Prob. yz= dg. Whence it is required to find Prob. xy or Prob. xy Prob.-x Probey et XY=S, yo=t, xy=w. Eliminating z, we have, on reduction, δὰ + ty + SyE+ xt5 + xy + (τ — xy)w =o, υ.. SET + SVE txts ἂν = 2xy—1 = xyst + Txpst + "cyst Ἔ Txpst ο ο ο ται τορι ee ᾿ς τε Ὁ + —xyst + oxyst + —xyst + —xyst ο ο ο τ ΤΠ Ὁ rey vigoe + —xyst + —xyst + oxyst + —xy5st ο ο ο + xyst + oxyst + oxysl + οαγτά (1) Hence, passing from Logic to Algebra, axyst + xyst Teo hese Prob. xy = ; x, y, Ss, and ¢ being determined by the system of equations xyst + xyst + xyst+ xyst xyst + xyst+ xyst + xyst a b _ xyst t+ xyst _ xyst + xyst epee ee 07 = xyst + xyst + xyst + xyst + xyst + xyst + xysl= V. [329] To reduce the above system to a more convenient form, let every member be divided by Χ752, and in the result let 346 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT We then find : mm +m+nn'+n mm +m +nn'+n' a ἯΙ b mm +m_ mm +m | = ap bg | =mm+m+m +nn'+n+n' +1. | mm +nn' | Also, Prob. xy = ma mm +m+m +nn +ntn +1 These equations may be reduced to the form mm +m mm +m nan'+n nn'+n' ap 2. αἷἱ 2): (xg) =(m+1)(m' Ἔ 1) Ἡ (κα τα)ῷσ΄ -Ἐ 1) ---τ. : mm + nn (m+1)(m' +1)+(u+1)(“'+1)-1- | Now assume | Prob. xy = ͵ μ ’ V +1)(m +1)= » (R+ I)" +1) > — τῷ 2) ἢ (me nin’ ει) τ (nea. (a) Then since | ee et tl) mp . m+1 (m+1)(v+p- 1) and so on for the other numerators of the system, we find, on substituting and multiplying each member of the system by v+yu—1, the following results : Mi TL ny : n'y = (m+1)ap (m'+1)bg (n+ τ)α(ι -- 2) (κ΄ +1)b(1-g) ὁ Prob. xy =(mm' +nn')(v -Ἑ μ -- 1). (3) From the above system we have 1 ΞΡ: whence ma fo: Si wt Salata p—ap , [330] Similarly | - ἢ 4«(1-Ξ2) to) | μ-- bg ν -α( -- 2) ν -- [((τ -- φ) Hence eck = ν ἴον Geran τ τι τ ΠῚ πὴ &c. Substitute these values in (2) reduced to the form PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 347 ds oil | Bo) τ ιγδ ee ot 2 id ae (m+1)(m' +1) (a+ 1)(#' + 1) ἡ μος = SPM) {v—a(1 oes τ} eda) Substitute also for m, m’, &c. their values in (3), and we have es abpg αὔ(ι - p(t -- φ) Prob. ay=| ayaa dg) * Eee. _ pg , atx ape?) by (4). μ ν Now the first equation of the system (4) gives et a ape ee (5) μ συ} 7... Ι- α2:- bg. μ Similarly, αὐι1 — p)(1-g) _ Vv p-1+a(1-p)+H(1 -9). Adding these equations together, and observing that the first member of the result becomes identical with the expression just found for Prob. xy, we have Prob, χγενε μεαό- 2. Let us represent Prob. xy by w, and let a+0—2=m, then p+tv=u-m, (6) Again, from (5) we have μν = abpg -- (ap +59 -- τ)μ. (7) [331] Similarly from the first and third members of (4) equated we have pv = ab(x — p)(1 -- g) — {a(t ~ 2) + (1 -- Φ) -- 1}. Let us represent af +0q—1 by 4, and al —p)+h(1-—g)-1 by Δ΄. We find on equating the above values of uy, hp - ἔν =ab{ pg τ (ι --2)( -- 4)} -- αὐ(2 -Ὁ 9 -- 1). Let ab(p+q—1)=4, then ἦἀμ-- ἔντε ἃ (8) 348 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Now from (6) and (8) we get _h(u-—m)+e yp δίῶ - ) - = m oe m Substitute these values in (7) reduced to the form μίν + h) = abpg, and we have (hu—J/){h'(u-m)+ 4) =abpgm’, (9) a quadratic equation, the solution of which determines 26, the value of Prob. «y sought. The solution may readily be put in the form Ui + Whim = 1) [{λ’ ~ Adm - 1)} + 4hhabpgn] ΄ 2hh' But if we further observe that ih —h('m —1)=Kh+ 1) —hh'm=(t— hk')m, since h=aptbg—-1, λ΄ -αί(ι -- 2) -Ἐόᾳ -- 4) -- τ, whence ht+h'=a+b-2=m, we find Prob, ay H+ M sim —) £m ψ{{- 115: 4habpo} (4) 2hh' It remains to determine which sign must be given to the radical. We might ascertain this by the general method exemplified in the last problem, but it is far easier, and it fully suffices in the present instance, to determine the sign by a comparison of the [332] above formula with the result proper to some known case. For instance, if it were certain that the event A is always, and the event B never, associated with the event 4, then it is certain that the events 4 and B are never conjoined. Hence if p=1, g=0, we ought to have «=0, Now the assumptions p= 1, g=0, give hkh=a-1, k=6-1, l=0, m=at6-2. Substituting in (10) we have (a-—1)(6-1)(@+6—2)+(a+d—2)(a—1)(6—1) 2(a — 1)(6—- 1) and this expression vanishes when the lower sign is taken. Prob. xy= PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 349 Hence the final solution of the general problem will be ex- pressed in the form Prob. xy 4λ' + λ( τε -- ἢ -- κ΄ , {{{{--ὄ 12) 411. α24) Prob. x _ 2ahh' wherein A=apt+dg-1, Δ΄ --α( -- 2) Ἐ6(ι -- 4) --, ἐξ αὐ(2 -Ἐφ-- τ), m=at+b-2, As the terms in the final logical solution affected by the coefficient = are the same as in the first problem of this chapter, the conditions among the constants will be the same, ViZ., = apei1—b1-g) bg=1-a(i—f). 7. It is a confirmation of the correctness of the above solution that the expression obtained is symmetrical with respect to the two sets of quantities 2, g, and 1 --2, 1 -Φ, 2.6. that on changing p into 1 -- 2, and g into 1—g, the ex- pression is unaltered. This is apparent from the equation Prob. xy= αὖ ες Ἔ2.1: 2) } μ ν employed in deducing the final result. Now if there exist probabilities ~, g of the event 4, as consequent upon a knowledge of the occurrences of A and δ᾽, there exist pro- babilities 1—f, 1 --φ of the contrary event, that is, of the non-occurrence of £ under the same circumstances. As then the data are unchanged in [333] form, whether we take account in them of the occurrence or of the non-occurrence of E, it is evident that the solution ought to be, as it is, a symmetrical function of 2, g and --2, I—@. Let us examine the particular case in which p=1, g=I. We find h=at+b-1, h#=-1, ΞΡ m=atb-2, and substituting Prob. xy —-—ab+(at+d- 1)(2 -a—-b-ab)-(a+b—2)(ab-a—b+ 1) Probe x. —2a(a+b - τὴ ὡς —2ab(at+b—-1)_ 5 Sonat -- τῈ 350 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT It would appear, then, that in this case the events A and B are virtually independent of each other. The supposition of their invariable association with some other event Z, of the — frequency of whose occurrence, except as it may be inferred — from this particular connexion, absolutely nothing is known, — does not establish any dependence between the events 4 and © Bthemselves. 1 apprehend that this conclusion is agreeable — to reason, though particular examples may appear at first sight to indicate a different result. For instance, if the probabilities of the casting up, Ist, of a particular species © of weed, 2ndly, of a certain description of zoophytes upon — the sea-shore, had been separately determined, and if it had © also been ascertained that neither of these events could happen ~ except during the agitation of the waves caused by a tempest, ἡ it would, I think, justly be concluded that the events in question were not independent. The picking up of a piece of seaweed of the kind supposed would, it is presumed, render more probable the discovery of the zoophytes than it would — otherwise have been. But I apprehend that this fact is due — to our knowledge of another circumstance not implied in the actual conditions of the problem, viz., that the occurrence of a tempest is but an occasional phenomenon, Let the range of observation be confined to a sea always vexed with storm. It would then, I suppose, be seen that the casting up of the weeds and of the zoophytes ought to be regarded as inde- pendent events. Now, to speak more generally, there are conditions common to all phz-[334]nomena,—conditions which, it is felt, do not affect their mutual independence. I apprehend therefore that the solution indicates, that when a particular condition has prevailed through the whole of our recorded experience, it assumes the above character with re- ference to the class of phenomena over which that experience has extended. 8. PROBLEM IV.—To illustrate in some degree the above observations, let there be given, in addition to the data of the last problem, the absolute probability of the event Z, the completed system of data being | PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 251 Prob. «=a, Prob. γ- δ, Prob. z=<, Prob. xz=ap, Prob. γε Ξε dg, and let it be required to find Prob. ry. Assuming, as before, +z=5, yz=¢, xy=w, the final logical equation is τὺ = xysts + xy Sts + O(xysis + xySts + xPZSE + Kysst + KYss7 + XZ ) : Ι + terms whose coefficients are —. (1) ο The algebraic system having been formed, the subsequent eliminations may be simplified by the transformations adopted in the previous problem. The final result is Prob. xy ab | 29 ἘΞ {δ ι 2) } i (2) c 1-¢ The conditions among the constants are c>ap, ¢sbg, c=a1-ali-p) cHa1-db(1-4@). Now if ΞΡ g=1, we find Prob. yee ; ἢ Ε not admitting of any value less than a or ὁ, It follows hence that if the event / is known to be an occaszonal one, its invariable attendance on the events 4 and y zucreases the probability of their conjunction in the inverse ratio of its own frequency. [335] The formula (2) may be verified in a large number of cases. Asa particular instance, let g=c, we find Prob. xy = ad. (3) Now the assumption g = c involves, by Definition (Chap. XVI.), the independence of the events B and Z. If then Band & are independent, no relation which may exist between A and ΑΕ can establish a relation between A and 4; wherefore A and B are also independent, as the above equation (3) implies. It may readily be shown from (2) that the value of Prob. 2, which renders Prob. «y a minimum, is 352 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT aa ν (24) ᾿ oe aC ἢ Prob. z=); If p=g, this gives a result, the correctness of which may be shown by the same considerations which have been applied to (3). PROBLEM V.—Given the probabilities of any three events, and the probability of their conjunction ; required the pro- bability of the conjunction of any two of them. Suppose the data to be Prob. x=, Prob. y=g, Prob.z=r7, Prob. xyz=™m, and the gu@sttum to be Prob. xy. Assuming zyz=s, xy=2, we find as the final logical equation, f= χγΖ5 + xyZ5 + O(xVS + XS) + : (sum of all other constituents) ; ο whence, finally, ; Prob. ΟΣ — 4697? ~ apgrm) 27 wherein p=1-p,&e. 41--ὴῷ -- (2- Φ};. This admits of verification when 2-ΞῚ, when g=1, when r=0, and therefore m=o0, &c. Had the condition, Prob. z=7, been omitted, the solution would still have been definite. We should have had [33] ρου.» 224 =m) + (1-2) - δ), ME (3 and it may be added, as a final confirmation of their correct- ness, that the above results become identical when m=pgr. 9. The following problem is a generalization of Problem I., and its solution, though necessarily more complex, is obtained by a similar analysis. PROBLEM VI.—If an event can only happen as a conse- quence of one or more of certain causes A,, A,, .. A,, and if generally c, represent the probability of the cause A,, and 2: the probability that if the cause A, exist, the event E will a ΠΤ PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 353 occur, then the series of values of c¢, and 2; being given, re- quired the probability of the event Z,* Let the causes 4,, A,,.. A, be represented by Wa Ue tee and the event £ by 52. Then we have generally, Prob. x;=¢;,, Prob. x2=¢,f;. Further, the condition that ΑΕ can only happen in connexion with some one or more of the causes A,, A,,.. A, establishes the logical condition, 2(1 -x,)(1-—x,) .. (1-—x,)=0. (1) [337] Now let us assume generally x,2= ἢ which is reducible to the form x2(1 -- 2) Ἐκ -- x3) =0, forming the type of a system οἵ z equations which, together with (1), express the logical conditions of the problem. Add- ing all these equations together, as after the previous re- duction we are permitted to do, we have 2{ x42(1 — 2) ἘΔ — x ,2)} + σά —%,)(1- x) . . (1-x,)=0, (2) (the summation implied by © extending from 7=1 ἴο ΖΞ 3), and this single and sufficient logical equation, together with the 2 data, represented by the general equations Prob. Δ; ΞΞ C55 Prob. L,=C; Pi, (3) * It may be proper to remark, that the above problem was proposed to the notice of mathematicians by the author in the Cambridge and Dublin Mathema- tical Journal, Nov. 1851, accompanied by the subjoined observations : ‘‘The motives which have led me, after much consideration, to adopt, with reference to this question, a course unusual in the present day, and not upon slight grounds to be revived, are the following :—First, I propose the question as a test of the sufficiency of received methods. Secondly, I anticipate that its discussion will in some measure add to our knowledge of an important branch of pure analysis. However, it is upon the former of these grounds alone that I desire to rest my apology. ** While hoping that some may be found who, without departing from the line of their previous studies, may deem this question worthy of their attention, I wholly disclaim the notion of its being offered as a trial of personal skill or know- ledge, but desire that it may be viewed solely with reference to those public and scientific ends for the sake of which alone it is proposed.” The author thinks it right to add, that the publication of the above problem led to some interesting private correspondence, but did not elicit a solution. 23 354 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT constitute the elements from which we are to determine rons: Let (2) be developed with respect to z. We have [Z{a(1 -4) +4(1 — x;)} + (1 -- λα — χῳ) . . (1 — χ,}]5 + ΣΙ - z) =0, whence is Bis τὴν Ὁ δ (4) BA, -— S{x,(1 -ἡ τᾷ — %)} — (τ τὴ) — Hq) . . (1- Hq) Now any constituent in the expansion of the second member of the above equation will consist of 22 factors, of which ἡ are taken.out of the set. 4, 7.0, 4,51 ab 7 to and #% out of the set ¢,, 7, .. ¢,, I—%,, I-—%,,.. 1—Z,, no such combination as #,(1—4%,), 4,(1—4,), being admissible. Let us consider first those constituents of which (1—4,), (1—¢,)..(1—¢,) forms the ¢-factor, that is the factor de- rived from the set z7,,.. 1—4,. The coefficient of any such constituent will be found by changing ¢,, ¢,,. . ¢, respectively into Oin the second member of (4), and then assigning to ΤΊ, 4, . . %, their values as de- pendent upon the nature of the x-factor of the constituent. Now simply substituting for Ζι, 24, ..¢, the value o, the second member becomes 3 ο - Σα,-- ἃ -- ἡ) -- χ9) .. (αι - ἁ,) [338] and this vanishes whatever values, 0, I, we subse- quently assign to 4,, 4%, ..4%,. For if those values are not all equal to ὁ; the term 2%, does not vanish, and if they are all equal to o, the term —(1—+7%,)..(1—4%,) becomes —1, so that in either case the denominator does not vanish, and therefore the fraction does. Hence the coefficients of all constituents of which (1—¢,).. (1 —¢,) is a factor will be o, and as the sum of all possible x-constituents is unity, there will be an aggregate term O(1—¢,). . (1 —¢,) in the develop- ment of 2. Consider, in the next place, any constituent of which the ¢-factor is ¢,7,.. ¢,(1—4,,,)..(1—4,), 7. being equal to or greater than unity. Making in the second member of (4), f,=1,..¢4,=1, ¢4,,,=0,.. 4,=0, we get the expression | PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 355 Bie Oe Χο εχ oe) τ τ τ Now the only admissible values of the symbols being o and I, it is evident that the above expression will be equal to I ποτ τ =. %—=1, 1%, =0, .. “,=0, and that for all other combinations of value that expression will assume a value greater than unity. Hence the coefficient 1 will be applied to all constituents of the final development which are of the form My ALS Ae) (XA Ar 4) (τὴ), the x-factor being similar to the ¢-factor, while other consti- tuents included under the present case will have the virtual coefficient ~. Also, it is manifest that this reasoning is in- O dependent of the particular arrangement and succession of the individual symbols. Hence the complete expansion of z will be of the form =2XT)+0(1-4)(1-4) . . (1-4) + constituents whose coefficients are = (5) ‘ where 7 represents any ¢-constituent except (1 ae (1—¢,), and X the corresponding or similar constituent of “-- 6ἐ [339] For instance, if z= 2, we shall have D(AT) λα hat Βα Xel bo: #1, %, δῖα, standing for 1—4,, 1—4,, &c. ; whence Z= Ly Xoby ly + Uy Xoliby +X Xolile + OX Xol ile +X Xnh lo +X Noll + δὰ. ἢ (6) . . I + constituents whose coefficients are = 3 This result agrees, difference of notation being allowed for, with the developed form of z in Problem I. of this Chapter, as it evidently ought to do. 10. To avoid complexity, | purpose to deduce from the above equation (6) the necessary conditions for the deter- 356 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT mination of Prob. ¢ for the particular case in which #= 2, in such a form as may enable us, by pursuing in thought the same line of investigation, to assign the corresponding con- ditions for the more general case in which z possesses any integral value whatever. Supposing then = 2, we have V = X,Xobjby + XyXalyby + Ly Xob ily + αγχρῆ ἧς, + HX Xgh ly + Ly Hobby + Hy Xol ilo. OE LY ΚΣ ΞΕ re 7, owe ae Pe ΠΝ ρα as the conditions for the determination of 1, 4,, &c., being Xy Nobby + Ky Xol ιν" 4X ally Cy Ζ 2 XX ybily Ἔ Δγλοίγΐ,, αχχοίγή, +A Koh ly _ V. , “Pi CoP2 | Divide the members of this system of equations by — %,%,/,f,, and the numerator and denominator of Prob. 2 by the same quantity, and in the results assume ! xyb Xol x x. | slam, 22=m, =m, τε». (7) Xb, Kobo xy Xo [340] we find Prob. z= adie ABN ΤΗΣ MMs + M+ My t+ MyMy+ Ny + 7. I and MM + My + Myo tM _ MMe Ὁ My Ἔ MN t Ny δ, τ a M,M,+M, MM +m ! CP) CoP2 / whence, if we assume, ! (m7, +1)(m,+1)=M, (4,4 1)(%.+1)=N, (9). we have, after a slight reduction, Prob. z= sas Mie, ; M+N-1 (y+ 1) ποίη 1) my(My+1)_ my(m, +1) ΣΝ q(t - 2) οἰ - 2.) A, “Po : ᾿ BROPLEALS ON CAUSES 357 or, m,M Mm oM n,1V (m, + 1) p, (Mo + ΞΕ (2, + 1)¢,(1 - 2.) nLV =M+N-1 ~ (tg an ἜΤ — po) Now let a similar series of transformations and reductions be performed in thought upon the final logical equation {6}. We shall obtain for the determination of Prob. g the follow- ing expression : Prob. 2= toy : (10) wherein M=(m,+1)(m,+1) .. (m,+1), N= (7, +1)(tg+1) . . (%,+ 1), M,,.. M,, δι n,, being given by the system of equations, Pe MoM 2 My, (m+ Da (mq + 1)eop, (Mtn + ΠΣ, n,1V n,1V ρον. (11) ~ (1+ 1)¢(1 — py) π᾿ “(5 Ὲ 1 )¢,( 1 “2. Still further to simplify the results, assume [341] ΠΝ τ Με τ M ft ͵ ΔΝ την whence jo A τ 3, sae μτεν--τ᾽ ἌΡΕΙ We find 772) = Mo eS (M,+1)o fp, (Mgt I)ly Po ~ (my HUE» Pn pe ny a Ny ες Nn ine (7, +1)e(1-—f,) (a+ 1)¢,(1 — po) (#,+1)e(1— Pa) Vv whence m, = apy ye μη μ- OP, CrP and finally, μ μ 22, τ Ὁ. ΞΞ “Ὁ eee Dae : : μ-ῶ μ- &nPn Vv Vv Ὁ ΣΑΣ ΚΣ Σ ΩΣ ὦ ἘΠ 22 te Ξ - v-¢(1 —p,)’ ν-ο(τ — pn) Substitute these values with those of 27 and WV in (9), and we have 358 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT μ' mated ee (μ — & Py) (MH -- 29) (i eRe) μεν τ The uv {v-a(1-p) Hy - αἱ =p,)} > -{v—e(1-p,)} ety =I which may be reduced to the symmetrical form (u— op). - (wr Cn Pn) μήν --1-Ξ VT se Ὅν ΘΑ = Pisa poe A ~ Pn)} (12) Vac Finally, M-1 ἔτους Sey grag τον (13) Let us then assume I —y=#, we have then Fe Coma al ες (μ - φιβη) | Foote _{1-4(t-A,) - 4} SAT GU Pa) τ} (1 -«u)""" [342] If we make for simplicity οὔ αι Snbn=any 1-4(1-—p,) =4,, &e., the above equations may be written as follows: pwn BO) A), 14) wherein eg eee”) : “ἀμ (15) (11) This value of , substituted in (14) will give an equa- tion involving only w, the solution of which will determine Tropes 2, since: by (13) Etob..2—z, < It remains. to assign the limits of z. ‘ es 11. Now the very same analysis by which the limits were — determined in the particular case in which 2=2 (XIX. 12), conducts us in the present case to the following result. The quantity #, in order that it may represent the value of Prob. 2, must have for its inferior limits the quantities ὅς, ν΄. @; and for its superior limits the quantities 6,, 0,,.. δ @,+a,..+a,. We may hence infer, a préord, that there will always exist one root, and only one root, of the equa- FROBLEMS ON CAUSES 359 tion (14) satisfying these conditions. I deem it sufficient, for practical verification, to show that there will exist one, and only one, root of the equation (14), a area the limits Me, 4,5. a and δι, 0b First, let us consider the nature of the changes to which pw is subject in (15), as w varies from ὦ,, which we will suppose the greatest of its minor limits, to 6,, which we will suppose the least of its major limits. When w=a,, it is evident that μ is positive and greater thana,. Whenuw=42,, we have μεεὖό,, which is also positive. Between the limits u=a,, u=b,, it may be shown that μ increases with a. Thus we have : n) dp _ , _(4,-%) ve (ὁ, -- μὴ) (d,— μ)(ός -- μὴ) . . (2 Ξ du {π| (1 —u)"" es οὐ χ{7, -- @)(,= 4) «᾿. On—%) (16) + (2-1) Gaus : Now let Cina ὅ, πὸ ὦ ΕΣ 1 τ τῇ n Evidently +,, +, . . x,, will be proper fractions, and 343 γ 41, “2 prop we have ἄμ ᾿ : i ~*~ Κλ Ἔν τα πα οι ee gees Oy, τ πτν χιϊχεῖοι. τς σὲ eg) tg es ἀντ: NE = hy) oe ἃ Now the negative terms in the second member are (if we may borrow the language of the logical developments) con- stituents formed from the fractional quantities 7, %,.. *%,, : : Tap νὰ Their sum cannot therefore exceed unity; whence π, 5 Posi- tive, and » increases with τε between the limits specified. Now let (14) be written in the form (w= ay) :- (ε΄ ts) _ (yu) m0, (17) n— and assume ~=a,, The first member becomes (u-a,) | #— 4) “ΠΟ δε. 0 ᾿ (18) n μ 360 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT and this expression is negative in value. For, making the same assumption in (15), we find | ae _ (4-4) τος (6,—4) 1 (1 - “yt μ =a positive quantity. At the same time we have (4 -- ας) es (μ --α,) μ.-- ας ee n—1 ne ae 2 μ μ μ and since the factors of the second member are positive - fractions, that member is less than unity, whence (18) is negative. Wherefore the assumption u=a, makes the first member of (17) negative. | secondly, let «=0,, then by (15) n=“=6,, and the first member of (17) becomes positive. Lastly, between the limits #=a, and “=0,, the first member of (17) continuously increases. For the first term — of that expression written under the form Be a On μ “ (μ -- αι) [344] increases, since » increases, and, with it, every factor contained. Again, the negative term μ —z diminishes with the increase of “4, as appears from its value deduced’ from (15), viz., (Os -- ) e (ὁ, -- ἡ (1 ae YM Hence then, between the limits τέ = a,, «= ,, the first member of (17) continuously increases, changing in so doing from a negative toa positive value. Wherefore, between the limits © assigned, there exists one value of z, and only one, by which | the said equation is satisfied. 12. Collecting these results together, we arrive at the following solution of the general problem. The probability of the event £ will be that value of w deduced from the equation eae) zu (μ - SrPn) | (19) μ PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 361 ᾿.. Ww ee alacant —p,)-u}.. {1-61 melas (1 -—x)""1 which (value) lies between the two sets of quantities, Py: 220... .ὡξκ and 1-4(1-f,), 1-6,(1 -2) -. 1-6,(1 —f,), _the former set being its inferior, the latter its superior, limits. And it may further be inferred in the general case, as it has been proved in the particular case of z= 2, that the value of #, determined as above, will not exceed the quantity Py το » + +onPn- 13. Particular verifications are subjoined. Est. Jet 7, bs Pol. f= a ΤῊΣ is, torsupposesit certain, that if any one of the events 4,, A,,.. A,, happen, the event # will happen. In this case, then, the probability of the occurrence of £ will simply be the probability that the events or causes 4,, A,,.. A, do not all fail of occurring, and its expression will therefore be 1—(1—c,)(I—¢,). . (I—©,). Now the general solution (19) gives [345] ey ea) ars) wherein "ἢ πω Ce (eae ἢ : Hence, t-“%=(1-4).. (1-4), “u=1—(1I-¢,) oss (1 — Cy), equivalent to the α priorz determination above. Onde Vet) ΞΟ 7,-0.7. Ξ-ο πο do) civics ea adaael oo. 2,ΞΞ Ὸ. as it evidently ought to be. 1 τεῦ, Cpe siball quantitics, so ἐπα} theit squares and products may be neglected. Then developing the second members of the equation (19), τ (GP τον ἘΦ ΖΜ: μ -—4=— n—-1 μ Ξμ-(αζι 24. » +orPn)s τεῦ, 21 τ 9 ere a One 362 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Now this is what the solution would be were the causes A,, Ay, .. A, mutually exclusive. But the smaller the pro- | babilities of those causes, the more do they approach the con- dition of being mutually exclusive, since the smaller is the probability of any concurrence among them. Hence the result above obtained will undoubtedy be the limiting form of the expression for the probability of 2. 4th. In the particular case of w=2, we may readily elimi- nate » from the general solution. The result is (u — ¢ Py)(4 -- C5 Do) a {1 —¢(1 —p,) — u} {1 — (1 — py) εν; Pi top, u thi which agrees with the particular solution before obtained for this case, Problem I. Though by the system (19), the solution is in general made to depend upon the solution of an equation of a high order, its [346] practical difficulty will not be great. For the con- ditions relating to the limits enable us to select at once a near value of z, and the forms of the system (19) are suitable for the processes of successive approximation. 14. PROBLEM VII.—The data being the same as in the last problem, required the probability, that if any definite and given combination of the causes A,, A,, .. A,, the event £ will be realized. The cases ἡ A,,..A,, being represented as before by present itself, 41, 4, 1 respectively, let the definite combination of them, referred to in the statement of the problem, be repre- sented by 4(4, +, . . #,) so that the actual occurrence of that combination will be expressed by the logical equation, ep oA ger i cod Pa The data are ΤῸ ec. 2 Probar, —c. (1) Prob. ἘΞ Δ biol: το A; and the object of investigation is BIO: OC ea ee eel P(X), Xp ) (2) PLOUR οὐ σὸς aces We shall first seek the value of the numerator. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 363 Let us assume, HyZ=t,.. X=, (3) OL yr ee (4) Or, if for simplicity, we represent $(%,, %, . . 2.) by ¢, the last equation will be oz =w, (5) to which must be added the equation Hi ees ΞΟ (6) Now any equation v,2=¢, of the system (3) may be reduced to the form . Xl, + t(1 — £,2) = Ὁ. Similarly reducing (5), and adding the different results to- gether, we obtain the logical equation [347] δἰ {τ τα} +4, .. %,54+620+w(1-g2)=0, (7) from which z being eliminated, w must be determined as a Beve lo ped. ocical AnctiOns Olas τ 1 Now making successively z=1, ¢=0 in the above equa- tion, and multiplying the results together, we have {2(x,2,.4+4,t,) +4, .. &,+ φῶ - τῷ} x (2t,+w) =o. Developing this equation with reference to w, and replac- ing in the result S¢,+1 by 1, in accordance with Prop. I. Chap. IX., we have Lw+ E'(1 -w)=0; wherein fea GA ea 59a το, OT gs FE = ΣΡ ΣΙ ΣΟ + ea,) +0) στ Py And hence ee 8 0 = rR (8) The second member of this equation we must now develop with respect to the double series of symbols z,, τῶ... . +,; t,,%,..4,. In effecting this object, it will be most con- venient to arrange the constituents of the resulting develop- ment in three distinct classes, and to determine the coefficients proper to those classes separately. 364 PHE LAWS OF ΟΝ First, let us consider those constituents of which Z, . . Z, is a factor. Making ¢,=0, . . 2,=0, we find E=0, L=2x,+%,.. ἃς ἘΦ. It is evident, that whatever values (0, 1) are given to the a-symbols, Ὁ does not vanish. Hence the coefficients of all constituents involving 4... 4, are o. Consider secondly, those constituents which do not involve the factor ὦ... ¢,, and which are symmetrical with reference fo the, two.sets of symbols 4... 7 4 and 73.7: By syne metrical constituents is here meant those which would re- main unchanged if 74, were converted into ¢,, %, into ¢,, &c., aie gece cers tic constitucnts 2, ΤῊ ee τὰ ἢ &c., are in this sense symmetrical. [348] For all symmetrical constituents it is evident that ΣΙ + t,X,) vanishes. For those which do not involve 4 . . Z,, it is further evident that 7, . . 7%, also vanishes, whence E=¢ 2’ = ΣΙ, (φ), ee), Σή,(φ) -- φ For those constituents of which the #-factor is found in ᾧ the second member of the above equation becomes 1 ; for those of which the +-factor is found in ᾧ it becomes o. Hence the coefficcents of symmetrical constituents not involv- ing t,.. t,, of which the x-factor ἐς found in p will be 1 ; of those of which the x-factor ts not found in ¢ it will be o. 4 Consider lastly, those constituents which are unsymmetrical ~ with reference to the two sets of symbols, and which at the same time do not involve Z,. . 7 n° Here it is evident, that neither Ε nor Z’ can vanish, whence the numerator of the fractional value of w in (8) must exceed the denominator. That value cannot therefore be represented O νι 0; OF 5° It must then, in the logical development, be represented by =. Such then will be the coefficient of this class of constituents. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 365 15. Hence the final logical equation by which w is ex- pressed as a developed logical function of 4,..4%,, 4,..¢ will be of the form w=3,(X7)+0{3,(X7) +4 . . %}+ ὦ (sum of other con- stituents), n? (9) wherein 2,(X 7) represents the sum of all symmetrical con- stituents of which the factor X is found in ¢, and Σ,(Χ 7), the sum of all symmetrical constituents of which the factor X is not found in ¢,—the constituent #,..7,Z,..7,, should it appear, being in either case rejected. Passing from Logic to Algebra, it may be observed, that [349] here and in all similar instances, the function V, by the aid of which the algebraic system of equations for the Metermmination of the values of 4.4.4 γὲ 7, is formed, is independent of the nature of any function ¢ involved, not in the expression of the data, but in that of the questtum of the problem proposed. Thus we have in the present n example, Prob. w= ACSA) ; KB wherein VeS(XT)+3(XT)+4,..4, SN ten oie (10) Here S(X7) represents the sum of all symmetrical con- stituents of the ἢ and ¢ symbols, except the constituent Wea 7. ee, © is Valle Ole ale thessame as that νὴ: tually employed in the solution of the preceding problem, and hence we may avail ourselves of the results there obtained. If then, as in the solution referred to, we assume xt, δ ἴῃ ε--...----Ξ τὰ, a : —M,, ==", &e., we shall obtain a result which may be thus written : M, M+ WV a GD M, being formed by rejecting from the function ¢ the con- stituent +,.. Ζ,» if it is there found, dividing the result by n? Prob. w= 366 CHE LAWS OF. THOCGH I a é ὌΝ the same constituent Ζ . . Ζ,, and then changing — into m,, og 1 *2 into m,, andsoon. The values of J and WM are the a} same as in the preceding problem. Reverting to these and to the corresponding values of m,, m,, &c., we find Prob. w= Ζη(μπν -- 1), the general values of m,, 2, being CP = (1 -2,) : μ- ὦ» μ- οὐτ-- 2) and uw and ν being given by the solution of the system of ‘equations. [350] μὲν! _(H= οι): UH Grn) _ tv = 4 (1 - Ay)} Ξ ἘΠῚ = GAT = Dn)} t= n—1 = The above value of Prob. w will be the numerator of the fraction (2). It now remains to determine its denominator. For this purpose assume φ(α» Hg)» My) =Y, or p=; whence pi + vp =o. Substituting the first member of this equation in (7) in place of the corresponding form ¢zw-+w(I — 2) we obtain as the primary logical equation, 2{x,2t,+4(1 —x,2)} +4, .. χε φῦ τ᾿ =0, whence eliminating z, and reducing by Prop. II. Chap. IX., Hence oa b+ 3t.{2(x,F,+6,4,)+ 4, .. 2φ--ἰ φῦ aM vd te A a Gee ἘΠ Ex} Bi Xy ον ὁ oe } ΞΞΟ. oe) ’ and developing as before, V=B(XT)+4 .. £3,(X)+0{2(XT)+4 . . 7,2,(X)} +. (sum of other constituents). (12) Here ΟΣ) indicates the, sum af all constituents found in ¢, 2 (xX) the sum of all constituents not found in 9. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 367 The expressions are indeed used in place of ¢ and I—¢ to preserve symmetry. It follows hence that =\(X)+2,(X)=1, and that, as be- fore, 2(X7)+2,(X7)=X(XT). Hence V will have the same value as before, and we shall have Prob pe a ὩΣ (Χ ye Or transforming, as in the previous case, M, +N, ΕΟ gare ee οὐ πὰ (13) [351] wherein δῆ, is formed by dividing dy DY aa ee ane ae ἘΠ: : changing in the result “1 into 7), *2 into Nn, SLC, ae 49 Now the final solution of the problem proposed will be given by assigning their determined values to the terms of the fraction BEG: Olas Kn 2 ἢ Prob. τὺ τ ν΄ Prob. Ὁ Hence, therefore, by (11) and (13) we have M, : ἢ Ὁ “τ Prob. soug M+ N, A very slight attention to the mode of formation of the functions 47, and JV, will show that the process may be greatly simplified. We may, indeed, exhibit the solution of the general problem in the form of a rule, as follows: Reject from the function (41, %, .. %,) the constituent 4,.. 4%, 17 tt ts therein contained, suppress in all the remain- ong constituents the factors 1, %,, &c., and change generally in the result x, into se Call thts result M,. —C,p, Again, replace in the function (4,, %, ..%,) the con- stituent <,.. 4%, tf 11 ἐς therein found, by unity ; suppress in all the remaining constituents the factors %,, ἅς, δῶ, and ε(τ -- 2.) aot Nees) Then the solution required will be expressed by the formula change generally in the result x, into 368 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT M, M+,’ equations ( -- αΖι) “(ἃ aes) "_fyaa(r=a)) -- ὕπο - 20}. G5) ν μ΄ ἘΡ--[ΞὉ It may be added, that the limits of μαὶ and ν are the same as in the previous problem. This might be inferred from the general principle of continuity ; but conditions of limita- tion, which are [352] probably sufficient, may also be estab- lished by other considerations. Thus from the demonstration of the general method in probabilities, Chap. XVII. Prop. IV., it appears that the Guanes τι το 47.2.5. in athe primary system, ol, al- gebraic equations must be posztzve proper fractions. Now χε (τ -- 2.) πο Gay): Hence generally 2, must be a positive quantity, and there- fore we must have vs¢,(1 -- 2,). In like manner since we have Xb, Se gs: C,Pr eae) eo ope we must have generally μβωΐ,. 16. It is probable that the two classes of conditions thus represented are together sufficient to determine generally which of the roots of the equations determining y« and ν are to be taken. Let us take in particular the case in which i= δ... {τ we have tees = ERP PY) = (ey + eghy) + SAPs, Shiri ag: ὦ 1 -- (4-40) )ooP2 vV=1-6p),—%pot+ rf ᾿ (14) μ and y being determined by the solution of the system of — PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 369 Whence, since u>c,p, we have generally V « Fn Here we find M eA δ ete ΩΣ ; : bop, Μ - nPn ose o(1 - 24) "ΠΝ C(I Pn) ; : v— (1 -2.) v—¢,(1 — Pn) whence we have the following result— [354] Probability that if some one alone 5 Dr Of the causes Ἢ... 4.1 μ -- Cpr present itself, the event Z will sy obra y Cae aa, follow μποΐ, ~v—6(1 -- 2,) Let it be observed that this case is quite different from the well-known one in which the mutually exclusive character of the causes A, . . A, is one of the elements of the data, ex- pressing a condition under which the very observations by which the probabilities of A,, A,, &c. are supposed to have been determined, were made. Consider, lastly, the case in which $(4 .. ,)=4,4,. τὶ Prete Myx Sb» οὖς αδι-- ad (μ τ αΖ1) Ὁ: (μ a CrPn) μ᾿ μ πα αὶ πὶ 1) q(1-p;) «+ οἱ -2Ξ2.) ἘΠ 20,5. οἴ τ N,= as 2 Waa =A)} fy =4(1- 2}} γον Hence the following result— Probability that if all 4 Causes το ΑΓ, con-| Doe Pv spire, the event 25 a ἘΡ ey ee 012)...» τ as follow This expression assumes, as it ought to do, the value 1 when any one of the quantities p, . . 2 is equal to 1. 17. PROBLEM VIII.—Certain causes A,, A,, . . A, being so restricted that they cannot all fail, but still can only occur in certain definite combinations denoted by the equation $(A,, a ou © Aa, PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 371 and there being given the separate probabilities Ge. Cer the said causes, and the corresponding probabilities je ΤΑ than an event £ will follow if those respective causes are realized, required the probability of the event ἢ. This problem differs from the one last considered in several particulars, but chiefly in this, that the restriction denoted by the equation $(4,.. A,)=1, forms one of the data, and is supposed [355] to be furnished by or to be accordant with the very experience from which the knowledge of the numerical elements of the problem is derived. Representing the events A,..A, by #,.., respect- ively, and the event & by z, we have— Prob: ἀξ, ΡΙΟΡ Yeo. (1) Let us assume, generally, ἌΞΕΙΝ then combining the system of equations thus indicated with the equations ree = Ore, Oe ie OL a furnished in the data, we ultimately find, as the developed expression of g, 22x) Oni. ΣΙΝ (2) where X represents in succession each constituent found in ¢@, and 7 a similar series of constituents of the symbols t,..%,; X(X7) including only symmetrical constituents with reference to the two sets of symbols. The method of reduction to be employed in the present case is so similar to the one already exemplified in former problems, that I shall merely exhibit the results to which it leads. We find Prob. z= (3) M M+N’ with the relations My Ὄπ δ Nn ey (4) “Pi ΕΣ δία -2}) C(I = 2.) 372 HE LAWS On THROCGHT Wherein J/ is formed by suppressing in ¢(7,. . %,) all the factors 7, . . #,, and changing in the result x, into m,, x, into m,, while WV is formed by substituting in 27, , for m,, &c. ; moreover J/, consists of that portion of 27 of which m, is a factor, MV, of that portion of VV of which 7, is a factor ; and so on, Let us take, in illustration, the particular case in which the causes A,.. A, are mutually exclusive. Here we have οί ἀπ Oe ee ey, [356] Whence M=m,+m.,.. +Mn, N=n, +m. τ +Mn; M,=m,, N,=m, &c. Substituting, we have Me eae {πο τὸς Mn Ay ey. OP; (ay Uf εἰ - 2.) rg — Pn) Hence we find ἘΠ Εν ΠΝ A AT Py + lah.» . τωι ' or M VN. CP, a as Say Le Hence, by (3), RIGO ΞΘ 07. Ἐπ}. a known result. There are other particular cases in which the system (4) admits of ready solution. It is, however, obvious in most instances it would lead to results of great complexity. Nor does it seem probable that the existence of a functional rela- tion among causes, such as is assumed in the data of the general problem, will often be presented in actual experience ; if we except only the particular cases above discussed. Had the general problem been modified by the restriction that the event ΖΦ cannot occur, all the causes A, . . A, being absent, instead of the restriction that the said causes cannot all fail, the remaining condition denoted by the equation (A, . . A,)=1 being retained, we should have found for the final logical equation g=2(XT7)+03(X ), —— PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 373 x(X) being, as before, equal to Olt. . #.), but 2(X T) formed by rejecting from ᾧ the particular constituent 4,..4, if therein contained, and then multiplying each #-constituent of the result by the corresponding ¢-constituent. It is obvious that in the particular case in which the causes are mutually exclusive the value of Prob. g hence deduced will be the same as before. 18. PROBLEM IX.—Assuming the data of any of the pre- [357]vious problems, let it be required to determine the pro- bability that if the event Z present itself, it will be associated with the particular cause 4,; in other words, to determine the @ posterior? probability of the cause A, when the event E has been observed to occur. In this case we must seek the value of the fraction Prob. x,2 Be ay ds Prob. s ’ Prob. z’ by the data. (1) As in the previous problems the value of Prob. z has been assigned upon different hypotheses relative to the connexion or want of connexion of the causes, it is evident that in all those cases the present problem is susceptible of a determinate solution by simply substituting in (1) the value of that element thus determined. If the a priort probabilities of the causes are equal, we have c,=c,..=c,. Hence for the different causes the value (1) will vary directly as the quantity 23,.. Wherefore what- ever the nature of the connexion among the causes, the a pos- tertort probability of each cause will be proportional to the probability of the observed event # when that cause is known toexist. The particular case of this theorem, which presents itself when the causes are mutually exclusive, is well known. We have then Prous Crs Py ΕΙΣ ΣΙ ee, the values οὗ c, . . ς, being equal. Although, for the demonstration of these and similar theorems in the particular case in which the causes are 374 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT mutually exclusive, it is not necessary to introduce the functional symbol ¢, which is, indeed, to claim for ourselves the choice of all possible and conceivable hypotheses of the connexion of the causes, yet, under every form, the solution by the method of this work of problems, in which the number of the data is indefinitely great, must always partake of a somewhat complex character. Whether the systematic evolution which it presents, first, of the logical, secondly, of the numerical relations of a problem, furnishes any com- pensation for the length and occasional tediousness of its [358] processes, I do not presume to inquire. Its chief value undoubtedly consists in its power,—in the mastery which it gives us over questions which would apparently baffle the unassisted strength of human reason. For this cause it has not been deemed superfluous to exhibit in this chapter its application to problems, some of which may possibly be regarded as repulsive, from their difficulty, without being recommended by any prospect of immediate utility. Of the ulterior value of such speculations it is, | conceive, impossible for us, at present, to form any decided judgment. 19. The following problem is of a much easier description than the previous ones, | PROBLEM X.— The probability of the occurrence of a certain watural phenomenon under given circumstances ts p. Obser- vation has also recorded a probability a of the existence of a permanent cause of that phenomenon, t.e. of a cause which would always produce the event under the circumstances supposed. What is the probability that if the phenomenon 7s observed to occur n times in succession under the given circumstances, tt will occur the n+" time? What also ts the probability, after such observation, of the existence of the permanent cause referred to ? FIRST CASE. —Let ¢ represent the existence of a permanent cause, and %, +,,.. %,,, the successive occurrences of the natural phznomenon. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 375 If the permanent cause exist, the events Ay, 495... Vy. ἈΓδ necessary consequences, Hence f=0x,, f=vx,, &e, and eliminating the indefinite symbols, 3 ‘(1 —2,)=0, ¢(1—x,)=0, 41 —«,,,)=0. Now we are to seek the probability that if the combination Ἔν, %, happen, the event x,,, will happen, z.e. we are to seek the value of the fraction Prob. aX. ἄμμι, PIOD) ivy an We witefrst.seck the value of Prob:-4,7, 3: [359] Represent the combination 4,2, . . x, by w, then we have the following logical equations : {i —x,)=0, #1—-x,)=0 .. f1—%,)=0, ee ee Reducing the last to the form εὐ τς αι εξ 0) Fw ie, and adding it to the former ones, we have Die x) ee ταιτ γε a, α) Ξο τ wherein > extends to all values of z from 1 to , for the one logical equation of the data. With this we must connect the numerical conditions, Prob. x,= Prob. x, .. =Prob. x,=, Prob. f=a; and our object is to find Prob. w. From (1) we have wy a EAE = σὴ + 1% ere Bi vl Σίι = Hi) +H Hy - . Hug Kye . . Hn es (2) χα ee ΣῈ ike AE ᾿ on developing with respect to 5 This result must further be developed with respect to 4%, %,.. %,,. Now if we make 4,-—1, %=1,.. 4%, =1, the coefficients both of ¢ and of 1—¢ become 1. If we give to the same 376 TARE LAWS CFL, THOUGHT, symbols any other set of values formed by the interchange of o and 1, it is evident that the coefficient of ¢ will become negative, while that of 1—¢ will become 0. Hence the full development (2) will be Ὁ χα. ἀπ αι, a Mall Ξε Ol Aan ee 2) Ὶ . I : I + constituents whose coefficients are — , or equivalent to — . ° ο Here we have Vee Lt a AE oP) 33 eo ce, τὶ}: ἢ ΞΕ Xo. - ἌΣ τ ἢ» whence, passing from Logic to Algebra, [360] “115 - - f+ αχ( - ξ ἢ 2%.» Xb+H—(1 - δ) - POO oe ΣΧ ee Ζ Be Χο Be Ot 5 es er nt + Xf 4)". 172 XX.» ΧΙΓΠῚ p a Prob. zw = 1. Ὁ Ὡ : Χο . . x,t+1-—¢ From the forms of the above equations it is evident that we have 7,=4,..=4%,. Replace then each of these quantities by x, and the system becomes αι ποῖ 2" py y τ p a μεθ, τ ΧΙ J from which we readily deduce 2 ᾿ς a. n—1 Prob. w= Prob. #,%, . . %,»=a+(p— a)( ) : 1 ΞΩ If in this result we change z into z+1, we get Φιαν Γτόῦ, eWeek, eat pa) =) I-—@ Hence we find— “εῳ- 254" ΒτΟθ 2 2, I-a angie, EIOD. 4X, era a as the expression of the probability that if the phanomenon (3) PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 377 be z times repeated, it will also present itself the 2+ 1” time. _ By the method of Chapter XIX. it is found that a cannot exceed 2 in value. The following verifications are obvious :— ist. If @=o, the expression reduces to Ὁ, as it ought to do. For when it is certain that no permanent cause exists, the successive occurrences of the phenomenon are independent. 2nd. If p=1, the expression becomes 1, as it ought to do. rd. If 7 —a, the expression becomes 1, unless a—o, “If the probability of a phenomenon is equal to the probability that there [361] exists a cause which under given circum- stances would always produce it, then the fact that that phenomenon has ever been noticed under those circum- stances, renders certain its re-appearance under the same. Ἐ 4th. As z increases, the expression approaches in value to unity. This indicates that the probability of the recurrence of the event increases with the frequency of its successive appearances,—a result agreeable to the natural laws of expectation. SECOND CASE.—We are now to seek the probability a postertort of the existence of a permanent cause of the phenomenon. This requires that we ascertain the value of the fraction LODE IX i Σ. b] Prob. να: the denominator of which has already been determined. To determine the numerator assume Ζχηλο . - Xp =D, * As wecan neither re-enter nor recall the state of infancy, we are unable to say how far such results as the above serve to explain the confidence with which young children connect events whose association they have once perceived. But we may conjecture, generally, that the strength of their expectations is due to the necessity of inferring (as a part of their rational nature), and the narrow but impressive experience upon which the faculty is exercised. Hence the reference of every kind of sequence to that of cause and effect. A little friend of the author’s, on being put to bed, was heard to ask his brother the pertinent question, —‘* Why does going to sleep at night make it light in the morning?” The brother, who was a year older, was able to reply, that it would be light in the morning even if little boys did not go to sleep at night. 378 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT then proceeding as before, we obtain for the logical development, W=1X,Xy . . αι Ἔσ( — 2). Whence, passing from Logic to Algebra, we have at once Prob, Ζ ὦ, a result which might have been anticipated. Substituting then for the numerator and denominator of the above frac- tion their values, we have for the ὦ posterior? probability of a permanent cause, the expression [362] a ie n—1 pol) I It is obvious that the value of this expression increases with the value of x. | I am indebted to a learned correspondent,* whose original contributions to the theory of probabilities have already been referred to, for the following verification of the first of the above results (3). ‘‘ The whole a priort probability of the event (under the circumstances) being 2, and the probability of some cause C which would necessarily produce it, a, let x be the proba- bility that it will happen if no such cause as C exist. Then we have the equation p=at(t—a)x, whence 2 τ I= @ Now the phenomemon observed is the occurrence of the event # times. The a priori probability of this would be— I supposing C to exist, #£" supposing C not to exist ; whence the a posterior? probability that C exists is a a +(1—a)x” : that C does not exist is (1 —a)x" a+(t—a)a" * Professor Donkin. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 379 - Consequently the probability of another occurrence is a (1 -- a)x” xX 1+ a+(t-a)x” a+(1—a)x" Ὁ or idols Sc a a+(1—a)x” Ὁ ~ [363] which, on replacing x by its value2—%, will be found I—a’ to agree with 3.” Similar verifications might, it is probable, also be found _ for the following results, obtained by the direct application of the general method. The probability, under the same circumstances, that if, out of #z occasions, the event happen 7. times, and fail x—r times, it will happen on the z+ 1” time is ἘΠῚ α- (2 -- Da Breet 4 wherein m2" 2h) 33a Ht ΤῊ ae 2. cere 7c 72 The probability of a permanent cause (7 being less than 7) is O. This is easily verified. If p be the probability of an event, and c the probability that if it occur it will be due to a permanent cause ; the pro- bability after 2 successive observed occurrences that it will recur on the (x+1)” similar occasion is c+(1 -0)x" Cha oa wherein 3 TAG τον τ 72 20. It is remarkable that the solutions of the previous pro- blems are void of any arbitrary element. We should scarcely, from the appearance of the data, have anticipated such a circumstance, It is, however, to be observed, that in all - those problems the probabilities of the causes involved are supposed to be known a priort. In the absence of this as- 380 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT sumed element of knowledge, it seems probable that arbitrary constants would xecessarily appear in the final solution. Some confirmation of this remark is afforded by aclass of problems to which considerable attention has been directed, and which, in conclusion, I shall briefly consider. [364] It has been observed that there exists in the heavens a large number of double stars of extreme closeness. Either these apparent instances of connexion have some physical ground or they have not. If they have not, we may regard the phenomenon of a double star as the accidental result of a ‘random distribution ” of stars over the celestial vault, z.e. of a distribution which would render it just as probable that either member of the binary system should appear in one spot as in another. If this hypothesis be assumed, and if the number of stars of a requisite brightness be known, we can determine what is the probability that two of them should be found within such limits of mutual distance as to con- stitute the observed phenomenon. Thus Mitchell,* esti- mating that there are 230 stars in the heavens equal in brightness to 8 Capricorni, determines that it is 80 to 1 against such a combination being presented were those stars distributed at random. The probability, when such a com- bination has been observed, that there exists between its members a physical ground of connexion, is then required. Again, the sum of the inclinations of the orbits of the ten known planets to the plane of the ecliptic in the year 1801 was Ο15 4187, according to the French measures. Were all inclinations equally probable, Laplace + determines, that there would be only the excessively small probability ‘OOOO000I 1235 that the mean of the inclinations should fall within the limit thus assigned. And he hence concludes, that there is a very high probability in favour of a disposing cause, by which the inclinations of the planetary orbits have been confined within such narrow bounds. Professor De Morgan, taking the sum of the inclinations at 92°, gives to * Phil. Transactions, An. 1767. + Lhéorte Analytigue des Probabilités, p. 276. + Encyclopedia Metropolitana, art. ““ Probabilities.” nae Gag PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 381 _ the above probability the value ‘oooo0012, and infers that “1 is I : 00000012, that there was a necessary cause in the _ formation of the solar system for the inclinations being what they are.” An equally determinate conclusion has been drawn from observed coincidences between the direction of [3657 circular polarization in rock-crystal, and that of certain oblique faces in its crystalline structure. * These problems are all of a similar character. A certain hypothesis is framed, of the various possible consequences of which we are able to assign the probabilities with perfect _rigour. Now some actual result of observation being found among those consequences, and its hypothetical probability being therefore known, it is required thence to determine the probability of the hypothesis assumed, or its contrary. In Mitchell’s problem, the hypothesis is that of a ‘‘random distribution of the stars,”—the possible and observed con- _ sequence, the appearance of a close double star. The very small probability of such a result is held to imply that the probability of the hypothesis is equally small, or, at least, of the same order of smallness. And hence the high and, and as some think, determinate probability of a disposing cause in the stellar arrangements is inferred. Similar re- marks apply to the other examples adduced. 21. The general problem, in whatsoever form it may be presented, admits only of an zudefinite solution. Let # re- present the proposed hypothesis, y a phanomenon which might occur as one of its possible consequences, and whose calculated probability, on the assumption of the truth of the hypothesis, is 23, and let it be required to determine the probability that if the phenomenon y is observed, the hypo- thesis x is true. The very data of this problem cannot be expressed without the introduction of an arbitrary element. _ We can only write Prob. x=a, Prob. xy=ap; (1) a being perfectly arbitrary, except that it must fall within * Edinburgh Review, No. 185, p. 32. This article, though not entirely free from error, is well worthy of attention. 382 THE LAWS ‘OF THOUGHT the limits o and 1 inclusive. If then P represent the con- ditional probability sought, we have ἔτοσς 2) ae 88 (2) ~ Prob. y Prob. γ᾽ It remains then to determine Prob, γ. [366] Let xy =z, then ee mtx +21 - 2) +0(1 = Ax + τα ~ 2)(1 ~ αν). (3) t x Hence observing that Prob. =a, Prob. ¢=ap, and passing from Logic to Algebra, we have 7 te τ κα - t)x τεῦ - 2 Prob. y= 3 with the relations τειν ἐν a =fx+1-f, Hence we readily find | Prob. y=ap+c(1-a). (4) Now recurring to (3), we find that ¢ is the probability, that if the event (1 —¢)(1—~) occur, the event y will occur. But (1 -¢)(1-x)=(1-xy)(I-x)=1-4%, Hence ¢ is the probability that tf the event x do not occur, the event y will occur. Substituting the value of Prob. y in (2), we have the following theorem : The calculated probability of any phenomenon y, upon an assumed physical hypothesis x, being p, the a posteriori pro- bability P of the physical hypothesis, when the phenomenon has been observed, ts expressed by the equation ἜΘΟΣ aes apt+c(1—a)’ (5) where a and c are arbitrary constants, the former representing the a priori probability of the hypothesis, the latter the pro- bability that tf the hypothesis were false, the event y would present itself. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 383 The principal conclusion deducible from the above theorem is that, other things being the same, the value of P in- creases and diminishes simultaneously with that of . Hence the greater or less the probability of the phanomenon when the hypothesis is assumed, the greater or less is the pro- bability of the hypothesis when the phenomenon has been observed. When 2. is very small, then generally P also is small, unless either ὦ is large or c small. [367] Hence, secondly, if the probability of the phznomenon is very small when the hypothesis is assumed, the probability of the hypothesis is very small when the phenomenon is ob- served, unless either the a 2220γὲ probability a of the hypo- thesis is large, or the probability of the phanomenon upon any other hypothesis small. The formula (5) admits of exact verification in various cases, as when c=O, or a@=1, ora=O. But it is evident that it does not, unless there be means for determining the values of aand ¢, yield a definite value of P. Any solutions which profess to accomplish this object, either are erroneous in principle, or involve a tacit assumption respecting the above arbitrary elements. Mr. De Morgan’s solution of Laplace’s problem concerning the existence of adetermining cause of the narrow limits within which the inclinations of the planetary orbits to the plane of the ecliptic are confined, appears to me to be of the latter description. Having found a proba- bility 23 = ‘00000012, that the sum of the inclinations would be less than 92° were all degrees of inclination equally pro- bable in each orbit, this able writer remarks: ‘‘If there be a reason for the inclinations being as described, the proba- bility of the event is 1. Consequently, it is I : ὉΟΟΟΟΟΙΖ (2.6. 1: 2), that there was a necessary cause in the formation of the solar system for the inclinations being what they are.” Now this result is what the equation (5) would really give, if, I assigning to 23 the above value, we should assume c= 1, a= > For we should thus find ea ee 384 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT I ἘΠ δοὺς ΤΡ» gee To fk op. (6) But P representing the probability, @ posteriori, that all inclinations are equally probable,1—VP is the probability, @ posteriori, that such is not the case, or, adopting Mr. De Morgan’s alternative, that a determining cause exists. The equation (6), therefore, agrees with Mr. De Morgan’s result. 22. Are we, however, justified in assigning to a and ¢ par- ticular values? I am strongly disposed to think that we are not. [368] The question is of less importance in the special instance than in its ulterior bearings. In the received applica- tions of the theory of probabilities, arbitrary constants do not | explicitly appear ; but in the above, and in many other in- stances sanctioned by the highest authorities, some virtual determination of them has been attempted. And this circum- stance has given to the results of the theory, especially in reference to questions of causation, a character of definite precision, which, while on the one hand it has seemed to exalt the dominion and extend the province of numbers, even beyond.the measure of their ancient claim to rule the world ; ἢ on the other hand has called forth vigorous protests against their intrusion into realms in which conjecture is the only basis of inference. The very fact of the appearance of arbitrary constants in the solutions of problems like the above, treated by the method of this work, seems to imply, that definite solution is impossible, and to mark the point where inquiry ought to stop. We possess indeed the means of in- terpreting those constants, but the experience which is thus indicated is as much beyond our reach as the experience which would preclude the necessity of any attempt at solution whatever. + * Mundum regunt numeri. + See an interesting paper by Prof. Forbes in the Philosophical Magazine, Dec. 1850 ; also Mill’s Zogzc, chap, xviii. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 385 Another difficulty attendant upon these questions, and inherent, perhaps, in the very constitution of our faculties, is that of precisely defining what is meant by Order. The manifestations of that principle, except in very complex in- stances, we have no difficulty in detecting, nor do we hesitate to impute to it an almost necessary foundation in causes operating under Law. But to assign to it a standard of numerical value would be a vain, not to say a presumptuous, endeavour. Yet must the attempt be made, before we can aspire to weigh with accuracy the probabilities of different constitutions of the universe, so as to determine the elements upon which alone a definite solution of the problems in question can be established. 23. The most usual mode of endeavouring to evade the necessary arbitrarinesss of the solution of problems in the theory of [369] probabilities which rest upon insufficient data, is to assign to some element whose real probability is unknown all possible degrees of probability ; to suppose that these degrees of probability are themselves equally probable ; and, regarding them as so many distinct causes of the phznomenon observed, to apply the theorems which represent the case of an effect due to some one of a number of equally probable but mutually exclusive causes (Problem IX.). For instance, the rising of the sun after a certain interval of darkness having been observed m times in succession, the probability of its again rising under the same circumstances is determined, on received principles, in the following manner. Let fp be any unknown probability between o and 1, and ς (infinitesimal and constant) the probability, that the probability of the sun’s rising after an interval of darkness lies between the limits and p+dp. Then the probability that the sun will rise # times in succession is 1 cf Pap 0 and the probability that he will do this, and will rise again, 25 386 THE. LAWS'‘OF THOUGHT A : . . . . ° 3 or, which is the same thing, that he will rise #2+ 1 times in ~ succession, 15 C i ods, Hence the probability that if he rise # times in succession, he will rise the (#+1)” time, is 1 [Pe m4 I “| "Δ m+2’ 0 the known and generally received solution. The above solution is usually founded upon a supposed analogy of the problem with that of the drawing of balls from an urn containing a mixture of black and white balls, between which all possible numerical ratios are assumed to be equally probable. And it is remarkable, that there are two or three distinct hypotheses which lead to the same final — result. For instance, if the balls are finite in number, and those which are drawn are not [370] replaced, or if they are infinite in number, whether those drawn are replaced or not, then, supposing that 7 successive drawings have yielded only white balls, the probability of the issue of a white ball at the (m+1)” drawing is M+ κα m+ 2 It has been said, that the principle involved in the above and in similar applications is that of the equal distribution of our knowledge, or rather of our ignorance—the assigning to different states of things of which we know nothing, and upon the very ground that we know nothing, equal degrees of probability. 1 apprehend, however, that this is an arbi- trary method of procedure. Instances may occur, and one such has been adduced, in which different hypotheses lead to the same final conclusion. But those instances are ex- ceptional. With reference to the particular problem in question, it is shown in the memoir cited, that there is one * See a memoir by Bishop Terrot, Zainburgh Trans., vol. xx. part iv. PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 387 hypothesis, viz., when the balls are finite in number and not replaced, which leads to a different conclusion, and it is easy to see that there are other hypotheses, as strictly involving the principle of the ‘‘equal distribution of knowledge or ignorance,” which would also conduct to conflicting results. 24. For instance, let the case of sunrise be represented by the drawing of a white ball from a bag containing an infinite number of balls, which are all either black or white, and let the assumed principle be, that αὐ possible constttu- tions of the system of balls are equally probable. By a con- stitution of the system, | mean an arrangement which assigns to every ball in the system a determinate colour, either black or white. Let us thence seek the probability, that if 7 white balls are drawn in m drawings, a white ball will be drawn in the (#+1)” drawing. First, suppose the number of the balls to be μ, and let the symbols 11, 22». . 4, be appropriated to them in the follow- ing manner. Let x, denote that event which consists in the 7. ball of the system being white, the proposition declaratory of such a state of things being #,=1. In like manner the compound [371] symbol 1 -- ας will represent the circumstance of the z” ball being black. It is evident that the several constituents formed of the entire set of symbols 4,, 4%, . - %, will represent in like manner the several possible constitu- tions of the system of balls with respect to blackness and whiteness, and the number of such constitutions being 2", the probability of each will, in accordance with the hypothesis, I cee . be re This is the value which we should find if we sub- stituted in the expression of any constituent for each of the I που 47. 2... τ the value = Hence, then, the pro- bability of any event which can be expressed as a series of constituents of the above description, will be found by sub- ane : : I stituting in such expression the value 5 for each of the above symbols, 388 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT Now the larger mw is, the less probable it is that any ball | which has been drawn and replaced will be drawn again. As © μ᾽ approaches to infinity, this probability approaches to 0. — And this being the case, the state of the balls actually drawn | 5 can be expressed as a logical function of m of the symbols — a. te, τι λα therciolc, by development, as a series of | constituents of the said » symbols. Hence, therefore, its | probability will be found by substituting for each of the | symbols, whether in the undeveloped or the developed form, the value ὦ. But this is the very substitution which it would 2 be necessary, and which it would suffice, to make, if the pro- bability of a white ball at each drawing were known, a prior, I to be -. 2 It follows, therefore, that if the number of balls be infinite, ~ and all constitutions of the system equally probable, the probability of drawing m white balls in succession will be se a “= and the probability of drawing # + 1 white balls in succession oe whence the probability that after # white balls have been drawn, the next drawing will furnish a white one, will be 2 In other [372] words, past experience does not int «“ this case affect future expectation. 25. It may be satisfactory to verify this result by ordinary methods. To accomplish this, we shall seek— First : The probability of drawing 7 white balls, and 2 —7 black balls, in 2) trials, out of a bag containing yu balls, every ball being replaced after drawing, and all constitutions of the systems being equally probable, ὦ priorz. Secondly : The value which this probability assumes when pw becomes infinite. Thirdly : The probability hence derived, that if #z white balls are drawn in succession, the #+1” ball drawn will be white also. |; Sf ἐξ. PROBLEM S°OW CAUSES 389 The probability that ~ white balls and p—,r black ones will be drawn in 2. trials out of an urn containing μ balls, each ball being replaced after trial, and all constitutions of: the system as above defined being equally probable, is equal to the sum of the probabilities of the same result upon the separate hypotheses of there being no white balls, 1 white ball,-—lastly « white balls inthe urn. Therefore, it is the sum of the probabilities of this result on the hypothesis of there being x white balls, 2 varying from 0 to μ. Now supposing that there are z white balls, the probability of drawing a white ball in a single drawing is “and the a probability of drawing 7 white balls and 2 —7 black ones in a particular order in 2 drawings, is πὰ But there being as many such orders as there are combina- tions of x things in p things, the total probability of drawing -y white balls in 2 drawings out of the system of u& balls of which z are white, is pI po) τ ay : =\i (1) Again, the number of constitutions of the system of μ balls, which admit of exactly balls being white, is [373] μίμ - 1)... (ᾳ--π τ) Li Τὰ 70 and the number of possible constitutions of the system is 2". Hence the probability that exactly 7 balls are white is Lace Vso et ica) 1. 2 9 27 ΝΣ Multiplying (1) by this expression, and taking the sum of the products from z=o to m=, We have Heat paregrylenD nA BA 2 9 μ τ.,2 Ὁ. 2-0 To eee 2 for the expression of the total probability, that out of a 390 THE LAWS ΟΣ ΤΟΣ system of « balls of which all constitutions are equally pro- bable, γ white balls will issue in drawings. Now grew) ss (want Hee -")" n=0 | Pay ae Ὁ: 25 μ πε ER ae oan ae _ yt 3). + (eo ei. Ve é? .. (8=0) n=0 1 25. 0 222 μ ἰ “(1 ἜΣ -ὴς (un t1) ag μ n=0 1.2, -22\(1- 2)" sey, οἷ μ ad : so that P(D)e9=p(~)e". Βυῖ D standing for the symbol a by a known theorem, 2m 3.m f= 1 4 Aor + eal 1}. cath t(¢—1)(¢- 2). LZ 1.7. 1 D1 + &)u={1+Ao —1)+&c.}(1 + 6). In the second member let ¢°=%, then a ρος δὲ D"(1 + εθ)μ = (1 + Ao™x ee x? + &c.)(1 + x)¥ dx v ae »since : a DD ὃ De ay iar ( 1) (D-it+1)=x ᾿ [374] In the second member of the above equation, perform- ing the differentiations and making x= 1 (since 9=0), we get D"(1 + 8)" = p(Ao") 2-1 ME (Aon ee + &e. te The last term of the second member of this equation will be | Mw—t). . (u—-m+1)A™”™ 1 2. ΠΣ 2u-™ μίβ τα) μ᾿ ἘΈ ΤΠ ΖΡ, since A”o"=1.2.. m. Μπέη μ is a large quantity this | term exceeds all the others in value, and as μ᾿ approaches to infinity tends to become infinitely great in comparison with them. And as moreover it assumes the form ,”2""", we have, on passing to the limit, 7 Dey pe εθ)μ = oh ae (£) 2h, 2 PROBLEMS ON CAUSES 391 Hence if @(D) represent any function of the symbol D, which is capable of being expanded in a series of ascending powers of D, we have D 0)u = ΕῚ H(D)(x + δ). = φίδ):», (4) if@=oand n= oo. Strictly speaking, this implies that the ratio of the two members of the above equation approaches a state of equality, as u increases towards infinity, θ being equal to o. By means of this theorem, the last member of (3) reduces to the torm Aa) ahs a) Εν τὸ Dba oe, 2é— | — . 2ΜΧᾺ2 2 2 P(p-1).. or ΤΟΣ ee OA 2 Hence (2) gives as the expression for the probability that from an urn con- taining an infinite number of black and white balls, all con- stitutions of the system being equally probable, 7 white balls will issue in 2 drawings. Hence, making p=m, r=m, the probability that in m drawings all the balls will be white is G) , and the proba- bility that this [375] will be the case, and that moreover the m+1 (m+ 1)" drawing will yield a white ball is (3: , whence the probability, that if the first # drawings yield white balls only, the (m +1)" drawing will also yield a white ball, is De ΓΝ L. () +() ae and generally, any proposed result will have the same pro- bability as if it were an even chance whether each particular drawing yielded a white or a black ball. This agrees with the conclusion before obtained. 26. These results only illustrate the fact, that when the defect of data is supplied by hypothesis, the solutions will, 392 LHE LA WS OF THOUGHT in general, vary with the nature of the hypotheses assumed ; so that the question still remains, only more definite in form, whether the principles of the theory of probabilities serve to guide us in the election of such hypotheses. I have already expressed my conviction that they do not—a conviction strengthened by other reasons than those above stated. Thus, a definite solution of a problem having been found by the method of this work, an equally definite solution is sometimes attainable by the same method when one of the data, suppose Prob. +=f,, is omitted. But I have not been able to discover any mode of deducing the second solution from the first by zxztegratzon, with respect to 2 supposed variable within limits determined by Chap. XIX. This de- duction would, however, I conceive, be possible, were the principle adverted to in Art. 23 valid. »-Still it is with diffidence that I express my dissent on these points from mathematicians generally, and more especially from one who, of English writers, has most fully entered into the spirit and the methods of Laplace ; and I venture to hope, that a question, second to none other in the Theory of Probabilities in importance, will receive the careful attention which it deserves. cg ee ee ee ee ee ee oe [376] CHART ER Ox] PARTICULAR APPLICATION OF THE PREVIOUS GENERAL METHOD TO THE QUESTION OF THE PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS I. ON the presumption that the general method of this treatise for the solution of questions in the theory of probabilities, has been sufficiently elucidated in the previous chapters, it is proposed here to enter upon one of its practical applications selected out of the wide field of social statistics, viz., the estimation of the probability of judgments. Per- haps this application, if weighed by its immediate results, is not the best that could have been chosen. One of the first conclusions to which it leads is that of the necessary insufficiency of any data that experience alone can furnish, for the accomplishment of the most important object of the inquiry. But in setting clearly before us the xecesszty of hypotheses as supplementary to the data of experience, and in enabling us to deduce with rigour the consequences of any hypothesis which may be assumed, the method accom- plishes all that properly lies within its scope. And it may be remarked, that in questions which relate to the conduct of our own species, hypotheses are more justifiable than in questions such as those referred to in the concluding sections of the previous chapter. Our general experience of human nature comes in aid of the scantiness and imperfection of statistical records. 2. The elements involved in problems relating to criminal assize are the following :— ist. The probability that a particular member of the jury will form a correct opinion upon the case. 2nd. The probability that the accused party is guilty. 393 394 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT 3rd. The probability that he will be condemned, or that he will be acquitted. 4th. The probability that his condemnation or acquittal will be just. 5th. The constitution of the jury. [377] 6th. The data furnished by experience, such as the relative numbers of cases in which unanimous decisions have been arrived at, or particular majorities obtained; the number of cases in which decisions have been reversed by superior courts, &c. Again, the class of questions under consideration may be regarded as either direct or inverse. The direct questions of probability are those in which the probability of correct decision for each member of the tribunal, or of guilt for the accused party, are supposed to be known a priorz, and in which the probability of a decision of a particular kind, or with a definite majority, is sought. Inverse problems are those in which, from the data furnished by experience, it is required to determine some element which, though it stand to those data in the relation of cause to effect, cannot directly be made the subject of observation ; as when from the records of the decisions of courts it is required to deter- mine the probability that a member of a court will judge correctly. To this species of problems, the most difficult and the most important of the whole series, attention will chiefly be directed here. 3. There is no difficulty in solving the direct problems referred to in the above enumeration. Suppose there is but one juryman. Let & be the probability that the accused person is guilty ; x the probability that the jurymen will form a correct opinion ; X the probability that the accused person will be condemned : then— kx = probability that the accused party is guilty, and that the juryman judges him to be guilty. (1 —&)(1 —*)= probability that the accused person is inno- cent, and that the juryman pronounces him guilty. ΑΝ eS ee Ee | ee eS ee ere PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 395 Now these being the only cases in which a verdict of condemnation can be given, and being moreover mutually exclusive, we have X=hx + (1 - &)(1 - 2), (1) In like manner, if there be x jurymen whose separate probabilities of correct judgment are z,, 4, .. #,, the pro- bability of an unanimous verdict of condemnation will be X= ha y% . . X+(1- kU -2,)(1 τα) (1 2... [378] Whence, if the several probabilities a, ty 2 ale equal, and are each represented by x, we have X=hx" + (1 -&)(1— x)", (2) The probability in the latter case, that the accused person is guilty, will be i kx” + (1-21 - 4)" All these results assume, that the events whose proba- bilites are denoted by 4, x,, 7, &c., are independent, an assumption which, however, so far as we are concerned, is involved in the fact that those events are the only ones of which the probabilities are given. The probability of condemnation by a given number of voices may be found on the same principles. If a jury is composed of three persons, whose several probabilities of correct decision are +, +’, x’, the probability that. the accused person will be declared guilty by two of them will be ΧΑ, Ξε ξίχα ( -- x") + xx"(1 - x’) + ἀχ (i x)} τὰ - λα = a)(1~ a')a" τα τ λα 2")a + (1 αγα - ἀμ} which if x=2’=7” reduces to φάχξᾳι — x) + 3(ι-- α)χᾷ -- x)? And by the same mode of reasoning, it will appear that if X;, represent the probability that the accused person will be declared guilty by z voices out of a jury consisting of ἡ 396 THE LAWS OF FHOUGHT persons, whose separate probabilities of correct judgment are equal, and represented by +, then πὸ πι a eee ee — xt 4 (1 A) — α)}. (3) 1.2. If the probability of condemnation by a determinate majority ὦ is required, we have simply t-a=n-1, whence Pa +a 2 3 [379] which must be substituted in the above formula. Of course a admits only of such values as make z an integer. lf wis even, those values: are-O, 2.4, &c?; 1f odd, 1,3, 5, &c., as is otherwise obvious. The probability of a condemnation by a majority of at least a given number of voices m, will be found by adding together the following several probabilities determined as above, Viz. : ist. The probability of a condemnation by an exact majority m ; 2nd. The probability of condemnation by the next greater majority m+2; and so on; the last element of the series being the prob- ability of unanimous condemnation. Thus the probability of condemnation by a majority of 4 at least out of 12 jurors, would be PG oe a τ the values of the above terms being given by (3) after making (herein ai 15. 4. When, instead of a jury, we are considering the case of a simple deliberative assembly consisting of persons, whose separate probabilities of correct judgment are denoted by x, the above formule are replaced by others, made some- what more simple by the omission of the quantity &. The probability of unanimous decision is X= x" + (1 -- x)", PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 397 The probability of an agreement of z voices out of the whole number is | x ue) εν (2-t+1) ae Lees (“Ὁ -- αὐτί τ αὐτὰ τα). (4) Of this class of investigations it is unnecessary to give any further account. They have been pursued to a con- siderable extent by Condorcet, Laplace, Poisson, and other writers, who have investigated in particular the modes of calculation and reduction which are necessary to be employed when # andz are large numbers. It is apparent that the whole inquiry is of a very speculative character. The values of x and & cannot be deter-[380]mined by direct observation. We can only presume that they must both in general exceed I the value Ξ that the former, x, must increase with the progress of public intelligence ; while the latter, %, must depend much upon those preliminary steps in the adminis- tration of the law by which persons suspected of crime are brought before the tribunal of their country. It has been remarked by Poisson, that in periods of revolution, as during the Reign of Terror in France, the value of & may fall, if account be taken of political offences, far below the limit I : ; + The history of Europe in days nearer to our own would probably confirm this observation, and would show that it is not from the wild license of democracy alone, that the accusation of innocence is to be apprehended. Laplace makes the assumption, that all values of x from x= ἢ to X— 1, NIM are equally probable. He thus excludes the supposition that a juryman is more likely to be deceived than not, but assumes that within the limits to which the probabilities of individual correctness of judgment are confined, we have no reason to give preference to one value of x over another. This hypothesis is entirely arbitrary, and it would be un- availing here to examine into its consequences. 398 THE LAWS OF THOOCGHT Poisson seems first to have endeavoured to deduce the values of x and &, inferentially, from experience. In the six years from 1825 to 1830 inclusively, the number of in- dividuals accused of crimes against the person before the tribunals of France was 11016, and the number of persons con- demned was 5286. The juries consisted each of 12 persons, and the decision was pronounced by a simple majority. Assuming the above numbers to be sufficiently large for the estimation of probabilities, there would therefore be a prob- 5286 11016’ accused person would be condemned by a simple majority. We should have the equation X, +X... +X 1.=°4782, (5) [381] the general expression for α΄, being given by (3) after making therein z=12. In the year 1831 the law, having received alteration, required a majority of at least four persons for condemnation, and the number of persons tried for crimes against the person during that year being 2046, and the number condemned 743, the probability of the con- 743, 2046’ ability measured by the fraction or ‘4782, that an demnation of an individual by the above majority was or *3631. Hence we should have Met Ag te ty = 3038: (6) Assuming that the values of & and x were the same for the year 1831 as for the previous six years, the two equa- tions (5) and (6) enable us to determine approximately their values. Poisson thus found, k='5354, x= 6786. For crimes against property during the same periods, he found by a similar analysis, k="6744, X= "7771. The solution of the system (5) (6) conducts in each case to two values of £, and to two values of x, the one value in ; I each pair being greater, and the other less, than = It was oo PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 399 assumed, that in each case the larger value should be pre- ferred, it being conceived more probable that a party accused should be guilty than innocent, and more probable that a juryman should form a correct than an erroneous opinion upon the evidence. 5. The data employed by Poisson, especially those which were furnished by the year 1831, are evidently too im- perfect to permit us to attach much confidence to the above determinations of + and £; and it is chiefly for the sake of the method that they are here introduced. It would have been possible to record during the six years, 1825-30, or during any similar period, the number of condemnations pronounced with each possible majority of voices. The values of the several elements Y,, X,, .. X,., were there no reasons of policy to forbid, might have been accurately ascertained. Here then the conception of the general problem, of which Poisson’s is a particular case, arises. How shall we, from [382] this apparently supernumerary system of data, determine the values of x and &? If the hypothesis, adopted by Poisson and all other writers on the subject, of the absolute independence of the events whose _ probabilities are denoted by x and & be retained, we should be led to form a system of five equations of the type (3), and either select from these that particular pair of equations which might appear to be most advantageous, or combine together the equations of the system by the method of least squares, There might exist a doubt as to whether the latter method would be strictly applicable in such cases, especially if the values of x and & afforded by different selected pairs of the given equations were very different from each other. M. Cournot has considered a somewhat similar problem, in which, from the records of individual votes in a court con- sisting of four judges, it is proposed to investigate the separate probabilities of a correct verdict from each judge. For the determination of the elements 7, 2’, x”, τὺ he obtains eight equations, which he divides into two sets of four equations, and he remarks, that should any consider- 400 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT able discrepancy exist between the values of 4, 2’, x”, x’, determined from those sets, it might be regarded as an indication that the hypothesis of the independence of the opinions of the judges was, in the particular case, unten- able. The principle of this mode of investigation has been adverted to in (XVIII. 4). 6. I proceed to apply to the class of problems above indi- cated, the method of this treatise, and shall inquire, first, whether the records of courts and deliberative assemblies, alone, can furnish any information respecting the proba- bilities of correct judgment for their individual members, and, it appearing that they cannot, secondly, what kind and amount of necessary hypothesis will best comport with the actual data. PROPOSITION | From the mere records of the dectsions of a court or delibera- tive assembly, it ts not possible to deduce any definite conclu- ston respecting the correctness of the individual judgments of ets members. Though this Proposition may appear to express but the conviction of unassisted good sense, it will not be without interest to show that it admits of rigorous demonstration. [383] Let us suppose the case of a deliberative assembly consisting of 2. members, no hypothesis whatever being made respecting the dependence or independence of their judgments. Let the logical symbols αὶ, #, .. +, be em- ployed according to the following definition, viz.: Let the generic symbol #, denote that event which consists in the uttering of a correct opinion by the z” member, A,, of the court. We shall consider the values of Prob. ΖΦ, Prob. ae τοῦ: τ as the gucstfa of a proplem. the. ex- pression of whose possible data we must in the next place investigate, Now those data are the probabilities of events capable of being expressed by definite logical functions of the symbols ee δ μὰ Pe Eee ΩΝ ee ee ee ee ““ PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 401 Εν, %,,.-.%,. Let X,, X,,.. X,, represent the functions in question, and let the actual system of data be Prob. X;=a,, Prob. X,=a,, Prob. X,,=am.- Then from the very nature of the case it may be shown that X,, X,.. X, are functions which remain unchanged if @,, %,,-. #, are therein changed into I—z,, I—4,,.. 1—2, respectively. Thus, if it were recorded that in a certain proportion of instances the votes given were unanimous, the event whose probability, supposing the instances suf- ficiently numerous, is thence determined, is expressed by the logical function χὰ oO Oe op) Crater) Eas mad @ ear 20) a function which satisfies the above condition. Again, let it be recorded, that in a certain proportion of instances, the vote of an individual, suppose A,, differs from that of all the other members of the court. The event, whose proba- bility is thus given, will be expressed by the function BRE ey) eM eel Ly ae Os also satisfying the above conditions. Thus, as agreement Γ᾽ in opinion may be an agreement in either truth or error ; eG and as, when opinions are divided, either party may be right or wrong; it is manifest that the expression of any particular state, whether of agreement or difference of senti- ment in the assembly, will depend upon a logical function of the symbols x,, %, . . %,, [384] which similarly involves the privative symbols 1—+,, 1-43, .. 1—%,. But in the records of assemblies, it is not presumed to declare which set of opinions is right or wrong. Hence the functions X,, X,, .. X,, must be solely of the kind above described. 7. Now in proceeding, according to the general method, to determine the value of Prob. x,, we should first equate the functions X,, .. X,, to a new set of symbols 4, . . Z,,. From the equations X,=4; Xo = boy etd Xm = bn thus formed, we should eliminate the symbols %, 43, . .ὄ ¥,, 26 402 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT and then determine +, as a developed logical function of the symbols ¢,, ¢,, . . Z,, expressive of events whose probabilities are given. Let the result of the above elimination be Ex,+ £1 -x,)=0; Gy anda ΑΕ being functions of-2,, 2; .. 722. then E' | if eee ν 2 if Fee 3 ( ) Now the functions Y,, X,,.. X, are symmetrical with reference to the symbols 4, .. 4, and 1—4,,..1-%,. It is evident, therefore, that in the equation 4’ must be identical Wit &. Hence.(2) gives and it is evident, that the only coefficients which can appear in the development of the second member of the above : fe) I equation are 5 and = The former will present itself when- ever the valiles assioned to 4), .. 2.,.in. détermining the coefficient of a constituent, are such as to make E=o0, the latter, or an equivalent result, in every other case. Hence we may represent the development under the form τς}, (3) Cand D being constituents, or aggregates of constituents, OC the Πρ 2 | [385] Passing then from Logic to Algebra, we have Ῥτοῦ: x, = m6 the function V of the general Rule (XVII. 17) reducing in the present case to C. The value of Prob. ἢ is therefore wholly arbitrary, if we except the condition that it must not transcend the limitso andi. The individual values of Prob. %,,.. Prob. x,, are in like manner arbitrary. It does not hence follow, that these arbitrary values are not connected with each other by necessary conditions dependent upon PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 403 the data. The investigation of such conditions would, how- ever, properly fall under the methods of Chapter XIX. If, reverting to the final logical equation, we seek the in- terpretation of c, we obtain but a restatement of the original problem. For since Cand D together include all possible constituents of 7,, 4,,. . Z,,, we have Cpt; : : . ες : and since D is affected by the coefficient a: it is evident that On substituting therein for ¢,, 7,,... ¢,, their expressions in eric Ol 2. 4,2. 4, we should have D—o; Hencethe same substitution would give C=1. Now by the rule, c is the probability that if the event denoted by C take place, the event τὸ will take place... Hence.C being equal to. 1, and, therefore, embracing all possible contingencies, c must be interpreted as the absolute probability of the occurrence of the event σι. It may be interesting to determine in a particular case the actual form of the final logical equation. Suppose, then, that the elements from which the data are derived are the records of events distinct and mutually exclusive. For in- stance, let the numerical data @,, a,,..4@,, be the respec- tive probabilities of distinct and definite majorities. Then the logical functions X,, X,,.. X,, being mutually ex- clusive, must satisfy the conditions Ae Mo = Oyu An Oh, Ne Os OLE. Whence we have, tly=0, tytn=0o, &c. [386] Under these circumstances it may easily be shown, that the developed logical value of x, will be wy = (Az pa een eee) : Ι + constituents whose coefficients are = In the above equation ἢ, stands for 1—¢,, &c. These investigations are equally applicable to the case in 404 THE LAWS OF THOUGAT which the probabilities of the verdicts of a jury, so far as agreement and disagreement of opinion are concerned, form the data of a problem. Let the logical symbol w denote that event or state of things which consists in the guilt of the accused person. Then the functions X,, X,,.. X,, of the present problem are such, that no change would therein ensue from simultaneously converting w, 4,, 4%, ..%, into W, t,, 4, . . #, respectively. Hence the final logical value of w, as well as those of +,, 2%, . . %, will be exhibited under the same form (3), and a like general conclusion thence deduced. It is therefore established, that from mere statistical documents nothing can be inferred respecting either the in- dividual correctness of opinion of a judge or counsellor, the guilt of an individual, or the merits of a disputed question. If the determination of such elements as the above can be reduced within the province of science at all, it must be by virtue either of some assumed criterion of truth furnishing us with new data, or of some hypothesis relative to the connexion or the independence of individual judgments, which may warrant a new form of the investigation. In the examination of the results of different hypotheses, the following general Proposition will be of importance. PROPOSITION II 8. Given the probabilities of the n simple events x1, . . Δ,» 2,» 725. -— ΓΕΘ XG bLODs 4, τ POD 7s (1) also the probabilities of the m—1 compound events X,, Xo, - Ay, UES. τ. Prob αὐ Rob, ν᾽ --ἰἰ περ paar; (2) [387] the latter events X,, .. X,,, being distinct and mutually exclusive ; required the probability of any other com- pound event X. In this Proposition it is supposed, that X,, X,, . . X. m—1) as well as X, are functions of the symbols 21, 4%, . - %, alone. PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 405 Moreover, the events X,, τ΄ Α΄ being mutually ex- clusive, we have AX X_=0, . . XXy1=0, X,X,=0, &c.; (3) the product of any two members of the system vanishing. Now assume X,=h, Xn—1=t -y X=, (4) Then ¢ must be determined as a logical function of x,, . . ,, Pee ee Now by (3), bi,=0, Lbn1=0, ff,=0, &c.; (5) 811 binary products οἵ ¢,, . . Ζ,.., vanishing. The developed expression for ¢ can, therefore, only involve in the list of constituents which have 1, 0, or - for their coefficients, such as contain some one of the following factors, viz. :— ra Ou ms ee, ae 55 ΖΞ oo A yous PS Ε1 (6) ἢ, standing for 1—Z,, &c. It remains to assign that portion of each constituent which involves the symbols 7, .. %,; to- gether with the corresponding coefficients. Since X,=7, (2 being any integer between 1 and m-—1I in- clusive), it is evident that Xf, or Zn—1 = 9, from the very constitution of the functions. Any constituent included in the first member of the above equation would, I : therefore, have a for its coefficient. Now let Xm=i-X, Ἔτι τ om—1 > (7) and it is evident that such constituents as involve ὦ... Z,_,, O as a factor, and yet have coefficients of the form 1, 0, or = must be [388] included in the expression ΧΟ er. Now X,, may be resolved into two portions, viz., XX, and 406 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT (1—X)YX,,, the former being the sum of those constituents of X,, which are found in XY, the latter of those which are not found in X. ΤῈ is evident that in the developed expres- sion of ¢, which is equivalent to Y, the coefficients of the constituents in the former portion XY, will be 1, while those of the latter portion (1 —Y)X,, will beo. Hence the elements we have now considered will contribute to the development of 2 the terms DOG te τον Xe Fe Again, since X,=2,, while X,¢,=2,t,=0, &c., it is evi- dent that the only constituents involving. το ¢.., asa : : O : factor which have coefficients of the form tO, OF a will be included in the expression GUNES Meta i mg and reasoning as before, we see that this will contribute to the development of ¢ the terms 2G. GF AE ee lm ΕΟ ΕΘ Δ ΧΙ; Chey 2 m—1°* Proceeding thus with the remaining terms of (6), we de- duce for the final expression of Ζ, ee οὐχ τ te pe τοι AGN Fy ο( me) Ale te re. (8) + terms whose coefficients are ὦ. O° In this expression it is to be noted that ΧΑ, denotes the sum of those constituents which are common to Y and De Ἰἴῶολ that sum being actually given by multiplying Y and X,, to- gether, according to the rules of the calculus of Logic. In passing from Logic to Algebra, we shall represent by (X-X,,,) what the above product becomes, when, after effecting the multiplication, or selecting the common constituents, we give to the symbols 4, .. #,, a quantitative meaning. [389] With this understanding we shall have, by the general Rule (XVII. 17), ΡΣ ἘΠ ΤΝ PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 407 Prob. ¢ COC το 10 6 on ae ee a » (9) ee et NGL ey eer ee ee tig) mnence-the relations determining τὶ 24/2)... 4.0 will be of the following type (ὦ varying from 1 to 2), (x: Xn)A, 0 fee ea Fe, Gp a os bet 5.288 + (4; Xm—1)2, ἐς ote aa C; _ hh rae pe es Χο νὴ iris ἐπ τεῦ Ἐν V. (41) a, Am -1 From the above system we shall next eliminate the sym- DOs hk... foe. We have δ: ay, V z a An-1 V hea . . gs Age OG 3 Ly oe SS 3 “1. = ΣῈ ; e (12) m— Substituting these values in (10), we find ΖΞ ΧΕ oe En—1+a,V ir) + An V. Pience i Fe pi Sol ΕΞ ἤν Now let a= 1-4, < —ay1, (13) then we have at ina (14) Now reducing, by means of (12) and (14), the equation (9), and the equation formed by equating the first line of (11) to the symbol VY; writing also Prob, X for Prob. 2, we have a (XX) | a(XX9) | : μα XXm) | Ι Prob. X = τ X, (15) a,(x;X)) a(x; Xp) : 4 lH Xm) _ o (16) pay ππτ Xn wherein X,, and a,, are given by (7) and (13). [390] These equations involve the direct solution of the problem under consideration. In (16) we have the type of m equations (formed by giving to Zine yalles 1, 2... 9.0% successively), from which the Wallies Olt, 4a, εν 408 THE ΕΝ OF Tf HOCGH YE. be found, and those values substituted in (15) give the value of Prob. X as a function of the constants ὧς, εἰ, &c. One conclusion deserving of notice, which is deducible from the above solution, is, that if the probabilities of the com- pound events X,, . . X,,_,, are the same as they would be were the events 7,, . . τὸ entirely independent, and with given probabilities c,, . . c,, then the probability of the event X will be the same as if calculated upon the same hypothesis of the absolute independence of the events ἜΝ . ¥,, For upon the hypothesis supposed, the assumption 4,=¢, %,=C¢,, inthe quantitative system would give AE Ξεαι, X,=4,, Whence (15) and (16) would give Brob: = (Υχλ 4 (0X) x.) (17) (x;,X,)+(4Xq) ... + (0: Xp) = eG. (18) But since. Y,+X,.. +_X,,=1,it isevident that thesecond member of (17) will be formed by taking all the constituents that are contained in Α΄, and giving them an algebraic signi- ficance. And a similar remark applies to (18). Whence those equations respectively give Prob. X (logical) =X (algebraic), Xx, = ¢;- Wherefore, if Y=¢(%,, %, . . x,), we have ΕΟ οὐ ee), which is the result in question. Hence too it would follow, that if the Quantities 9.0 were indeterminate, and no hypothesis were made as to the possession of a mean common value, the system (15) (16) would be satisfied by giving to those quantities any such values, 41, %, . . #,, as would satisfy the equations X, =a, er ae PG as SR Aa, supposing the value of the element a, like the values of a, . . @,_,, to be given by experience. [391] 9. Before applying the general solution (15). (16);.t0 the question of the probability of judgments, it will be con- a eat ἕξ PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 409 venient to make the following transformation. Let the data be Ny =O... By =ey, Γοῦ with these transformations, and observing that (τ, OX) =0: εἰ except ‘when r=m— I, and that it is then equal to _Y may tHe equations (15) (16) give ine 1+ Gn) Xin ik am — 1s Dear Exe ? (19) af a,(x;,X}) ee Ans (ὦ: a 2) 4 (Gm lay τ Am); ae tal a x Xm) (20) Oe Χο τος ἀν a De "ΟΣ Now from (19) we find Ae 1 eo EEX. Sta ’ am 1 Qn an 1 τς LP by virtue of which the last term of (20) may be reduced to the form Ay XAG 4) 4 GA.) : Χο v.68 With these reductions the system (17) and (18) may be re- placed by the following symmetrical one, viz. : Gar ae Xin Am-1 an : oe ας (Gala XG) Am Xi Xm) _ τ a as gee Cie (22) These equations, in connexion with (7) and (13), enable us ΠΕ 102] dcterimine 2) as a function οἱ ἐν δ αἰ δ. the numerical data supposed to be furnished by experience. We now proceed to their application. 410 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT PROPOSITION III 10. Given any system of probabilities drawn from recorded instances of unanimity, or of assigned numerical majority in the decisions of a deliberate assembly ; required, upon a certain determinate hypothesis, the mean probability of correct judg- ment for a member of the assembly. In what way the probabilities of unanimous decision and of specific numerical majorities may be determined from ex- perience, has been intimated in a former part of this chapter. Adopting the notation of Prop. I. we shall represent the events whose probabilities are given by the functions. X,, X,, . . Χο It has appeared from the very nature of the case that these events are mutually exclusive, and that the functions by which they are represented are symmetrical with reference to the symbols 4,, #, . . %,. Those symbols we continue to use in the same sense as in Prop. I., viz., by 2, we understand that event which consists in the formation of a correct opinion by the z’ member of the assembly. Now the immediate data of experience are— Prob. X,=a,, Prob. X,=a,, .. Prob. Xn_3=@n_a; (1) ΡΟ i s 4. (2) Ay. ot, , being functions of the locical symbols 4,, . τ to the probabilities of the events denoted by which we shall assign the intermediate value c. Thus we shall have Prob. x, = Prob. x, . . =Prob. x,=<¢. (3) Now it has been seen, Prop. I., that the immediate data (1) (2), unassisted by any hypothesis, merely conduct us to a restatement of the problem. On the other hand, it is manifest that if, adopting the methods of Laplace and Poisson, we employ the system (3) alone as the data for the application of the method of this work, finally comparing the results obtained with the experimental system (1) (2), we are relying wholly upon a doubtful hypothesis,—the inde- pendence of individual judgments. But [393] though we PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 411 ought not wholly to rely upon this hypothesis, we cannot wholly dispense with it, or with some equivalent substitute. Let us then examine the consequences of a 4mzted indepen- dence of the individual judgments ; the conditions of limita- tion being furnished by the apparently superfluous data. From the system (1) (3) let us, by the method of this work, determine Prob. X,,_,, and, comparing the result with (2), determine c. Even here an arbitrary power of selection is claimed. But it is manifest from Prop. I. that something of this kind is unavoidable, if we would obtain a definite solution at all. As tothe principle of selection, I apprehend that the equation (2) reserved for final comparison should be that which, from the magnitude of its numerical element @,-1, is esteemed the most important of the primary series furnished by experience. Now, from the mutually exclusive character of the events denoted by the functions X,, X,,.. X,_1, the concluding equations of the previous proposition become applicable. On account of the symmetry of the same functions, and the re- duction of the system of values denoted by ¢; to a single value c, the equations represented by (22) become identical, the values of +,, 25» . - 2, become equal, and may be replaced by a single value x, and we have simply, care ῳ πα, ee ie + Slee) we, (5) The following is the nature of the solution thus indicated : The functions X,, .. X,,-1, and the values a, .. @,_, being given in the data, we have first, Ne LX) ag ee Ga. κα From each of the functions X,, X,,.-. X,, thus given or determined, we must select those constituents which contain a particular symbol, as +4, for a factor. This will determine the functions (#X,), (¢X,), &c., and then in all the functions 412 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT we must change 7,, 22», - - 2, individually tox. Or we may regard any [394] algebraic function X,in the system (4) (5) as expressing the probability of the event denoted by the logical function .Y,, on the supposition that the logical symbols #,, %,, . . #, denote independent events whose common probability is % On the same supposition (#X;,) would denote the probability of the concurrence of any Marticuiar event of the series 2,, 4,,° . 2% with 4; πὸ forms of X,, («X,), &c. being determined, the equation (4) gives the value of x, and this, substituted in (5), determines the value of the element c required. Of the two values which its solution will offer, one being greater, and the other less, than 4, the greater one must be chosen, when- soever, upon general considerations, it is thought more probable that a member of the assembly will judge correctly, than that he will judge incorrectly. Here then, upon the assumed principle that the largest of the values a,,_, shall be reserved for final comparison in the equation (2), we possess a definite solution of the problem proposed, And the same form of solution remains applicable should any other equation of the system, upon any other ground, as that of superior accuracy, be similarly reserved in the place of:(2), 11. Let us examine to what extent the above reserva- tion has influenced the final solution. It is evident that the equation (5) is quite independent of the choice in question. So is likewise the second member of (4). Had we reserved the function .Y,, instead of X the equation for the de- m—-1) termination of « would have been Ay δες Die Gu (6) but the value of # thence determined would still have to be substituted in the same final equation (5). We know that were the events %,, 4%, . Ὁ. really independent, the equa- tions (4) (6), and all others of which they are types, would prove equivalent, and that the value of x furnished by any ee ee ee Ὁ i ie CASES PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 413 one of them would be the true value of c. This affords a means of verifying (5). For if that equation be correct, it ought, under the above circumstances, to be satisfied by the assumption c=. In other words, the equation ΠΗ ΦΧ a(xX,) ἀκ τ a ae Ps an ὁ fe es ams ἘΞ (7) [395] ought, on solution, to give the same value of x as the equation (4) or (6). Now this will be the case. For since, by hypothesis, ἜΣ Xe a, a, a ? we have, by a known theorem, X,_X; eg te ee : : τ ay Ay rs i Ages) te On Hence (7) becomes on substituting a, for X,, &c. (xX) +(#X,) .. τ =x a mere identity. Whenever, therefore, the events +,, +, . . %, are really independent, the system (4) (5) is a correct one, and is in- dependent of the arbitrariness of the first step of the process by which it was obtained. When the said events are not in- dependent, the final system of equations will possess, leaving in abeyance the principle of selection above stated, an arbi- trary element. But from the persistent form of the equation (5) it may be inferred that the solution is arbitrary in a less degree than the solutions to which the hypothesis of the absolute independence of the individual judgments would con- duct us. The discussion of the limits of the value of c, as dependent upon the limits of the value of 4, would determine such points. These considerations suggest to us the question whether the equation (7), which is symmetrical with reference to the functions Y,, Y,, . . X,,, free from any arbitrary elements, and rigorously exact when the events +,,%,, . . ¥,are really independent, might not be accepted as a mean general solu- 414 THE LAWS: OF THOUGHT tion of the problem. The proper mode of determining this point would, I conceive, be to ascertain whether the value of « which it would afford would, in general, fall within the limits of the value of c, as determined by the systems of equations of which the system (4) (5) presents the type. It seems probable that under ordinary circumstances this would be the case. Independently of such considerations, however, we may regard (7) as itself the expression of a certain principle of solution, viz., that regarding X,, X,, . X,, as exclusive causes of the event whose probability is x, we accept the [396] probabilities of those causes a, . . a,, from experience, but form the conditional probabilities of the event as dependent upon such causes, ee, or &ec. (XVII. Prop. I.) on the hypothesis of the independence of individual judg- ments, and so deduce the equation (7). I conceive this, however, to be a less rigorous, though possibly, in practice a more convenient mode of procedure than that adopted in the general solution. 12. It now only remains to assign the particular forms which the algebraic functions X,, (~X,), &c. in the above equations assume when the logical function Α΄; represents that event which consists in 7, members of the assembly voting one way, and z—yv members the other way. It is evident that in this case the algebraic function Y, expresses what the probability of the supposed event would be were the events 41, %,, . . x, independent, and their common probability measured by x. Hence we should have, by Art. 3, Ἐπ OE rns Under the same circumstances (1 Δ ὃ would represent the pro- bability of the compound event, which consists ina particular member of the assembly forming a correct judgment, con- jointly with the general state of voting recorded above. It would, therefore, be the probability that a particular member PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 415 votes correctly, while of the remaining 2—1 members, r—1 ᾿ vote correctly ; or that the same member votes correctly, while of the remaining »—1 members 7, vote incorrectly. Hence ἐλ). Ξ τ)(γι -- 2)... τω ὡν ΤΕ λα Dee) (7-7) enor PROPOSITION IV 13. Grven any system of probabilities drawn from recorded instances of unanimity, or of assigned numerical majority in the decisions of a criminal court of justice, required upon hypotheses stmtlar to those of the last proposition, the mean probability c of [397] correct judgment for a member of the court, and the general probability k of guilt in an accused person. The solution of this problem differs in but a slight degree from that of the last, and may be referred to the same general formule, (4) and (5), or (7). It is to be observed, that as there are two elements, c and ᾧ, to be determined, tL is Necessary. to reserve two ol the functions. x, τ, Πὰς let us suppose Y, and YX,,_,, for final comparison, employing either the remaining 772 — 3 functions in the expression of the ata or tiie: two “respective. Seto: A) ον τ and as πα΄ in either case it 45 supposea that there must be at least two original independent data. If the equation (7) be alone employed, it would in the present instance furnish two equations, which may thus be written : Gi we “ας 3 fe Wan) ΕΣ "ἢ + Sa eae x; (1) a(AX,) | ao(kX 9) a An(AXm) _ 2. 2 ἘΠ an ae (2) These equations are to be employed in the following manner : —Let x,, 4, .. 4%, represent those events which consist in the formation of a correct opinion by the members of the court respectively. Let also w represent that event which 416 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT consists in the guilt of the accused member. By the aid of these symbols we can logically express the functions Αἱ, X,,.. X,,,, whose probabilities are given, as also the function Y,,. Then from the function , select those con- stituents which contain, as a factor, any particular symbol of the set +,, *%,..%,, and also those constituents which contain as a factor w. In both results change 4,, 4%, .. %, severally into x, and w into k. The above results will give (7X,) and (£X,). Effecting the same transformations throughout, the system (1) (2) will, upon the particular hypothesis involved, determine + and &. 14. We may collect from the above investigations the following facts and conclusions : _ Ist. That from the mere records of agreement and dis- agreement in the opinions of any body of men, no definite numerical conclusions can be drawn respecting either the probability of cor-[398]rect judgment in an individual member of the body, or the merit of the questions submitted to its consideration. 2nd. That such conclusions may be drawn upon various distinct hypotheses, as—rst, Upon the usual hypothesis of the absolute independence of individual judgments ; 2ndly, upon certain definite modifications of that hypothesis war- ranted by the actual data; 3rdly, upon a distinct principle of solution suggested by the appearance of a common form in the solutions obtained by the modifications above ad- verted to. | Lastly. That whatever of doubt may attach to the final results, rests not upon the imperfection of the method, which adapts itself equally to all hypotheses, but upon the un- certainty of the hypotheses themselves. It seems, however, probable that with even the widest limits of hypothesis, consistent with the taking into account of afl the data of experience, the deviation of the results obtained would be but slight, and that their mean values might be determined with great confidence by the methods of Prop. III. Of those methods I should be disposed to PROBABILITY OF JUDGMENTS 417 give the preference to the first. Such a principle of mean solution having been agreed upon, other considerations seem to indicate that the values of ¢ and & for tribunals and assemblies possessing a definite constitution, and governed in their deliberations by fixed rules, would remain nearly constant, subject, however, to a small secular variation, dependent upon the progress of knowledge and of justice among mankind, There exist at present few, if any, data proper for their determination. 27 [399] CHAPTER XXII ON THE NATURE OF SCIENCE, AND THE CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 1. WHAT I mean by the constitution of a system is the aggregate of those causes and tendencies which produce its observed character, when operating, without interference, under those conditions to which the system is conceived to be adapted. Our judgment of such adaptation must be founded upon a study of the circumstances in which the system attains its freest action, produces its most harmonious results, or fulfils in some other way the apparent design of its construction. There are cases in which we know dis- tinctly the causes upon which the operation of a system depends, as well as its conditions and its end. This is the most perfect kind of knowledge relatively to the subject under consideration. There are also cases in which we know only imperfectly or partially the causes which are at work, but are able, nevertheless, to determine to some extent the laws of their action, and, beyond this, to discover general tendencies, and to infer ulterior purpose. It has thus, I think rightly, been concluded that there is a moral faculty in our nature, not because we can understand the special in- struments by which it works, as we connect the organ with the faculty of sight, nor upon the ground that men agree in the adoption of universal rules of conduct ; but because, while, in some form or other, the sentiment of moral appro- bation or disapprobation manifests itself in all, it tends, wherever human progress is observable, wherever society is not either stationary or hastening to decay, to attach itself to certain classes of actions, consentaneously, and after a manner indicative both of permanency and of law. Always 418 CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 10 and everywhere the manifestation of Order affords a pre- sumption, not measurable indeed, but real (XX. 20)" ot the fulfilment of an end or purpose, and the existence of a ground of orderly causation. [400] 2. The particular question of the constitution of the intellect has, it is almost needless to say, attracted the efforts of speculative ingenuity in every age. For it not only addresses itself to that desire of knowledge which the greatest masters of ancient thought believed to be innate in our species, but it adds to the ordinary strength of this motive the inducement of a human and personal interest. A genuine devotion to truth is, indeed, seldom partial in its aims, but while it prompts to expatiate over the fair fields of outward observation, forbids to neglect the study of our own faculties. Even in ages the most devoted to material in- terests, some portion of the current of thought has been reflected inwards, and the desire to comprehend that by which all else is comprehended has only been baffled in order to be renewed. It is probable that this pertenacity of effort would not have been maintained among sincere inquirers after truth, had the conviction been general that such speculations are hope- lessly barren. We may conceive that it has been felt that if something of error and uncertainty, always incidental to a state of partial information, must ever be attached to the results of such inquiries, a residue of positive knowledge may yet remain; that the contradictions which are met with are more often verbal than real; above all, that even probable conclusions derive here an interest and a value from their subject, which render them not unworthy to claim regard beside the more definite and more splendid results of physical science. Such considerations seem to be perfectly legitimate. Insoluble as many of the problems connected with the inquiry into the nature and constitution of the mind must be presumed to be, there are not wanting others upon which a limited but not doubtful knowledge, others upon which the conclusions of a highly probable analogy, 420 THE LAWS. OF THOUGH! are attainable. As the realms of day and night are not strictly conterminous, but are separated by a crepuscular zone, through which the light of the one fades gradually off into the darkness of the other, so it may be said that every region of positive knowledge lies surrounded by a debateable and speculative territory, over which it in some degree extends its influence and its light. Thus there may be questions relating to the constitution of the intellect which, though they do not admit, in the present state of know-[40I]ledge, of an absolute decision, may receive so much of reflected information as to render their probable solution not difficult ; and there may also be questions re- lating to the nature of science, and even to particular truths and doctrines of science, upon which they who accept the general principles of this work cannot but be led to entertain positive opinions, differing, it may be, from those which are usually received in the present day.* In what follows I shall recapitulate some of the more definite conclusions established in the former parts of this treatise, and shall then indicate one or two trains of thought, connected with the general objects above adverted to, which they seem to me calculated to suggest. 3. Among those conclusions, relating to the intellectual constitution, which may be considered as belonging to the realm of positive knowledge, we may reckon the scientific laws of thought and reasoning, which have formed the basis of the general methods of this treatise, together with the principles, Chap. V., by which their application has been determined. The resolution of the domain of thought into two spheres, distinct but coexistent (IV. XI.); the sub- jection of the intellectual operations within those spheres * The following illustration may suffice :— It is maintained by some of the highest modern authorities in grammar that conjunctions connect propositions only. Now, without inquiring directly whether this opinion is sound or not, it is obvious that it cannot consistently be held by any who admit the scientific principles of this treatise ; for to such it would seem to involve a denial, either, Ist, of the possibility of performing, or 2ndly, of the possibility of express¢ng, a mental operation, the laws of which, viewed in both these relations, have been investigated and applied in the present work.— (Latham on the English Language ; Sir John Stoddart’s Unzversal Grammar, &c.) CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 421 to a common system of laws (XI.); the general mathe- matical character of those laws, and their actual expression (iI. I1I.); the extent of their affinity with the laws of thought in the domain of number, and the point of their divergence therefrom ; the dominant character of the two limiting conceptions of universe and eternity among all the subjects of thought with which Logic is concerned ; the relation of those conceptions to the fundamental conception of unity in the science of number,—these, with many similar results, are not to be ranked as merely [402] pro- bable or analogical conclusions, but are entitled to be re- garded as truths of science. Whether they be termed meta- physical or not, is a matter of indifference. The nature of the evidence upon which they rest, though in kind distinct, is not inferior in value to any which can be adduced in support of the general truths of physical science. Again, it is agreed that there is a certain order observable in the progress of all the exacter forms of knowledge. The study of every department of physical science begins with observation, it advances by the collation of facts to a pre- sumptive acquaintance with their connecting law, the validity of such presumption it tests by new experiments so devised as to augment, if the presumption be well founded, its probability indefinitely ; and finally, the law of the pheno- menon having been with sufficient confidence determined, the investigation of causes, conducted by the due mixture of hypothesis and deduction, crowns the inquiry. In this advancing order of knowledge, the particular faculties and laws whose nature has been considered in this work bear their part. It is evident, therefore, that if we would im- partially investigate either the nature of science, or the in- tellectual constitution in its relation to science, no part of the two series above presented ought to be regarded as isolated. More especially ought those truths which stand in any kind of supplemental relation to each other to be con- sidered in their mutual bearing and connexion. 4. Thus the necessity of an experimental basis for all 422 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT positive knowledge, viewed in connexion with.the existence and the peculiar character of that system of mental laws, and principles, and operations, to which attention has been directed, tends to throw light upon some important questions by which the world of speculative thought is still in a great measure divided. How, from the particular facts which experience presents, do we arrive at the general propositions of science? What is the nature of these propositions? Are they solely the collections of experience, or does the mind supply some connecting principle of its own? In a word, what is the nature of scientific truth, and what are the grounds of that confidence with which it claims to be received ? [403] That to such questions as the above, no single and general answer can be given, must be evident. There are cases in which they do not even need discussion. Instances are familiar, in which general propositions merely express per enumerationem simplicem, a fact established by actual observation in all the cases to which the proposition applies. The astronomer asserts upon this ground, that all the known planets move from west to east round the sun. But there are also cases in which general propositions are assumed from observation of their truth in particular instances, and extension of that truth to instances unobserved. No prin- ciple of merely deductive reasoning can warrant such a pro- cedure. When from a large number of observations on the planet Mars, Kepler inferred that it revolved in an ellipse, the conclusion was larger than his premises, or indeed than _any premises which mere observation could give. What other element, then, is necessary to give even a prospective validity to such generalizations as this? It is the ability inherent in our nature to appreciate Order, and the con- current presumption, however founded, that the phenomena of Nature are connected by a principle of Order. Without these, the general truths of physical science could never have been ascertained. Grant that the procedure thus established can only conduct us to probable or to approximate results; Se ee ee! eae a oe CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT _ 423 it only follows, that the larger number of the generalizations of physical science possess but a probable or approximate truth. The security of the tenure of knowledge consists in this, that wheresoever such conclusions do truly represent the constitution of Nature, our confidence in their truth receives indefinite confirmation, and soon becomes undis- tinguishable from certainty. The existence of that principle above represented as the basis of inductive reasoning enables us to solve the much disputed question as to the necessity of general propositions in reasoning. The logician affirms, that it is impossible to deduce any conclusion from particular premises. Modern writers of high repute have contended, that all reasoning is from particular to particular truths. They instance, that in concluding from the possession of a property by certain members of a class, its possession by some other member, it is not necessary to establish the intermediate general conclu-[404]sion which affirms its possession by aé/ the members of the class incommon. Now whether it is so or not, that principle of order or analogy upon which the reasoning is conducted must either be stated or apprehended as a general truth, to give validity to the final conclusion. In this form, at least, the necessity of general propositions as the basis of inference is confirmed, —a necessity which, however, I conceive to be involved in the very existence, and still more in the peculiar nature, of those faculties whose laws have been investigated in this work, For if the process of reasoning be carefully analyzed, it will appear that abstraction is made of all peculiarities of the individual to which the conclusion refers, and the atten- tion confined to those properties by which its membership of the class is defined. 5. But besides the general propositions which are derived by induction from the collated facts of experience, there exist others belonging to the domain of what is termed necessary truth. Such are the general propositions of Arith- metic, as well as the propositions expressing the laws of thought upon which the general methods of this treatise are 424 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT founded; and these propositions are not only capable of being rigorously verified in particular instances, but are made manifest in all their generality from the study of particular instances. Again, there exist general propositions expressive of necessary truths, but incapable, from the imperfection of the senses, of being exactly verified. Some, if not all, of the propositions of Geometry are of this nature ; but it is not in the region of Geometry alone that such propositions are found. The question concerning their nature and origin is a very ancient one, and as it is more intimately connected with the inquiry into the constitution of the intellect than any other to which allusion has been made, it will not be irrelevant to consider it here. Among the opinions which have most widely prevailed upon the subject are the follow- ing. It has been maintained, that propositions of the class referred to exist in the mind independently of experience, and that those conceptions which are the subjects of them are the imprints of eternal archetypes. With such arche- types, conceived, however, to possess a reality of which all the objects of sense are but a faint shadow or dim suggestion, Plato furnished his ideal world. It [405] has, on the other hand, been variously contended, that the subjects of such propositions are copies of individual objects of experience ; that they are mere names; that they are individual objects of experience themselves ; and that the propositions which relate to them are, on account of the imperfection of those objects, but partially true ; lastly, that they are intellectual products formed by abstraction from the sensible perceptions - of individual things, but so formed as to become, what the individual things never can be, subjects of science, ze. sub- jects concerning which exact and general propositions may be affirmed. And there exist, perhaps, yet other views, in some of which the sensible, in others the intellectual or ideal, element predominates. Now if the last of the views above adverted to be taken (for it is not proposed to consider either the purely ideal or the purely nominalist view) and if it be inquired what, in Pe eS eT τ - CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 425 the sense above stated, are the proper objects of science, objects in relation to which its propositions are true without any mixture of error, it is conceived that but one answer can be given. It is, that neither do individual objects of experience, nor with all probability do the mental images which they suggest, possess any strict claim to this title. It seems to be certain, that neither in nature nor in art do we meet with anything absolutely agreeing with the geo- metrical definition of a straight line, or of a triangle, or of a circle, though the deviation therefrom may be inappreciable by sense; and it may be conceived as at least doubtful, whether we can form a perfect mental image, or conception, with which the agreement shall be more exact. But it is not doubtful that such conceptions, however imperfect, do point to something beyond themselves, in the gradual ap- proach towards which all imperfection tends to disappear. Although the perfect triangle, or square, or circle, exists not in nature, eludes all our powers of representative con- ception, and is presented to us in thought only, as the limit of an indefinite process of abstraction, yet, by a wonderful faculty of the understanding, it may be made the subject of propositions which are absolutely true. The domain of reason is thus revealed to us as larger than that of imagination. Should any, indeed, think that we are able to picture to ourselves, with rigid accuracy, the scientific elements of form, direction, mag-[406]nitude, &c., these things, as actually conceived, will, in the view of such persons, be the proper objects of science. But if, as seems to me the more just opinion, an incurable imperfection attaches to all our attempts to realize with precision these elements, then we can only affirm, that the more external objects do approach in reality, or the conceptions of fancy by abstraction, to certain /zmzt- ing states, never, it may be, actually attained, the more do the general propositions of science concerning those things or conceptions approach to absolute truth, the actual devia- tion therefrom tending to disappear. To some extent, the same observations are applicable also to the physical sciences. = 426 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT What have been termed the ‘‘ fundamental ideas” of those sciences as force, polarity, crystallization, &c.,* are neither, as I conceive, intellectual products independent of experience, nor mere copies of external things; but while, on the one hand, they have a necessary antecedent in experience, on the other hand they require for their formation the exercise of the power of abstraction, in obedience to some general faculty or disposition of our nature, which ever prompts us to the research, and qualifies us for the appreciation, of order.t Thus we study approximately the effects of gravi- tation on the motions of the heavenly bodies, by a refer- ence to the Aimzting supposition, that the planets are perfect [407]spheres or spheroids. We determine approximately the path of a ray of light through the atmosphere, by a process in which abstraction is made of all disturbing influences of temperature. And such is the order of procedure in all the higher walks of human knowledge. Now what is remark- able in connexion with these processes of the intellect is the disposition, and the corresponding ability, to ascend from the imperfect representations of sense and the diversities of individual experience, to the perception of general, and it may be of immutable truths. Wherever this disposition and this ability unite, each series of connected facts in nature may furnish the intimations of an order more exact than that which it directly manifests. For it may serve as ground and occasion for the exercise of those powers, whose office * Whewell’s Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, pp. 71, 775 213. + Of the idea of order it has been profoundly said, that it carries within itself its own justification or its own control, the very trustworthiness of our faculties being / judged by the conformity of their results to an order which satisfies the reason. ““Lridée de Vordre a cela de singulier et d’eminent, qu’elle porte en elle méme sa justification ou son contréle. Pour trouver si nos autres facultés nous trompent ou nous ne trompent pas, nous examinons si les notions qu’elles nous donnent s’enchainent on ne s’enchainent pas suivant un ordre qui satisfasse la raison,” — Cournot, Zssaz sur les fondements de nos Connaissances, Admitting this principle as the guide of those powers of abstraction which we undoubtedly possess, it seems unphilosophical to assume that the fundamental ideas of the sciences are not deriv- able from experience. Doubtless the capacities which have been given to us for the comprehension of the actual world would avail us in a differently con- stituted scene, if in some form or other the dominion of order was still maintained. It is conceivable that in such a new theatre of speculation, the laws of the in- tellectual procedure remaining the same, the fundamental ideas of the sciences might be wholly different from those with which we are at present acquainted. ah ita ae ier EE OR ee ee ee Ee ee, ae CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 427 = it is to apprehend the general truths which are indeed ex- emplified, but never with perfect fidelity, in a world of changeful phanomena. 6. The truth that the ultimate laws of thought are mathe- matical in their form, viewed in connexion with the fact of the possibility of error, establishes a ground for some re- markable conclusions. If we directed our attention to the scientific truth alone, we might be led to infer an almost exact parallelism between the intellectual operations and the movements of external nature. Suppose any one conversant with physical science, but unaccustomed to reflect upon the nature of his own faculties, to have been informed, that it had been proved, that the laws of those faculties were mathe- matical; it is probable that after the first feelings of in- credulity had subsided, the impression would arise, that the order of thought must, therefore, be as necessary as that of the material universe. We know that in the realm of natural science, the absolute connexion between the initial and final elements of a problem, exhibited in the mathe- matical form, fitly symbolizes that physical necessity which binds together effect and cause. The necessary sequence of states and conditions in the inorganic world, and the necessary connexion of premises and conclusion in the pro- cesses of exact demonstration thereto applied, seem to be co-ordinate. It may possibly be a question, to which of the two series the primary application of the term ‘‘necessary ” is due ; whether to the observed constancy of [408] Nature, or to the indissoluble connexion of propositions in all valid reasoning upon her works. Historically we should perhaps give the preference to the former, philosophically to the latter view. But the fact of the connexion is indisputable, and the analogy to which it points is obvious. Were, then, the laws of valid reasoning uniformly obeyed, a very close parallelism would exist between the operations of the intellect and those of external Nature. Subjection to laws mathematical in their form and expression, even the subjection of an absolute obedience, would stamp upon the 428 ΤΗΣ LAWS: OF THOUGHT two series one common character. The reign of necessity over the intellectual and the physical world would be alike complete and universal. But while the observation of external Nature testifies with ever-strengthening evidence to the fact, that uniformity of operation and unvarying obedience to appointed laws pre- vail throughout her entire domain, the slightest attention to the processes of the intellectual world reveals to us another state of things. The mathematical laws of reasoning are, properly speaking, the laws of rvzght reasoning only, and their actual transgression is a perpetually recurring pheeno- menon. Error, which has no place in the material system, occupies a large one here. We must accept this as one of those ultimate facts, the origin of which it lies beyond the province of science to determine. We must admit that there exist laws which even the rigour of their mathematical forms does not preserve from violation. We must ascribe to them an authority the essence of which does not consist in power, a supremacy which the analogy of the inviolable order of the natural world in no way assists us to comprehend. As the distinction thus pointed out is veal, it remains un- affected by any peculiarity in our views respecting other portions of the mental constitution. If we regard the in- tellect as free, and this is apparently the view most in accordance with the general spirit of these speculations, its freedom must be viewed as opposed to the dominion of necessity, not to the existence of a certain just supremacy of truth. The laws of correct inference may be violated, but they do not the less truly erzs¢ on this account. Equally do they remain unaffected in character and authority if the hypothesis of necessity in its extreme form be [409] adopted. Let it be granted that the laws of valid reasoning, such as they are determined to be in this work, or, to speak more generally, such as they would finally appear in the con- clusions of an exhaustive analysis, form but a part of the system of laws by which the actual processes of reasoning, whether right or wrong, are governed. Let it be granted Page ΠΤ ee ee ae Se ee ee a ee CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLEC? 429 that if that system were known to us in its completeness, we should perceive that the whole intellectual procedure was necessary, even as the movements of the inorganic world are necessary. And let it finally, as a consequence of this hypothesis, be granted that the phenomena of incorrect reasoning or error, wheresoever presented, are due to the interference of other laws with those laws of which right reasoning is the product. Still it would remain that there exist among the intellectual laws a number marked out from the rest by this special character, viz., that every movement of the intellectual system which is accomplished solely under their direction is v¢ght, that every interference therewith by other laws is not interference only, but vzolation. It cannot but be felt that this circumstance would give to the laws in question a character of distinction and of predominance. They would but the more evidently seem to indicate a final purpose which is not always fulfilled, to possess an authority inherent and just, but not always commanding obedience. Now a little consideration will show that there is nothing analogous to this in the government of the world by natural law. The realm of inorganic Nature admits neither of pre- ference nor of distinctions. We cannot separate any portion of her laws from the rest, and pronounce them alone worthy of obedience,—alone charged with the fulfilment of her highest purpose. On the contrary, all her laws seem to stand co-ordinate, and the larger our acquaintance with them, the more necessary does their united action seem to the harmony, and, so far as we can comprehend it, to the general design of the system. How often the most signal departures from apparent order in the inorranic world, such as the perturbations of the planetary system, the interruption of the process of crystallization by the intrusion of a foreign force, and others of a like nature, either merge into the conception of some more exalted scheme of order, or lose toa [410] more attentive and instructed gaze their abnormal aspect, it is needless to remark. One explanation only of these facts can be given, viz., that the distinction between ¢vve and 430 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT false, between correct and incorrect, exists in the processes of the intellect, but not in the region of a physical necessity. As we advance from the lower stages of organic being to the higher grade of conscious intelligence, this contrast gradually dawns upon us. Wherever the phenomena of life are mani- fested, the dominion of rigid law in some degree yields to that mysterious principle of activity. Thus, although the structure of the animal tribes is conformable to certain general types, yet are those types sometimes, perhaps, in relation to the highest standards of beauty and proportion, always, imperfectly realized. The two alternatives, between which Art in the present day fluctuates, are the exact imita- tion of individual forms, and the endeavour, by abstraction from all such, to arrive at the conception of an ideal grace and expression, never, it may be, perfectly manifested in forms of earthly mould. Again, those teleological adapta- tions by which, without the organic type being sacrificed, species become fitted to new conditions or abodes, are but slowly accomplished,—accomplished, however, not, appar- ently, by the fateful power of external circumstances, but by the calling forth of an energy from within. Life in all its forms may thus be contrasted with the passive fixity of inorganic nature. But inasmuch as the perfection of the types in which it is corporeally manifested is in some measure of an ideal character, inasmuch as we cannot precisely define the highest suggested excellency of form and of adaptation, the contrast is less marked here than that which exists between the intellectual processes and those of the purely _material world. For the definite and technical character of the mathematical laws by which both are governed, places in stronger light the fundamental difference between the kind of authority which, in their capacity of government, they respectively exercise. 7. There is yet another instance connected with the general objects of this chapter, in which the collation of truths or facts, drawn from different sources, suggests an instructive train of reflection. It consists in the comparison of the laws CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 431 of thought, in their scientific expression, with the actual forms which physical [411] speculation in early ages, and metaphysical speculation in allages, have tended to assume. There are two illustrations of this remark, to which, in particular, 1 wish to direct attention here. Ist. It has been shown (III. 13) that there is a scientific connexion between the conceptions of unity in Number, and the universe in Logic. They occupy in their respective systems the same relative place, and are subject to the same formal laws. Now to the Greek mind, in that early stage of activity,—a stage not less marked, perhaps not less necessary, in the progression of the human intellect, than the era of Bacon or of Newton,—when the creat problems of Nature began to unfold themselves, while the means of observation were as yet wanting, and its necessity not understood, the terms ‘‘ Universe” and ‘*The One” seem to have been regarded as almost identical. To assign the nature of that unity of which all existence was thought to be a manifestation, was the first aim of philosophy.* Thales sought for this fundamental unity in water. Anaximenes and Diogenes conceived it to be air. Hippasus of Metapontum, and Heraclitus the Ephesian, pronounced that it was fire. Less definite or less confident in his views, Parmenides simply declared that all existing things were One; Melissus that the Universe was infinite, unsusceptible of change or motion, One, like to itself, and that motion was not, but seemed to be.t In a spirit, which, to the reflective mind of Aristotle, appeared sober when contrasted with the rashness of previous speculation, Anaxagoras of Clazomene, following, perhaps, the steps of his fellow- citizen, Hermotimus, sought in Intelligence the cause of the world and of its order.t The pantheistic tendency which * See various passages in Aristotle’s Meéaphyszcs, Book I. Τ᾿ Ἐδόκει δὲ αὐτῷ τὸ πᾶν ἄπειρον εἶναι, καὶ ἀναλλοίωτον, καὶ ἀκίνητον, καὶ ἕν, ὅμοιον ἑαυτῷ καὶ πλῆρες. κινησίν τε μὴ εἶναι δοκεῖν δὲ elyou.—Diog. Laert. ix. cap. 4. t Νοῦν δή τις εἰπὼν ἐνεῖναι, καθάπερ ἐν τοῖς ζῴοις, καὶ ἐν τῇ φύσει, τὸν αἴτιον τοῦ κόσμον καὶ τῆς τάξεως πάσης οἷον νήφων ἐφάνη παρ᾽ εἰκῇ λέγοντας τοὺς πρότερον. Φανερῶς μὲν οὖν ᾿Αναξαγόραν ἴσμεν ἁψάμενον τούτων τῶν λόγων, αἰτίαν δ᾽ ἔχει πρότερον Ἑρμότιμος ὁ Κλαζομένιος εἰπεῖν. ---Αὐἴδί, 27ε1., I. 3. 432 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT pervaded many of these speculations is manifest in the language of Xenophanes, the founder of the Eleatic school, who, ‘‘surveying the expanse of [412] heaven, declared that the One was God.” * Perhaps there are few, if any, of the forms in which unity can be conceived, in the abstract as numerical or rational, in the concrete as a passive sub- stance, or a central and living principle, of which we do not meet with applications in these ancient doctrines. The writings of Aristotle, to which 1 have chiefly referred, abound with allusions of this nature, though of the larger number of those who once addicted themselves to such speculations, it is probable that the very names have perished. Strange, but suggestive truth, that while Nature in all but the aspect of the heavens must have appeared as little else than a scene of unexplained disorder, while the popular belief was distracted amid the multiplicity of its gods,—the conception of a primal unity, if only ina rude, material form, should have struck deepest root ; surviving in many a thoughtful breast the chills of a lifelong disappoint- ment, and an endless search ! + 2ndly. In equally intimate alliance with that law of thought which is expressed by an equation of the second degree, and which has been termed in this treatise the law of duality, stands the tendency of ancient thought to those forms of philosophical speculation which are known under the name of dualism. The theory of Empedocles,t which * Ἐενοφάνης δὲ... els τὸν ὅλον οὐρανὸν ἀποβλέψας, τὸ ἕν εἶναι φησι τὸν θεόν. --- 70. + The following lines, preserved by Sextus Empiricus, and ascribed to Timon the Sillograph, are not devoid of pathos :— ὡς Kal ἐγὼν ὄφελον πυκινοῦ νόου ἀντιβολῆσαι ἀμφοτερόβλεπτος (δολίῃ δ᾽ ὁδῷ ἐξεπατήθην, πρεσβυγενὴς ἔ ἔτ ἐὼν) καὶ ἀναμφήριστος ἁ ἁπάσης σκεπτοσύνης᾽ ὅππη γὰρ ἐμὸν νόον εἰρύσαιμι, εἰς ἕν 7 αὐτὸ τε πᾶν ἀνέλνετο. I quote them from Ritter, and venture to give the following version : Be mine, to partial views no more confin’d Or sceptic doubts, the truth illumin’d mind ! For, long deceiv’d, yet still on Truth intent, Life’s waning years in wand’rings wild are spent. Still restless thought the same high quest essays, And still the One, the All, eludes my gaze. ~ Arist. AZed, I. 4, 6. SS ee περλωδ ξὺν ge eS ee Te ee ΡΨ Ὶ 4 4 ; CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 433 explained the apparent contradictions of nature by referring them to the two opposing principles [413] of ‘strife’ and ‘friendship ” ; and the theory of Leucippus, * which resolved all existence into the elements of a plenum and a vacuum, are of this nature. The famous comparison of the universe to a lyre or a bow,t its ‘‘ recurrent harmony ” being the product of opposite states of tension, betrays the same origin. In the system of Pythagoras, which seems to have been a com- bination of dualism with other elements derived from the study of numbers, and of their relations, ten fundamental antitheses are recognised : finite and infinite, even and odd, unity and multitude, right and left, male and female, rest and motion, straight and curved, light and darkness, good and evil, the square and the oblong. In that of Alemzon the same fundamental dualism is accepted, but without the definite and numerical limitation with which it is connected in the Pythagorean system. The grand development of this idea is, however, met with in that ancient Manichzan doctrine, which not only formed the basis of the religious system of Persia, but spread widely through other regions of the East, and became memorable in the history of the Christian Church. The origin of dualism as a speculative opinion, not yet connected with the personification of the Evil Principle, but naturally succeeding those doctrines which had assumed the primal unity of Nature, is thus stated by Aristotle :—‘‘ Since there manifestly existed in Nature things opposite to the good, and not only order and beauty, but also disorder and deformity ; and since the evil things did manifestly preponderate in number over the good, and the deformed over the beautiful, some one else at length introduced strife and friendship as the respective causes of these diverse phznomena.”+ And in Greece, indeed, it * Arist. 7722. I. 4, 9. : ΤΣ + παλίντροπος ἁρμονίη ὅκως περ τόξου καὶ Adpns.—Heraclitus, quoted in Orzgenzs Philosophumena, 1X. 9. Also Plutarch, De /szde et Ostride. : + "Emel δὲ καὶ τἀναντία τοῖς ἀγαθοῖς ἐνόντα ἐφαίνετο ἐν τῇ φύσει, καὶ οὐ μόνον τάξις καὶ τὸ καλὸν ἀλλὰ καὶ ἀταξία καὶ τὸ αἰσχρόν, καὶ πλείω τὰ κακὰ τῶν ἀγαθῶν καὶ τὰ φαῦλα τῶν καλῶν, οὕτως ἄλλος τις φιλίαν εἰσήνεγκε καὶ νεῖκος ἑκάτερον ἑκατέρων αἴτιον τούτων. ---Ατἱϑδί. Metaphysica, 1. 4. ᾿ 2 434 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT seems to have been chiefly as a philosophical opinion, or as an adjunct to philosophical speculation, that the dualistic theory obtained ground.* The moral application of the doctrine most in [414] accordance with the Greek mind is preserved in the great Platonic antithesis of ‘‘ being and non-being,”—the connexion of the former with whatsoever is good and true, with the eternal ideas, and the archetypal world: of the latter with evil, witherror, with the perishable phenomena of the present scene. The two forms of specu- lation which we have considered were here blended together ; nor was it during the youth and maturity of Greek philo- sophy alone that the tendencies of thought above described were manifested. Ages of imitation caught up and adopted as their own the same spirit. Especially wherever the genius of Plato exercised sway was this influence felt. The unity of all real being, its identity with truth and goodness considered as to their essence ; the illusion, the profound unreality, of all merely phanomenal existence ; such were the views,—such the dispositions of thought, which it chiefly tended to foster. Hence that strong tendency to mysticism which, when the days of renown, whether on the field of intellectual or on that of social enterprise, had ended in Greece, became prevalent in her schools of philosophy, and reached their culminating point among the Alexandrian Platonists. The supposititious treatises of Dionysius the Areopagite served to convey the same influence, much modified by its contact with Aristotelian doctrines, to the scholastic disputants of the middle ages. It can furnish no just ground of controversy to say, that the tone of thought _ thus encouraged was as little consistent with genuine de- votion as with a sober philosophy. That kindly influence of human affections, that homely intercourse with the common things of life, which form so large a part of the true, because intended, discipline of our nature, would be ill replaced by * Witness Aristotle’s well-known derivation of the elements from the qualities warm,” and ‘‘ dry,” and their contraries. It is characteristic that Plato connects their generation with mathematical principles. — 77maeus, cap. xi. [1 SS a pe δὰ λυ eee Oe υνὰ —" ———— poi ale CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 435 the contemplation even of the highest object of thought, viewed by an excessive abstraction as something concerning which not a single intelligible proposition could either be affirmed or denied.* I would but slightly allude to those connected speculations on the Divine Nature which ascribed [415] to it the perfect union of opposite qualities, + or to the remarkable treatises of Anselm, designed to establish a theory of the universe upon the analogies of thought and being.{ The primal unity is there represented as having its abode in the one eternal Truth. The conformity of Nature to her laws, the obedience of moral agents to the dictates of rectitude, are the same Truth seen in action ; the world itself being but an expression of the self-reflecting thought of its Author.§ Still more marked was the revival of the older forms of speculation during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The friends and associates of Lorenzo the Magnificent, the recluses known in England as the Cam- bridge Platonists, together with many meditative spirits scattered through Europe, devoted themselves anew, either to the task of solving the ancient problem, De Uno, Vero, Bono, or to that of proving that all such inquiries are futile and vain.|| The logical elements which underlie all these speculations, and from which they appear to borrow at least * Αὐτὸς καὶ ὑπὲρ θέσιν ἐστὶ καὶ dpaipeoww.—Dion. Areop. De Divinis Nomini- bus, cap. li. t+ See especially the lofty strain of Hildebert beginning ‘‘ Alpha et 2 magne Deus.” (Trench’s Sacred Latin Poetry.) The principle upon which all these speculations rest is thus stated in the treatise referred to in the last note. Οὐδὲν οὖν ἄτοπον, ἐξ ἀμυδρῶν εἰκόνων ἐπὶ τὸ πάντων αἴτιον ἀναβάντας, ὕπερ- κοσμιοῖς ὀφθαλμοῖς θεωρῆσαι πάντα ἐν τῷ παντῶν αἰτίῳ, καὶ τὰ ἀλλήλοις ἐναντία μονοειδῶς καὶ ἡνωμένως.---72ὲ Divinis Nominibus, cap. v. And the kind οἵ knowledge which it is thus sought to attain is described as a ‘‘darkness beyond light,” ὑπερφῶτος γνόφος. (De Mystica Theologia, cap. i.) Milton has a similar thought-— κε Dark with excessive bright Thy skirts appear.” Par, Lost, Book III. Contrast with these the nobler simplicity of 1 Johni. 5. 1 Monologium, Prosologium, and De Verztate. § ‘‘Idcirco cum ipse summus spiritus dicit seipsum dicit omnia quz facta sunt.” — Monolog. cap. xxiii. | See dissertations in Spinoza, Picus of Mirandula, H. More, ἄς, Modern discussions of this nature are chiefly in connexion with esthetics, the ground of the application being contained in the formula of Augustine: ‘‘ Omnis porro pulchritudinis forma, unitas est.” 436 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT their form, it would be easy to trace in the outlines of more modern systems,—more especially in that association of the doctrine of the absolute unity with the distinction of the ego and the zon-ego as the type of Nature, which forms the basis of philosophy of Hegel. The attempts of specula- tive minds to ascend to some high pinnacle of truth, from which they might survey the entire framework and con- [416]nexion of things zx the order of deductive thought, have differed less in the forms of theory which they have pro- duced, than through the nature of the interpretations which have been assigned to those forms.* And herein lies the real question as to the influence of philosophical systems upon the disposition and the life. For though it is of slight moment that men should agree in tracing back all the forms and conditions of being to a primal unity, it is otherwise as concerns their conceptions of what that unity is, and what are the kinds of relation, beside that of mere causality, which it sustains to themselves. Herein too may be felt the powerlessness of mere Logic, the insufficiency of the profoundest knowledge of the laws of the understanding, to resolve those problems which lie nearer to our hearts, as progressive years strip away from our life the illusions of its golden dawn. 8. If the extremely arbitrary character of human opinion be considered, it will not be expected, nor is it here main- tained, that the above are the only forms in which speculative men have shaped their conjectural solutions of the problem of existence. Under particular influences other forms of _ doctrine have arisen, not unfrequently, however, masking * For instance, the learned mysticism of Gioberti, widely as it differs in its spirit and its conclusions from the pantheism of Hegel (both being, perhaps, equally remote from truth), resembles it in applying both to ¢hought and to being the principles of unity and duality. It is asked :—‘‘ Or non ὃ egli chiaro che ogni discorso si riduce in fine alle idee di Dio, del mondo, e della creazione, P ultima delle quali ἃ il legame delle due prime?” And this question being affirmatively answered in the formula, ‘1’ Ente crea le esistenze,” it is said of that formula, —‘‘ Essa abbraccia la realta universale nella dualita del necessario e del contingente, esprime il vincolo di questi due ordini, e collocandolo nella creazion sostanziale, riduce la dualita reale a un principio unico, all unita primordiale dell’ Ente non astratto, complessivo, e generico,g{ma concreto, individuato, assoluto, e creatore,”—De/ Bello e del Buono, pp. 30, 31. ee ὅδε ee eee ee ΤΣ CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 437 those portrayed above. * [417] But the wide prevalence of the particular theories which we have considered, together with their manifest analogy with the expressed laws of thought, may justly be conceived to indicate a connexion between the two systems. As all other mental acts and procedures are beset by their peculiar fallacies, so the Opera- tion of that law of thought termed in this work the law of duality may have its own peculiar tendency to error, exalt- ing mere want of agreement into contrariety, and thus form a world which we necessarily view as formed of parts supple- mental to each other, framing the conception of a world fundamentally divided by opposing powers. Such, with some large but hasty inductions from phenomena, may have been the origin of dualism,—independently of the question whether dualism is in any form a true theory or not. Here, however, it is of more importance to consider in detail the bearing of these ancient forms of speculation, as revived in the present day, upon the progress of real knowledge ; and upon this point I desire, in pursuance of what has been said in the previous section, to add the follow- ing remarks : Ist. All sound philosophy gives its verdict against such speculations, if regarded as a means of determining the actual constitution of things. It may be that the progress of natural knowledge tends towards the recognition of some central Unity in Nature. Of such unity as consists in the mutual relation of the parts of a system there can be little doubt, and able men have speculated, not without grounds, on a more intimate correlation of physical forces than the mere idea of a system would lead us to conjecture. Further, it may be that in the bosom of that supposed unity are * Evidence in support of this statement will be found in the remarkable treatise recently published under the title (the correctness of which seems doubt- ful) of Origents Philosophumena. The early corruptions of Christianity of which it contains the record, though many of them, as is evident from their Ophite character, derived from the very dregs of paganism, manifest certain persistent forms of philosophical speculation. For the most part they either belong to the dualistic scheme, or recognise three principles, primary or derived, between two of which the dualistic relation may be traced.—Orvzg. Phil, pp. 135, 139, 150, 235, 253, 264. 4:8. THE LAWS OF THOUGHT involved some general principles of division and re-union, the sources, under the Supreme Will, of much of the related variety of Nature. The instances of sex and polarity have been adduced in support of such a view. As a supposition, I will venture to add, that it is not very improbable that, in some such way as this, the constitution of things without may correspond to that of the mind within. But such corre- spondence, if it shall ever be proved to exist, will appear as the last induction from human knowledge, not as the first principle of scientific inquiry. The natural order of dis- covery is from the particular to the universal, and it may confidently be affirmed [418] that we have not yet advanced sufficiently far on this track to enable us to determine what are the ultimate forms into which all the special differences of Nature shall merge, and from which they shall receive their explanation. 2ndly. Were this correspondence between the forms of thought and the actual constitution of Nature proved to exist, whatsoever connexion or relation it might be supposed to establish between the two systems, it would in no degree affect the question of their mutual independence. It would in no sense lead to the consequence that the one system is the mere product of the other. A too great addiction to metaphysical speculations seems, in some instances, to have produced a tendency toward this species of illusion. Thus, among the many attempts which have been made to explain the existence of evil, it has been sought to assign to the fact a merely relatzve character,—to found it upon a species _ of logical opposition to the equally relative element of good. It suffices to say, that the assumption is purely gratuitous. What evil may be in the eyes of Infinite wisdom and purity, we can at the best but dimly conjecture ; but to us, in all its forms, whether of pain or defect, or moral transgression, or retributory woe, it can wear but one aspect,—that of a sad and stern reality, against which, upon somewhat more than the highest order of prudential considerations, the whole . preventive force of our nature may be exerted. Now what CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 439 has been said upon the particular question just considered, is equally applicable to many other of the debated points of philosophy ; such, for instance, as the external reality of space and time. We have no warrant for resolving these into mere forms of the understanding, though they un- questionably determine the present sphere of our knowledge. And, to speak more generally, there is no warrant for the extremely subjective tendency of much modern speculation. Whenever, in the view of the intellect, different hypotheses are equally consistent with an observed fact, the instinctive testimony of consciousness as to their relative value must be allowed to possess authority. 3rdly. If the study of the laws of thought avails us neither to determine the actual constitution of things, nor to explain the facts involved in that constitution which have perplexed the wise [419] and saddened the thoughtful in all ages, — still less does it enable us to rise above the present con- ditions of our being, or lend its sanction to the doctrine which affirms the possibility of an zztuztzve knowledge of the infinite, and the unconditioned,—whether such knowledge be sought for in the realm of Nature, or above that realm. ‘We can never be said to comprehend that which is repre- sented to thought as the limit of an indefinite process of abstraction. A progression ad infinitum is impossible to finite powers. But though we cannot comprehend the in- finite, there may be even scientific grounds for believing that human nature is constituted in some relation to the in- finite. We cannot perfectly express the laws of thought, or establish in the most general sense the methods of which they form the basis, without at least the implication of ele- ments which ordinary language expresses by the terms “Universe” and ‘‘Eternity.” As in the pure abstractions of Geometry, so in the domain of Logic it is seen, that the empire of Truth is, in a certain sense, larger than that of Imagination. And as there are many special departments of knowledge which can only be completely surveyed from an external point, so the theory of the intellectual processes, 440 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT as applied only to finite objects, seems to involve the recog- nition of a sphere of thought from which all limits are with- drawn. If then, on the one hand, we cannot discover in the laws of thought and their analogies a sufficient basis of proof for the conclusions of a too daring mysticism ; on the other hand we should err in regarding them as wholly unsuggestive. As parts of our intellectual nature, it seems not improbable that they should manifest their presence otherwise than by merely prescribing the conditions of formal inference. What- ever grounds we have for connecting them with the peculiar tendencies of physical speculation among the Ionian and Italic philosophers, the same grounds exist for associating them with a disposition of thought at once more common and more legitimate. To no casual influences, at least, ought we to attribute that meditative spirit which then most delights to commune with the external magnificence of Nature, when most impressed with the consciousness of sempiternal verities,—which reads in the nocturnal heavens a bright manifestation of order; or feels in some wild scene among the [420] hills, the intimations of more than that abstract eternity which had rolled away ere yet their dark foundations were laid. * 9. Kefraining from the further prosecution of a train of thought which to some may appear to be of too speculative a character, let us briefly review the positive results to which we have been led. It has appeared that there exist in our nature faculties which enable us to ascend from the particular facts of experience to the general propositions which form the basis of Science ; as well as faculties whose office it is to deduce from general propositions accepted as true the particular conclusions which they involve. It has been seen, that those faculties are subject in their operations to laws capable of precise scientific expression, but invested with an authority which, as contrasted with the authority of the laws of nature, is distinct, suz generts, and underived. Further, there has appeared to be a manifest fitness between * Psalm xc. 2. CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 4a the intellectual procedure thus made known to us, and the conditions of that system of things by which we are sur- rounded,—such conditions, I mean, as the existence of species connected by general resemblances, of facts associated under general laws ; together with that union of permanency with order, which while it gives stability to acquired know- ledge, lays a foundation for the hope of indefinite progression. Human nature, quite independently of its observed or mani- fested tendencies, is seen to be constituted in a certain relation to Truth; and this relation, considered as a subject of speculative knowledge, is as capable of being studied in its details, is, moreover, as worthy of being so studied, as are the several departments of physical science, considered in the same aspect. I would especially direct attention to that view of the constitution of the intellect which represents it as subject to laws determinate in their character, but not operating by the power of necessity ; which exhibits it as redeemed from the dominion of fate, without being aban- doned to the lawlessness of chance. We cannot embrace this view without accepting at least as probable the intima- tions which, upon the principle of analogy, it seems to furnish respecting another and a higher aspect of our nature, —its subjection in the sphere of duty as well as in that of knowledge to [421] fixed laws whose authority does not consist in power,—its constitution with reference to an ideal standard and a final purpose. It has been thought, indeed, that scientific pursuits foster a disposition either to overlook the specific differences between the moral and the material world, or to regard the former as in no proper sense a subject for exact knowledge. Doubtless all exclusive pursuits tend to produce partial views, and it may be, that a mind long and deeply immersed in the contemplation of scenes over which the dominion of a physical necessity is unquestioned and supreme, may admit with difficulty the possibility of another order of things. But it is because of the exclusiveness of this devotion to a particular sphere of knowledge, that the prejudice in question takes possession, 442 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT if at all, of the mind. The application of scientific methods to the study of the intellectual phanomena, conducted in an impartial spirit of inquiry, and without overlooking those elements of error and disturbance which must be accepted as facts, though they cannot be regarded as Jaws in the constitution of our nature, seems to furnish the materials of a juster analogy. 10. If it be asked to what practzcal end such inquiries as the above point, it may be replied, that there exist various objects, in relation to which the courses of men’s actions are mainly determined by their speculative views of human nature. Education, considered in its largest sense, is one of those objects. The ultimate ground of all inquiry into its nature and its methods must be laid in some previous theory of what man is, what are the ends for which his several faculties were designed, what are the motives which have power to influence them to sustained action, and to elicit their most perfect and most stable results. It may be doubted, whether these questions have ever been considered fully, and at the same time impartially, in the relations here suggested. The highest cultivation of taste by the study of the pure models of antiquity, the largest acquaint- ance with the facts and theories of modern physical science, viewed from this larger aspect of our nature, can only appear as parts of a perfect intellectual discipline. Looking from the same point of view upon the means to _be employed, we might be led to inquire, whether that all but exclusive appeal which is made in [422] the present day to the spirit of emulation or cupidity, does not tend to weaken the influence of those more enduring motives which seem to have been implanted in our nature for the immediate end in view. Upon these, and upon many other questions, the just limits of authority, the reconciliation of freedom of thought with discipline of feelings, habits, manners, and upon the whole moral aspect of the question,—what unfixedness of opinion, what diversity of practice, do we meet with! Yet, in the sober view of reason, there is no object within the compass CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 443 of human endeavours which is of more weight and moment than this, considered, as I have said, in its largest meaning. Now, whatsoever tends to make more exact and definite our view of human nature, in any of its real aspects, tends, in the same proportion, to reduce these questions into narrower compass, and restrict the limits of their possible solution. Thus may even speculative inquiries prove fruitful of the most important principles of action. 11. Perhaps the most obviously legitimate bearing of such speculations would be upon the question of the place of Mathematics in the system of human knowledge, and the nature and office of mathematical studies, as a means of in- tellectual discipline. No one who has attended to the course of recent discussions can think this question an unimportant one. Those who have maintained that the position of Mathe- matics is in both respects a fundamental one, have drawn one of their strongest arguments frem the actual constitution of things. The material frame is subject in all its parts to the relations of number. All dynamical, chemical, electrical, thermal, actions, seem not only to be miserable in them- selves, but to be connected with each other, even to the extent of mutual convertibility, by numerical relations of a perfectly definite kind. But the opinion in question seems to me to rest upon a deeper basis than this. The laws of thought, in all its processes of conception and of reasoning, in all those operations of which language is the expression or the instument, are of the same kind as are the laws of the acknowledged processes of Mathematics. It is not con- tended that it is necessary for us to acquaint ourselves with those laws in order to think coherently, or, in the ordinary sense of [423] the terms, to reason well. Men draw in- ferences without any consciousness of those elements upon which the entire procedure depends. Still less is it desired to exalt the reasoning faculty over the faculties of observa- tion, of reflection, and of judgment. But upon the very ground that human thought, traced to its ultimate elements, reveals itself in mathematical forms, we have a presumption 444 THE LAWS OF THOUGHT that the mathematical sciences occupy, by the constitution of our nature, a fundamental place in human knowledge, and that no system of mental culture can be complete or funda- mental, which altogether neglects them. But the very same class of considerations shows with equal force the error of those who regard the study of Mathe- matics, and of their applications, as a sufficient basis either of knowledge or of discipline. If the constitution of the material frame is mathematical, it is not merely so. If the mind, in its capacity of formal reasoning, obeys, whether consciously or unconsciously, mathematical laws, it claims through its other capacities of sentiment and action, through its perceptions of beauty and of moral fitness, through its deep springs of emotion and affection, to hold relation to a different order of things. There is, moreover, a breadth of intellectual vision, a power of sympathy with truth in all its forms and manifestations, which is not measured by the force and subtlety of the dialectic faculty. Even the revelation of the material universe in its boundless magnitude, and per- vading order, and constancy of law, is not necessarily the most fully apprehended by him who has traced with minutest accuracy the steps of the great demonstration. And if we embrace in our survey the interests and duties of life, how little do any processes of mere ratiocination enable us to comprehend the weightier questions which they present ! As truly, therefore, as the cultivation of the mathematical or deductive faculty is a part of intellectual discipline, so truly is it only a part. The prejudice which would either -banish or make supreme any one department of knowledge or faculty of mind, betrays not only error of judgment, but a defect of that intellectual modesty which is inseparable from a pure devotion to truth. It assumes the office of criticising a constitution of things which no human ap- pointment has established, or can annul. It sets aside the [424] ancient and just conception of truth as one though manifold. Much of this error, as actually existent among us, seems due to the special and isolated character of scientific Sas Oe eee CONSTITUTION OF THE INTELLECT 4as teaching—which character it, in its turn, tends to foster, The study of philosophy, notwithstanding a few marked in- stances of exception, has failed to keep pace with the advance of the several departments of knowledge, whose mutual rela- tions it is its province to determine. It is impossible, how- ever, not to contemplate the particular evil in question as part of a larger system, and connect it with the too prevalent view of knowledge as a merely secular thing, and with the undue predominance, already adverted to, of those motives, legiti- mate within their proper limits, which are founded upon a regard to its secular advantages. In the extreme case it is not difficult to see that the continued operation of such motives, uncontrolled by any higher principles of action, un- corrected by the personal influence of superior minds, must tend to lower the standard of thought in reference to the objects of knowledge, and to render void and _ ineffectual whatsoever elements of a noble faith may still survive. And ever in proportion as these conditions are realized must the same effects follow. Hence, perhaps, it is that we some- times find juster conceptions of the unity, the vital con- nexion, and the subordination to a moral purpose, of the different parts of Truth, among those who acknowledge nothing higher than the changing aspect of collective humanity, than among those who profess an intellectual allegiance to the Father of Lights. But these are questions which cannot further be pursued here. To some they will appear foreign to the professed design of this work. But the consideration of them has arisen naturally, either out of the speculations which that design involved, or in the course of reading and reflection which seemed necessary to its accomplishment. INDEX Abbreviation, methods of, 139 ff. Abelard, 2. Addition, logical, 36, 60, 72. Adimantus, 193. Alcmezeon, 433. Alexandrian Platonists, 434. Anaxagoras, 431. Anaximenes, 431. Anselm, 2, 435. Aristotelian logic and its modern exten- sions, 239 ff. Aristotle, 1, 4, ΤΊ, 54, 143, 146, 147, 173, 206, 239, 254, 431, 432, 433, 434- Astronomical observations, of. 21, Augustine, 435. reduction Bacon, Francis (Lord), 2, 431. Boole, Mrs. Mary Everest, v. Butler, Joseph (Bishop), 212, 213, 229. Ceesar, 38. Calculus of logic, 6. Calculus of 0 and 1, 41. Cause and effect, relation of, 337 ff. Chrysippus, 191. Cicero, 190, 191. Clarke, Samuel, 197 ff., 232. Class term, 60. Combination, law of, 39, 54. Condorcet, Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Caritat, 397. Constituents of an expansion, 82. Contradiction, principle of, 53. Conversion, logical, 113. Copula, 38. opiate Antoine Augustine, 297, 399, 426. De Morgan, Augustus, xii, 240, 315, 380, 383, 384. Descartes, René, 2. Development, 77 ff. Dichotomy, 55. 446 Dickson, ΧΙ, Diogenes, 431. Dionysius the Areopagite, 434, 435. ‘* Divisible,” 140. Division, logical, 78, 94. Donkin, William, 266, 278. Duality, law of (see Law of duality), George Stephens (Rev.), Effect, relation of cause and, 337 ff. Elimination, problem of, 9, 107 ff. Empedocles, 432. : Expansion, 77 ff. Fabius, 190, 101} 192. Faugere, Prosper, 257. Fermat, Pierre de, 257. Forbes, James David, 385. Fractions, logical, 81, 94. | Free-agency, human, 22. Function, logical, 78, 87, 90, 109. General method in logic, 7. General truths, 5. Gioberti, Vincenzo, 436. Graves, Charles (Rev.), 259. - Hamilton, Sir William, 240. _ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 436. Heraclitus, 431. Hermotimus, 431. Hildebert, 435. Hincks, Edward, 259. Hippasus, 431. Identity, sign of, 29. Indefinite class, 96. Independent events, 270. Independent system of propositions, 163. Intellect, constitution of the, 418 ff. Interpretability, 73. Interpretability, condition of, ror. Interpretation of logical equations, 87 ff. INDEX John (Evangelist), 435. Judgments, probability of, 393. Kant, Immanuel, 253. Kepler, Johann, 5, 422. Language, 26 ff., 46. Laplace, Pierre Simon, 2, 22, 263, 380, 383, 392, 397, 410. Latham, 420. ae commutative, of logical addition, 36. Law, commutative, of logical multipli- cation, 31. Law, distributive, 36. Law of duality, 34, 50, 56, 62, 71, 85, 108, 132, 139, 160, 162, 164, 176, 195, 196, 373. Laws of Nature, 4. Laws of the mind, 4. Layard, Austen Henry (Sir), 259. Leibnitz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 254. Leucippus, 433. Locke, John, 2, 196. Logic, Aristotelian, and its modern extensions, 2309 ff. Logic, definition of, 5. Logic, general method in, 7. Lorenzo the Magnificent, 435. Lubbock, Sir John, xii. Manichzean doctrine, 433. Melissus, 431. Méré, Chevalier de, 257. Method, conditions of a perfect, 159 ff. Method of reduction, 232 ff. Methods of abbreviation, 130 ff. Mill, John Stuart, 253, 385. Milton, John, 33, 435 Mind, derivation of logical laws from laws of, 43. Mind, nature and constitution of, 24. Mitchell, J. (Rev.), 380, 381. More, Henry, 435. Multiplication, logical, 31. Multipliers, arbitrary constant, 124. Newton, Isaac (Sir), 208, 431. Nineveh, 259. Nothing, 52, 96. Ogham inscriptions, 259. Operation, signs of, 29. Origen, 437. Pallas, 253. Parmenides, 431. Particular affirmative propositions, 66. 447 Particular negative propositions, 69. Pascal, Blaise, 2, 257. Picus of Mirandula, 435. Plato, 173, 192, 424, 434. Platonists, Alexandrian, 434. Platonists, Cambridge, 435. Plutarch, 433. Poisson, Siméon Dénis, 22, 258, 397, 398, 399, 410. Porphyry, 2. asia! propositions, 57 ff. Probabilities, theory of, 14, 155, 257 fh, ees y OF, 14, 155, 257 Probability of Judgments, 393 ff. Proclus, 2. Propositions, primary, 57. Propositions, secondary, 57, 168. Propositions, universal negative, 68 Quality, 246. Quantitative symbols, 282, 287. (Quantity, 246. Quetelet, Lambert Adolphe Jacques, X11, Ramus, Petrus, 2. Reduction, method of, 232 ff. Reduction of systems of propositions, 123 ff. Relations among things and relations among facts, 8. Ritter, Heinrich, 432. Ryall, John, ix. Sainte Beuve, Charles Augustine de, 257. Science, nature of, 418 ff, Secondary propositions, 57, 168 ff. Senior, Nassau William, 65, 114. Sextus Empiricus, 432. Sign for copula, 38. Signs, 26 ff. ὯΝ Signs, appellative or descriptive, 30. | Social system, movements of the 22. ‘Sones 64,07 ΤΙ Ὶ τῆ. 102. Space, notion of, in theory of secondary propositions, 185. Spinoza, Benedict de, 197 ff., 435. Statistical conditions, 311 ff. Stoddart, John (Sir), 420. Subtraction, logical, 37, 53, 60. Syllogism, 107, 244 ff. Symbolical reasoning, 72 ff. Symbols, literal, 29. Taylor, Brook, 79. Terrot (Bishop), 386. 448 THE LAWS OF THOGGAT Thales, 431. Thomson, William (Archbishop) xi, 240, Time, secondary propositions and idea of, 171 ff. Timon the Sillograph, 432. Transposition, law of, 39, 54. Trench, Richard Chenevix (Arch- bishop), 435. Truths, general, 5. Universal affirmative proposition, 64. Universal negative propositions, 68. Universe of discourse, 46, 52, 176. Whately, Richard (Archbishop), xi, 11. 7252: Whewell, William (Rev. ), 426. Xenophanes, 433. PRINTED IN GREAT BRITAIN BY NEILL AND CO., LTD., EDINBURGH. = = Ἴ τ sae BINDING SECT. OCT 4 (979 a PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY Philos. Boole, George Logie Collected logical works. as oS a ΒΔ Vol.2 if att ian i | ἣ Ae Hap riba hi rn aie PA ea δὴν ἮΝ Ἀ ay) τᾷ Lt oP μὴν ih urd Path se ἕξ pe Sem ae ἘΣ ᾿ x 73 eee yy eae Myre